Skip to main content

Abduction, Clinical Reasoning, and Therapeutic Strategies

  • Living reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbook of Abductive Cognition

Abstract

The debate on the role and possible uses of abduction in the health sciences has mainly concerned diagnosis. Indeed, whereas a range of works have addressed abductive reasoning in the elaboration of diagnoses, very limited attention has been devoted to whether and how abduction plays a relevant role also in the adoption and implementation of therapeutic strategies. This chapter provides an attempt to start filling such a gap, considering, in particular, two aspects, that is, the selection and evaluation of evidence when addressing clinical decisions on single cases and the choice of some therapeutic strategy rather than others. Some reflections will be put forward which try to set a dialogue between philosophical discourse on abductive reasoning and actual therapeutic situations in clinical practice where clinicians’ expertise is particularly relevant in conceiving hypotheses about which treatment should be adopted. A couple of actual cases will be presented to exemplify conditions in which abductive reasoning actually plays an important part in clinical contexts.

Raffaella Campaner and Fabio Sterpetti contributed equally to the chapter. More specifically, the first two sections are due to Fabio Sterpetti, while the last two sections are due to Raffaella Campaner.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ai, J., et al. (2020). COVID-19: Treating and managing severe cases. Cell Research, 30, 370–371. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41422-020-0329-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ali, M. J., et al. (2020). Treatment options for Covid-19: A review. Frontiers in Medicine, 7, 480. https://doi.org/10.3389/fmed.2020.00480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aliseda, A. (2006). Abductive reasoning: Logical investigations into discovery and explanations. Dordrecht, Springer.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. (1995). Inference to the loveliest explanation. Synthese, 103(2), 251–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartha, P. (2019). Analogy and analogical reasoning. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/reasoning-analogy/

  • Beghi, E. (2010). Treating epilepsy across its different stages. Therapeutic Advances in Neurological Disorders, 3(2), 85–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boniolo, G., & Campaner, R. (2019). Causal reasoning and clinical practice: Challenges from molecular biology. Topoi, 38(2), 423–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campaner, R. (2019). Varieties of causal explanation in medical contexts. Milan, Mimesis International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campaner, R., & Galavotti, M. C. (2012). Evidence and the assessment of causal relations in the health sciences. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26(1), 27–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campos, D. G. (2009). On the distinction between Peirce’s abduction and Lipton’s inference to the best explanation. Synthese, 180(3), 419–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrara, M., Chiffi, D., De Florio, C., & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2021). We don’t know we don’t know: Asserting ignorance. Synthese, 198(4), 3565–3580.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2006). The architecture of the mind: Massive modularity and the flexibility of thought. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cellucci, C. (2013). Rethinking logic: Logic in relation to mathematics, evolution, and method. Dordrecht, Springer.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Chiffi, D., & Zanotti, R. (2015). Medical and nursing diagnosis: A critical comparison. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 21(1), 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiffi, D., & Zanotti, R. (2017). Fear of knowledge: Clinical hypotheses in diagnostic and prognostic reasoning. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 23(5), 928–934.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dammann, O. (2020). Etiological explanations: Illness causation theory. Abingdon, CRC Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Sarro, G. (2016). Managing epilepsy in the third millenium: Recent achievements and future perspectives. Pharmacological Research, 113, 332–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2011). Abduction. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/abduction/

  • Epi25 Collaborative. (2019). Ultra-rare genetic variation in the epilepsies: A whole-exome sequencing study of 17,606 individuals. The American Journal of Human Genetics, 105, 267–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Firestein, S. (2012). Ignorance: How it drives science. Oxford, Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2000). The mind doesn’t work that way: The scope and limits of computational psychology. Cambridge (MA), MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Franco, V., French, J. A., & Perucca, E. (2016). Challenges in the clinical development of new antiepileptic drugs. Pharmacological Research, 103, 95–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gambardella, A., Labate, A., & Aronica, E. (2016). Pharmacological modulation in mesial temporal lobe epilepsy: Current status and future perspectives. Pharmacological Research, 113, 421–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2014). Risk. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/risk/

  • Harman, G. H. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. The Philosophical Review, 74(1), 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1998). What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 34(3), 503–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jin, W., et al. (2021). Deep learning identifies synergistic drug combinations for treating COVID-19. PNAS, 118(39), e2105070118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J. R., & Josephson, S. G. (Eds.). (2003). Abductive inference: Computation, philosophy, technology. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). London, Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luoni, C., et al. (2011). Determinants of health-related quality of life in pharmacoresistant epilepsy: Results from a large multicenter study of consecutively enrolled patients using validated quantitative assessments. Epilepsia, 52(12), 2181–2191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackonis, A. (2013). Inference to the best explanation, coherence and other explanatory virtues. Synthese, 190(6), 975–995.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Magiorkinis, E., Sidiropoulou, K., & Diamantis, A. (2010). Hallmarks in the history of epilepsy: Epilepsy in antiquity. Epilepsy & Behavior, 17(1), 103–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2001). Abduction, reason and science: Processes of discovery and explanation. Dordrecht, Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mameniškienė, R., Rimšienė, J., & Puronaitė, R. (2016). Cognitive changes in people with temporal lobe epilepsy over a 13-year period. Epilepsy & Behavior, 63, 89–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKaughan, D. J. (2008). From ugly duckling to swan: C.S. Peirce, abduction, and the pursuit of scientific theories. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 44(3), 446–468.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minnameier, G. (2004). Peirce-suit of truth: Why inference to the best explanation and abduction ought not to be confused. Erkenntnis, 60(1), 75–105.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Mula, M. (2016). The pharmacological management of psychiatric comorbidities inpatients with epilepsy. Pharmacological Research, 107, 147–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Naik, R. R., & Shakya, A. K. (2021). Therapeutic strategies in the management of COVID-19. Frontiers in Molecular Biosciences, 7, 636738. https://doi.org/10.3389/fmolb.2020.636738

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1999). Defending abduction. Philosophy of Science, 66(Suppl), S436–S451.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2018). Truth-seeking by abduction. Cham, Springer.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (CP). (1931–1958). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vols. 1–6, Hartshorne, C., & Weiss P. (eds.); Vols. 7–8, Burks, A. W. (ed.). Cambridge (MA), Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen, A.-V., & Bellucci, F. (2014). New light on Peirce’s conceptions of retroduction, deduction, and scientific reasoning. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 28(4), 353–373.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2002). Simply the best: A case for abduction. In A. C. Kakas & F. Sadri (Eds.), Computational logic: Logic programming and beyond (pp. 605–625). Berlin, Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Santulli, L., et al. (2016). The challenges of treating epilepsy with 25 antiepileptic drugs. Pharmacological Research, 107, 211–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2008). Patterns of abduction. Synthese, 164(2), 201–234.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Shio-Shin, J., Lee, P.-I., & Hsueh, P.-R. (2020). Treatment options for COVID-19: The reality and challenges. Journal of Microbiology, Immunology and Infection, 53, 436e443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. P. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. New York, Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, D. E., & Campos, D. G. (2013). The logic of medical diagnosis. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 56(2), 300–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, D. E., & Campos, D. G. (2016). Selecting clinical diagnoses: Logical strategies informed by experience. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 22(4), 588–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, D. E., & Nyrup, R. (2020). Strategies in abduction: Generating and selecting diagnostic hypotheses. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 45(2), 159–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterpetti, F. (2020). Mathematical proofs and scientific discovery. In M. Bertolaso & F. Sterpetti (Eds.), A critical reflection on automated science (pp. 101–136). Cham, Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2011). Patterns of medical discovery. In F. Gifford (Ed.), Handbook of philosophy of medicine (pp. 187–202). Amsterdam, Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, B. (2012). Abductive reasoning and case formulation in complex cases. In L. Robertson (Ed.), Clinical reasoning in occupational therapy: Controversies in practice (pp. 15–30). Chicester (UK), Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuzet, G. (2006). Projectual abduction. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 14(2), 151–160.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Ullah, M., et al. (2020). Therapeutic options for treating COVID-19. Engineered Science, 10, 8–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Upshur, R. (1997). Certainty, probability and abduction: Why we should look to C.S. Peirce rather than Gödel for a theory of clinical reasoning. Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 3(3), 201–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vertue, F. M., & Haig, B. D. (2008). An abductive perspective on clinical reasoning and case formulation. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 64(9), 1046–1068.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, R. (2020). An update on current therapeutic drugs treating COVID-19. Current Pharmacology Reports, 6, 56–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J., Xieb, B., & Hashimoto, K. (2020). Current status of potential therapeutic candidates for the COVID-19 crisis. Brain, Behaviour, and Immunity, 87, 59–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Raffaella Campaner .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

Campaner, R., Sterpetti, F. (2022). Abduction, Clinical Reasoning, and Therapeutic Strategies. In: Magnani, L. (eds) Handbook of Abductive Cognition. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-68436-5_12-1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-68436-5_12-1

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-68436-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-68436-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Reference Intelligent Technologies and RoboticsReference Module Computer Science and Engineering

Publish with us

Policies and ethics