1 Introduction

Throughout this paper, all groups are finite and G always denotes a finite group. The notation and terminology used in this paper are standard as in [8, 12].

Baer in [1] considered the intersection of normalizers of all subgroups of G, which is called the norm of G, and denoted by \(\mathcal {N}(G)\). Much investigation has focused on using the concepts of the norm to determine the structure of groups (see, for example, [1,2,3,4, 22]).

Recall that a class of groups \(\mathfrak {F}\) is called a formation if \(\mathfrak {F}\) is closed under taking homomorphic images and subdirect products. A formation \(\mathfrak {F}\) is said to be saturated if \(G \in \mathfrak {F}\) whenever \(G/\Phi (G) \in \mathfrak {F}\). If \(\mathfrak {F}\) is a non-empty formation, then the \(\mathfrak {F}\)-residual of G, denoted by \(G^{\mathfrak {F}}\), is the smallest normal subgroup N of G with \(G/N \in \mathfrak {F}\). Li and Shen in [21] considered D(G), where D(G) is the intersection of the normalizers of derived subgroups of all subgroups of G. Shen et al. in [24] introduced S(G), which is the intersection of the normalizers of nilpotent residuals of all subgroups of G. Recall that a group G is called p-decomposable if there exists a subgroup H of G such that \(G = P \times H\) for the Sylow p-subgroup P of G. In 2020, Fu, Shen and Yan [9] introduced \(\mathcal {N}^{\mathcal {D}_p}(G)\), which is the intersection of the normalizers of p-decomposable residuals of all subgroups of G.

In recent years, a new theory of \(\sigma \)-groups has been established by Skiba and Guo (See [13, 14, 25,26,27]).

In fact, following Shemetkov [23], \(\sigma =\{\sigma _i |i\in I\}\) is some partition of all primes \(\mathbb {P}\), that is, \(\mathbb {P}=\bigcup _{i\in I}\sigma _i\) and \(\sigma _i\cap \sigma _j=\emptyset \) for all \(i\ne j\). We write \(\sigma (G)=\{\sigma _i|\sigma _i\cap \pi (G)\ne \emptyset \}\).

Following [25, 26], G is said to be: \(\sigma \)-primary if \(|\sigma (G)|\le 1\); \(\sigma \)-soluble if every chief factor of G is \(\sigma \)-primary; \(\sigma \)-nilpotent if \(G = G_1 \times \cdots \times G_n\) for some \(\sigma \)-primary groups \(G_1, \cdots , G_n\). Clearly, a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group is \(\sigma \)-soluble. We use \(\mathfrak {S}_{\sigma }\) and \(\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }\) to denote the class of all \(\sigma \)-soluble groups and the class of all \(\sigma \)-nilpotent groups, respectively. If \(G \not \in {\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\) but every proper subgroup of G belongs to \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\), then G is called an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical or a minimal non-\(\sigma \)-nilpotent group.

Remark 1.1

When \(\sigma ={\sigma }^1=\{\{2\},\{3\},\cdots \}\) (we use here the notation in [26]), then \(\sigma \)-soluble groups and \(\sigma \)-nilpotent groups are just soluble groups and nilpotent groups respectively, and an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{{\sigma }^{1}}\)-critical group G (that is, G is not nilpotent but every proper subgroup of G is nilpotent) is a

Schmidt group. Let \(\sigma =\{\{p\},p'\}\), then \(\sigma \)-soluble groups and \(\sigma \)-nilpotent groups are just p-soluble groups and p-decomposable groups, respectively. For the set \(\pi =\{p_{1}, \ldots , p_{n}\}\) of primes, we deal with the partition \(\sigma =\sigma ^{1\pi }=\{\{p_{1}\}, \ldots , \{p_{n}\}, \pi ' \}\) of \(\mathbb {P}\) [26]. Then G is: \(\sigma ^{1\pi }\)-soluble if and only if G is \(\pi \)-soluble; \(\sigma ^{1\pi }\)-nilpotent if and only if G is \(\pi \)-special [7], that is, \(G=O_{p_{1}}(G)\times \cdots \times O_{p_{n}}(G)\times O_{\pi '}(G)\).

This new theory of \(\sigma \)-groups is actually the development and popularization of the famous Sylow theorem, the Hall theorem of the soluble groups and the Chunihin theorem of \(\pi \)-soluble groups. A series of studies have been caused (See, for example, [13, 15, 18, 25, 26, 30,31,32]).

In 2021, Hu et al. [18] introduced the notion of \(\sigma \)-nilpotent norm as follows:

Definition 1.2

([18, Definition 1.2]) A subgroup \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) of G is called the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent norm of G if \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) is the intersection of the normalizers of the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent residuals of all subgroups of G, that is,

$$\begin{aligned} \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) = \bigcap _{H \le G} N_G(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}). \end{aligned}$$

Now let \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{0}(G) = 1\) and define \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i+1}(G)/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i}(G) = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i}(G))\) for \(i= 0, 1, 2, \ldots \). Then, there exists a series of normal subgroups of G:

$$\begin{aligned} 1 = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{0}(G) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{1}(G) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{2}(G) \le \cdots \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{n}(G) = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{n+1}(G) = \cdots . \end{aligned}$$

Denote by \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)\) the terminal term of this ascending series and say that \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)\) is the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent hypernorm of G.

Remark 1.3

The \(\sigma \)-nilpotent norm \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) of G covers many possible definitions. For example, in one case when \(\sigma = {\sigma }^1 =\{\{2\},\{3\},\ldots \}\), the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent norm \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) is S(G), that is, the intersection of the normalizers of nilpotent residuals of all subgroups in G.

In the case when \(\sigma =\{\{p\},p'\}\), the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent norm \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) is \(\mathcal {N}^{\mathcal {D}_p}(G)\), that is, the intersection of the normalizers of p-decomposable residuals of all subgroups of G.

In the other case when \(\sigma =\sigma ^{1\pi }=\{\{p_{1}\}, \ldots , \{p_{n}\}, \pi ' \}\), the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent norm is the \(\pi \)-special norm, that is, the intersection of the normalizers of \(\pi \)-special residuals of all subgroups of G.

In [18], the authors studied the relationship of the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent length with the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent norm of G, and get some important results. In this paper, we continue to study the influence of the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent norm and \(\sigma \)-nilpotent hypernorm of G on the structure of G.

For any \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group G, it is easy to see that \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) = G.\) If \(\sigma = \{ \{2\}, \{2\}'\}\) and \(G = S_4\), the symmetry group of degree four. Then \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) = 1.\)

Motivated by the above observations, the following question naturally arise:

Question 1.4

What is the structure of G under the condition that \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) = G?\)

We use \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) to denote the class of all finite group G with \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) nilpotent.

In this paper, we give the affirmative answer to this above problem and get the following theorem:

Theorem 1.5

Let G be a finite group. Then, the following statements are equivalent:

  1. (i)

    \(G \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }};\)

  2. (ii)

    \(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }};\)

  3. (iii)

    \(G = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G);\)

  4. (iv)

    \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G/N) > 1\) for any proper normal subgroup N of G.

For a formation \(\mathfrak {X}\), G is called an \(\mathfrak {X}\)-group if \(G \in \mathfrak {X}\).

Remark 1.6

It follows from the Theorem 1.5 that G is an \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\)-group if and only if \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) = G.\)

In [24], Shen, Shi and Qian introduced the definition of S-groups:

Definition 1.7

A group G is called an S-group if \(G = S(G)\), that is, the nilpotent residuals of all subgroups of G are normal.

The authors in [24] discussed some characters and the structure of S-groups. Recently, the S-groups are also studied by Guo and Gong, see [10, 16].

Here, we generalize the definition of S-groups and give the following definition:

Definition 1.8

A group G is called an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group if \(G = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\), that is, the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent residuals of all subgroups of G are normal.

In this paper, we would also study the properties and structure of \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups.

The paper is organized as follows. In Sect. 2, we prove some basic properties of the subgroups \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) and \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G).\) In Sect.. 3, we give the structure of G under the condition that \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) = G\) and prove Theorem 1.5. In Sect. 4, we study the properties and structure of \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups.

2 Preliminaries

In this section, we give some basic properties of the subgroups \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) and \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G).\)

Lemma 2.1

(See [18, Proposition 2.5] and [6, Lemma 2.4])

  1. (1)

    If \(M \le G\), then \(M \cap \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(M)\) and so \(M \cap \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(M).\)

  2. (2)

    If \(N \unlhd G\), then \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)N/N \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G/N)\) and so \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)N/N \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G/N)\).

  3. (3)

    If \(N \unlhd G\) and \(N \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)\), then \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G/N) = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)/N.\)

Lemma 2.2

  1. (1)

    The class \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\) of all \(\sigma \)-nilpotent groups is closed under taking direct products, homomorphic images and subgroups. Moreover, if H is a normal subgroup of G and \(H/H\cap \Phi (G)\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent, then H is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent. [25, Lemma 2.5]

  2. (2)

    The class \(\mathfrak {S}_\sigma \) of all \(\sigma \)-soluble groups is closed under taking direct products, homomorphic images and subgroups. Moreover, any extension of the \(\sigma \)-soluble group by a \(\sigma \)-soluble group is a \(\sigma \)-soluble group as well. [28, Lemma 2.1]

Remark 2.3

From the above Lemma 2.2(1), we know that \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\) is a subgroup closed saturated formation.

Recall that \(\Phi (G)\) is the intersection of all maximal subgroups of G and F(G) is the Fitting subgroup of G, that is the maximal normal nilpotent subgroup of G.

Lemma 2.4

(See [23, Ch. V, Theorem 26.1]) If G is a Schmidt group, then \(G=P\rtimes Q\), where \(P=G^{\mathfrak {N}}=G'\) is a Sylow p-subgroup of G and \(Q=\langle x \rangle \) is a cyclic Sylow q-subgroup of G with \(\langle x^{q} \rangle \le Z(G)\cap \Phi (G)\). Hence \(Q^{G}=G\).

Lemma 2.5

(See [5, Theorem 1.2]) If G is an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group, then G is a Schmidt group.

Proposition 2.6

If \(G = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\), then \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent.

Proof

Suppose it is false and let G be a counterexample of minimal order. Then:

  1. (1)

    For every proper subgroup H of G, \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent and so \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le F(G)\). For every proper subgroup H of G, \(H = H \cap \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(H)\) by the hypothesis and Lemma 2.1(1) and so \(H = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(H)\). Hence, H satisfies the hypothesis of the proposition. The choice of G implies that \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. From the definition of \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\), \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is normal in \(G = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\). Hence \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le F(G)\). Therefore Claim (1) holds.

  2. (2)

    \(\Phi (G) = 1\) If \(\Phi (G) \ne 1\), then \(G/\Phi (G) = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\Phi (G)/\Phi (G) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G/\Phi (G))\) by Lemma 2.1(2). So \(G/\Phi (G)\) satisfies the hypothesis of the proposition. The choice of G implies that \((G/\Phi (G))^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\Phi (G)/\Phi (G) \cong G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}/G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \cap \Phi (G)\) is nilpotent. Then \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent, a contradiction. Therefore Claim (2) holds.

  3. (3)

    \(F(G) > 1\). Assume that \(F(G) = 1\). Then \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1\) for every proper subgroup H of G by Claim (1). This shows that every proper subgroup of G is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent. Therefore G is either a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group or an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group. If G is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group, then \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1\), a contradiction. Assume that G is an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group. Then by Lemma 2.5, G is a Schmidt group. It follows from Lemma 2.4 that \(G^{\mathfrak {N}} = G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le G' < G\). Hence \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. This contradiction shows that Claim (3) holds.

  4. (4)

    The finial contradiction.

By Claim (3), there exists a minimal normal subgroup N of G such that \(N \le F(G)\). Then N is an elementary abelian group. By Claim (2), there exists a maximal subgroup M of G such that \(G = NM\) and \(N \cap M =1\). Since \(G/NM^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = MNM^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}/NM^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \simeq M/M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \in \mathfrak {N}_{\sigma },\) \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le NM^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). By Claim (1), \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\le F(G)\). Hence \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\le F(G)\). The final contradiction completes the proof. \(\square \)

Proposition 2.7

For any group G, the subgroup \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)\) of G is \(\sigma \)-soluble.

Proof

In view of Lemma 2.2(2), we only need to show that \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) is \(\sigma \)-soluble. Write \(X = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\). Let M be a maximal subgroup of X. If \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} > 1\), then \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is normal in X. By Lemmas 2.1(1) and 2.1(2) and induction, \(X/M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) and \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) are \(\sigma \)-soluble. Therefore X is \(\sigma \)-soluble by Lemma 2.2(2). If \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1\) for all maximal subgroups of X, then X is either a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group or an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group. Therefore by Lemmas 2.4 and 2.5, X is \(\sigma \)-soluble. The proof is completed. \(\square \)

Theorem 2.8

Suppose that G has no \(\sigma \)-primary Schmit subgroups. Then \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \cap \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) = 1\) if and only if \(Z(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) = 1\).

Proof

Assume that \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \cap \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) = 1\). By [9, Lemma 2.1] and Lemma 2.2, we have \(C_G(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\). It follows that \(Z(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) = C_G(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) \cap G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \cap G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1.\) Hence, the necessity holds.

Next we prove the sufficiency, that is, if \(Z(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) = 1\), then \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \cap \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) = 1\).

Suppose that \(Z(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) = 1\) and \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \cap \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) > 1\). Hence there exists a minimal normal subgroup N of G such that \(N \le G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \cap \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\). Since \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) is \(\sigma \)-soluble by Proposition 2.7, N is a \(\sigma _i\)-group for some i. Set \(C = C_G(N)\).

We show that the factor G/C is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group. Suppose it is false. Then, there exists a minimal non-\(\sigma \)-nilpotent subgroup K/C of G/C, that is, K/C is not \(\sigma \)-nilpotent but all of whose proper subgroups are \(\sigma \)-nilpotent. Choose a subgroup L of K such that \(K = CL\) and \(C \cap L \le \Phi (L)\). Then by Remark 2.3, \(L/\Phi (L)\) is a minimal non-\(\sigma \)-nilpotent subgroup. By Lemmas 2.4 and 2.5, \(L/\Phi (L) = (Q/\Phi (L))(P/\Phi (L))\), where \(Q/\Phi (L)\) is a normal Sylow q-subgroup of \(L/\Phi (L)\) and \(P/\Phi (L)\) is a cyclic Sylow p-subgroup of \(L/\Phi (L)\). Since \(L/\Phi (L)\) is not \(\sigma \)-nilpotent, clearly p and q belong to different partitions, that is, \(p \in \sigma _{i}\) and \(q \in \sigma _{j}\), where \(\sigma _{i} \cap \sigma _{j} = \emptyset \). By Lemma 2.4, we also know that \((L/\Phi (L))^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = L^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\Phi (L)/\Phi (L)\) is a q-subgroup, so \(L^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. Take the Sylow q-subgroup \(Q_0\) of \(L^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). Then \(Q_0\) is characterize in \(L^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). By definition of \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\), \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) normalizers \(L^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). Hence \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) normalizers \(Q_0\). If \(N \cap Q_0 =1\), then \(Q_0 \le C \cap L \le \Phi (L)\). It follows that \((L/\Phi (L))^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1\). Hence \(L/\Phi (L)\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent, a contradiction. Assume \(N \cap Q_0 \ne 1\). It follows from N is a minimal normal subgroup of G and \(N \cap Q_0\) is a normal q-subgroup of N that N is an elementary abelian q-subgroup of G. Now we show that G/C is p-nilpotent for every prime \(p \ne q\). Assume that it is false, then there exists a minimal non-p-nilpotent subgroup H/C of G/C. Choose a subgroup M of H such that \(H = CM\) and \(C \cap M \le \Phi (M)\). Then \(M/\Phi (M)\) is a minimal-non-p-nilpotent subgroup. In the light of a theorem of Ito [19, Chapert IV, Theorem 5.4], \(M/\Phi (M) = (P^{*}/\Phi (M))(R/\Phi (M))\) is a Schmit group of order \(p^{m}r^{n}\), where \(P^{*}/\Phi (M)\) is a normal Sylow p-subgroup of \(M/\Phi (M)\) and \(R/\Phi (M)\) is a cyclic Sylow r-subgroup of \(M/\Phi (M)\), \(r \ne p\) is a prime, \(m, n \ge 1\). It is clear that p and r belong to different partitions. In fact, if \(p, r \in \sigma _{j}\) for some j. Then \(M/\Phi (M)\) is a \(\sigma \)-primary Schmit group. Since \(M/\Phi (M)\) is a \(\sigma _{j}\)-group, M is a \(\sigma _{j}\)-group. Clearly M is not nilpotent, so there exists a Schmit subgroup S of M. Hence, S is a \(\sigma \)-primary Schmit group of G, which contradicts the hypothesis. Therefore, p and r belong to different partitions. Then \((M/\Phi (M))^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = (M/\Phi (M))^{\mathfrak {N}} = P^{*}/\Phi (M)\). Now as \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\Phi (M)/\Phi (M) = (M/\Phi (M))^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma } }= (M/\Phi (M))^{\mathfrak {N}} = M^{\mathfrak {N}}\Phi (M)/\Phi (M)\) is a p-subgroup, \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. Take the Sylow p-subgroup \(P_0\) of \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). Then \(P_0\) is characterize in \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). By definition of \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\), N normalizes \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), and so N normalizes \(P_0\). Since \(N \cap P_0 =1\), we have that \(P_0 \le C \cap M \le \Phi (M)\). It follows that \((M/\Phi (M))^{\mathfrak {N}} = 1\). Hence \(M/\Phi (M)\) is nilpotent, a contradiction. Therefore G/C is p-nilpotent for every prime \(p \ne q\). We now show that G/C is q-closed. Let H(p)/C be the normal Hall \(p'\)-subgroup of G/C for every prime p with \(p \ne q\). Write \(T/C = \bigcap _{p \ne q}H(p)/C\). It is clear that T/C is a normal Sylow q-subgroup of G/C. Therefore G/C is q-closed. It follows that G/T is a \(q'\)-group. Then by [23, Chapter III, Lemma 11.2], there exists a \(q'\)-subgroup W of G such that \(G = TW\). Since \([N, W^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}] \subseteq N\cap W^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}= 1\), \(W^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le C\). It follows that G/T is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent. Thus \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le T\). Take \(Q_1\) is a Sylow q-subgroup of T containing N. Then \(N \cap Z(Q_1) \ne 1\). Hence, there exists an element x such that \(1 \ne x \in N \cap Z(Q_1)\). Now \(C \le C_{G}(x)\) and \(Q_1 \le C_{G}(x)\). Since \(T = CQ_1\), we have that \(T \le C_{G}(x)\). Hence \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le T \le C_{G}(x)\) and \(x \in C_{G}(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) \cap N \le C_{G}(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) \cap G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = Z(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }})\), contrary to \(Z(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) = 1\). This contradiction shows that G/C is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group.

Now G/C is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent, that is, \((G/C)^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1\). Hence, \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le C = C_{G}(N)\). Consequently \(N \le C_G(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) \cap G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = Z(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }})\), contrary to \(Z(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) = 1\). The proof is completed. \(\square \)

Remark 2.9

We do not know whether the result of Theorem 2.8 is still true if we remove the hypothesis that G has no \(\sigma \)-primary Schmit subgroups. Note also that when \(\sigma = {\sigma }^1 =\{\{2\},\{3\},\cdots \}\), then clearly G has no \(\sigma \)-primary Schmit subgroups and so the hypothesis of Theorem 2.8 natural holds. Hence our Theorem 2.8 covers the Theorem 2.5 in [24].

3 The Proof of Theorem 1.5

Let \(\mathfrak {M}\) and \(\mathfrak {H}\) be non-empty formations, then the Gaschütz product \(\mathfrak {M}\circ \mathfrak {H} \) of \(\mathfrak {M}\) and \(\mathfrak {H}\) is defined as follows: \(G\in \mathfrak {M}\circ \mathfrak {H} \) if and only if \(G^{\mathfrak {H}}\in \mathfrak {M}\). In particular, \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = \mathfrak {N}\circ \mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }\) is the class of finite groups G with \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) nilpotent.

In order to prove Theorem 1.5, we first need to prove the following two propositions.

Proposition 3.1

  1. (1)

    \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is a formation;

  2. (2)

    \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is subgroup closed, that is , if \(G \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) and \(H \le G\), then \(H \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\).

  3. (3)

    \(G \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) if and only if \(G/\Phi (G) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\).

Proof

  1. (1)

    It follows that [8, IV, Theorem 1.8(a)].

  2. (2)

    It is well known that the class \(\mathfrak {N}\) of all nilpotent groups is subgroup closed. By Lemma 2.2, we also know that \(\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }\) is subgroup closed. Now we only need to prove the more general result: If two formations \(\mathfrak {M}\) and \(\mathfrak {H}\) are subgroup closed, then \(\mathfrak {M}\circ \mathfrak {H}\) is subgroup closed. In fact, if \(G\in \mathfrak {M}\circ \mathfrak {H}\) and \(H\le G\), then \(G^{\mathfrak {H}}\in \mathfrak {M}\). Since \(\mathfrak {H}\) is subgroup closed and \(G/G^{\mathfrak {H}}\in \mathfrak {H}\), we have that \(HG^{\mathfrak {H}}/G^{\mathfrak {H}}\in \mathfrak {H}\). By the isomorphism \(HG^{\mathfrak {H}}/G^{\mathfrak {H}}\simeq H/H\cap G^{\mathfrak {H}}\), we see that \(H/H\cap G^{\mathfrak {H}}\in \mathfrak {H}\), and so \(H^{\mathfrak {H}}\le G^{\mathfrak {H}}\in \mathfrak {M}\). But as \(\mathfrak {M}\) is subgroup closed, we obtain that \(H^{\mathfrak {H}}\in \mathfrak {M}\). Hence \(H\in \mathfrak {M}\circ \mathfrak {H}\).

  3. (3)

    It follows from [11, Theorems 3.1.11 and 3.1.20].

\(\square \)

Remark 3.2

The Proposition 3.1 shows that \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is a subgroup closed saturated formation.

Proposition 3.3

The following statements are equivalent:

  1. (1)

    \(G \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\)

  2. (2)

    \(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\)

Proof

\((1) \Longrightarrow (2)\):

It follows from Proposition 3.1(1).

\((2) \Longrightarrow (1)\):

Assume that this is false and let G be a counterexample of minimal order. We proceed via the following steps.

  1. (1)

    For any proper subgroup L of G, \(L^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. Since \(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), we have that \(L\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) by Proposition 3.1(2). It follows that \(L\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \cong L/(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \cap L)\) that \(L/(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \cap L) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}.\) By Lemma 2.1(1), \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \cap L \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(L).\) So \(L/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(L) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). Hence \(L \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) by the minimal choice of G.

  2. (2)

    For any nontrivial normal subgroup K of G, \((G/K)^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. Since \(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)K \cong (G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G))/(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)K/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G))\) and \(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), we have that \(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)K \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). By Lemma 2.1(2), \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)K/K \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G/K).\) This shows that G/K satisfies the hypothesis of the proposition. Therefore \((G/K)^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent by the choice of G.

  3. (3)

    \(\Phi (G) = 1\). If \(\Phi (G) \ne 1\), then \((G/\Phi (G))^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\Phi (G)/\Phi (G)\) is nilpotent by Claim (2). So \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent, that is, \(G \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), a contradiction. Therefore \(\Phi (G) = 1\).

  4. (4)

    The minimal normal subgroup of G is unique. Assume N is a minimal normal subgroup of G. By Claim (2), \((G/N)^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}N/N\) is nilpotent. If \(N \nsubseteq G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) , then \(N \cap G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1\). From the isomorphism \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}N/N \simeq G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), we have \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent, a contradiction. Hence, any minimal normal subgroup of G is contained in \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). If there exist two different minimal normal subgroups of G, says \(N_1, N_2\). Then \(N_1 \cap N_2 = 1\) and \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}/N_1, G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}/N_2\) are both nilpotent. So we have \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent, a contradiction. Thus the minimal normal subgroup of G is unique.

  5. (5)

    The finial contradiction.

Let N be the unique minimal normal subgroup of G. Clearly, \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) > 1\). Then, \(N \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\). If N is solvable, then N is an elementary abelian group. Since \(\Phi (G) = 1\) by Claim (3), there exists a maximal subgroup M of G such that \(G = NM\) and \(N \cap M = 1\). Then \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le NM^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). By Claim (1), \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. Now as \(N \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) and \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) normalizes \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), we have that \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is normal in G. The minimality of N implies that \(N \cap M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1\) and so \(NM^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = N \times M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). Since N is an elementary abelian group and \(M^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent, we conclude that \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. The contradiction shows that N is not soluble, and so N is a direct product of copies of a nonabelian simple group. Since N is the unique minimal normal subgroup of G, we have \(C_G(N) = 1\). Let H be any proper subgroup of G. By Claim (1), \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. Therefore \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \cap N = 1\). Since \(N \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) and \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\) normalizes \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), N normalizes \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). Hence \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le C_G(N) = 1\) and so \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1\) for any proper subgroup H of G. It follows that G is either a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group or an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group. If G is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group, then \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = 1\), and so \(G \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), a contradiction. If G is an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group, then \(G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le G^{\mathfrak {N}}\) is nilpotent by Lemmas 2.5 and 2.4, a contradiction also. The proposition is proved. \(\square \)

The Proof of Theorem 1.5.

Proof

\((i) \Longrightarrow (ii)\): It follows from Proposition 3.1(1).

\((ii) \Longrightarrow (iii)\): Firstly, we prove a fact that if \(X > 1\) is an \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\)-group, then \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(X) > 1\). In fact, if \(X \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), then \(X^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent, and so \(C_X(X^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) > 1\). But \(C_X(X^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(X)\) by Remark 2.3 and [9, Lemma 2.1], so we have \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(X) > 1\). Using the fact and the noting that \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)) = 1\), we get \(G = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)\).

\((iii) \Longrightarrow (i)\): By Lemma 2.1(3), \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)) = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\). Then by induction, \(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). It follows from Proposition 3.3 that \(G \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\).

\((i) \Longrightarrow (iv)\): Using the fact which is proved in \((ii) \Longrightarrow (iii)\), it is obvious.

\((iv) \Longrightarrow (iii)\): By definition, \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i+1}(G)/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i}(G) = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i}(G))\) for \(i = 0, 1, 2, \ldots \). By the hypothesis, \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i}(G)) > 1\) if \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i}(G) < G\), so \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i+1}(G) > \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i}(G)\) for any \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{i}(G) < G\). Hence, the terminal term \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)\) of the ascending series must be G. \(\square \)

Corollary 3.4

If H is an \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\)-subgroup of G, then \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)H\) is an \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\)-group. Consequently, \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)\) is contained in every maximal \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\)-subgroup of G.

Proof

Let \(M = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)H\). By Lemma 2.1(1), we have \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(M)\). Hence \(M/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(M) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(M)H/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(M) \cong H/(H \cap \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(M))\). Since \(H \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\), \(M/\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(M) \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) by Proposition 3.1. It follows from Theorem 1.5 that \(M \in \mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). In particular, we take H is any maximal \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\)-subgroup of G. Then \(M = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)H = H\), and so \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) \le H\). Therefore \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)\) is contained in every maximal \(\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\)-subgroup of G. \(\square \)

Following [12], we use \(Int_{\mathfrak {X}}(G)\) to denotes the intersection of all \(\mathfrak {X}\)-maximal subgroups of G, where \(\mathfrak {X}\) is a class of finite groups.

Remark 3.5

The above Corollary 3.4 shows that \(\mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G) \le Int_{\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}}(G).\) But we do not know whether \(Int_{\mathcal {F}_{\mathfrak {N}\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}}(G) \le \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }^{\infty }(G)\) is true.

4 The Properties and Structures of \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups

In this section, we discuss the class of \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups.

Recall that a group G is an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group if \(G = \mathcal {N}_{\sigma }(G)\), that is, the \(\sigma \)-nilpotent residual of every subgroup of G is normal in G; a group G is an S-group if \(G = S(G)\), that is, the nilpotent residual of every subgroup of G is normal in G. Firstly we discuss the relationship between \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups and S-groups.

The following example shows that \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups and S-groups are different.

Example 4.1

Let \(G=A_5\) be the alternating group with degree 5 and \(\sigma = \{ \sigma _1, \sigma _2 \}\), where \(\sigma _1 = \{ 2, 3,5\}\) and \(\sigma _2 = \{2,3,5\}'\). Clearly, G is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent, so every subgroup of G is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent by Lemma 2.2(1). Hence G is an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group. However, G is not an S-group. In fact, \(A_4{^{\mathfrak {N}}} \ne 1\) is not normal in G.

Now we give the following proposition to show \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups and S-groups are same under certain conditions.

Recall (see [25, 26, 29]) that a set \(\mathcal {H}\) of subgroups of G is said to be a complete Hall \(\sigma \)-set of G if every non-identity member of \(\mathcal {H}\) is a Hall \(\sigma _i\)-subgroup of G for some \(\sigma _i\) and \(\mathcal {H}\) contains exactly one Hall \(\sigma _i\)-subgroup for every \(\sigma _i\in \sigma (G)\). G is said to be: \(\sigma \)-full if G possesses a complete Hall \(\sigma \)-set; a \(\sigma \)-full group of Sylow type if every subgroup of G is a \(D_{\sigma _i}\)-group for all \(\sigma _i\in \sigma (G)\).

Proposition 4.2

Let G be a \(\sigma \)-full group of Sylow type and \(\mathcal {H} = \{W_1, \ldots , W_t\}\) be a complete Hall \(\sigma \)-set of G such that \(W_i\) is a nilpotent \(\sigma _i\)-subgroup for all \(i = 1, \ldots , t\). Then G is an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group if and only if G is an S-group.

Proof

Let H be any subgroup of G. It is clear that \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \le H^{\mathfrak {N}}\). Now we show \(H^{\mathfrak {N}} \le H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). Since \(H/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \in \mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }\), we have that \(H/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = H_1/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \times H_2/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \times \ldots H_t/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }},\) where \(H_i/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is a Hall \(\sigma _i\)-subgroup of \(H/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) for all \(i = 1, 2, \ldots , t.\) By the hypothesis, we see that \(H_i/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent. Hence \(H/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent, that is, \(H/H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} \in \mathfrak {N}\). Therefore \(H^{\mathfrak {N}} \le H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). It follows that \(H^{\mathfrak {N}} = H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\). If G is an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group, then \(H^{\mathfrak {N}} = H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}\) is normal in G for every subgroup H of G. Hence G is an S-group. If G is an S-group, then \(H^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = H^{\mathfrak {N}}\) is normal in G for every subgroup H of G. It follows that G is an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group. Therefore, the proof is completed. \(\square \)

Next we give some characters of \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups and some judging theorems for a group to be an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group.

Note that for any normal subgroup N of G, \((G/N)^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }} = G^{\mathfrak {N}_{\sigma }}N/N\) (see [11, Lemma 2.1.3]). Hence the following facts are clear from Definition 1.8, Lemma 2.2(1), Lemmas 2.4 and 2.5:

Proposition 4.3

  1. (i)

    The subgroups of an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group are \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups;

  2. (ii)

    The quotient groups of an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group are \(N_{\sigma }\)-groups;

  3. (iii)

    If G is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group or a minimal non-\(\sigma \)-nilpotent group, then G is an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group.

Lemma 4.4

G is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group if and only if there is a normal nilpotent subgroup N of G such that \(G/N'\) is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group.

Proof

The necessity follows from Lemma 2.2(1). We now show the sufficiency. Since N is nilpotent, then \(N' \le \Phi (G)\). Then as \(G/N'\) is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group, we have that \(G/\Phi (G)\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent by Lemma 2.2(1). Hence G is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group by Remark 2.3. The lemma is proved. \(\square \)

Remark 4.5

Through the proof process of the above Lemma 4.4, we can see that the Lemma 4.4 is also valid when the class of \(\sigma \)-nilpotent groups is replaced by any saturated formation. Hence Lemma 4.4 covers a famous result of Hall (see [17, page 2]).

From Lemmas 4.4,  2.2 and Proposition 2.6, we directly obtain the following:

Theorem 4.6

G is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group if and only if G is an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group and \(G/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'\) is a \(\sigma \)-nilpotent group.

Following Definition 3.10 in [20], let \(G_{n+1}=[G_n,G]\), if a group G satisfies \(G_{c+1}=1\), then we say that G is nilpotent of class \(\le c\); the least such number c is called the nilpotency class of G.

Theorem 4.7

If \(G/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'\) is an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group and \(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\) is of nilpotency class 2, then G is an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group.

Proof

Assume that the theorem is false and let G be a counterexample of minimal order. Then there exists \(M < G\) such that \(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\) is not normal in G. Consider \(N_G(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})\). As \(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent of class 2, \((G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})' \le Z(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})\). Since \(M/M \cap G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \simeq MG^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}/G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \le G/G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \in {\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\) and \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\) is subgroup closed by Lemma 2.2(1), \(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \le G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\). Then \(G > N_G(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}) \ge M(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'.\) Since \(G/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'\) is an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group, \(M(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent. It follows from \(M(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})' \simeq M/M \cap (G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})' \in {\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\) that \(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \le M \cap (G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})' \le Z(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}).\) Hence \(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \le N_G(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}),\) and so \(MG^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \le N_G(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}) < G.\) Then \(MG^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent as \(G/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'\) is an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group. Hence by Lemma 4.4, \(MG^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent. It follows from Lemma 2.2(1) that M is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent and so \(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} = 1\) is normal in G. The contradiction completes the proof. \(\square \)

By using the same method of the Proof of Theorem 4.7, we can also get the following general result.

Theorem 4.8

If \(G/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n\) is an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group and \(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\) is of nilpotency class n, where n is an integer and \(n \ge 2\), then G is an \(N_{\sigma }\)-group.

Proof

Assume that the theorem is false and let G be a counterexample of minimal order. Then there is \(M < G\) such that \(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\) is not normal in G. Consider \(N_G(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})\). If \(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\) is nilpotent of class n, then \((G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n \le Z(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})\). Clearly \(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \le G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\), so \(G > N_G(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}) \ge M(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n.\) Since \(G/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n\) is an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group, \(M(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent. It follows from \(M(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n \simeq M/M \cap (G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n \in {\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\) that \(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \le M \cap (G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n \le Z(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}).\) Hence \(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \le N_G(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}),\) and so \(MG^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} \le N_G(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}) < G.\) Therefore \(MG^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent as \(G/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n\) is an \({\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }\)-critical group. Since \((G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})_n \le (G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'\), \(MG^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}/(G^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }})'\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent by Lemma2.2. Hence by Lemma 4.4, \(MG^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }}\) is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent. Consequently M is \(\sigma \)-nilpotent, and so \(M^{{\mathfrak {N}}_{\sigma }} = 1\) is normal in G. The contradiction completes the proof. \(\square \)

Remark 4.9

It is clear that Theorem 4.5 and 4.6 in [24] are corollaries of our Theorem 4.8.