Skip to main content

Theory-Generating Abduction and Its Justification

  • Living reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbook of Abductive Cognition
  • 78 Accesses

Abstract

Theory-generating abductions introduce new (theoretical) concepts into their conclusion. This form of abduction underlies all uncertain inferences from (singular or general) empirical facts to theoretical hypotheses that explain these facts by unobserved or unobservable entities and properties, expressed by theoretical concepts. Theory-generating abductions are discriminated from speculative post-facto abductions by two scientific rationality criteria: unification and independent testability. A particularly important form of theory-generating abductions in science is common cause abductions that explain correlated empirical dispositions in terms of common theoretical causes. These abductions play also an important role in the justification of metaphysical theories, such as perceptual realism. A justification of theory-generating abductions is possible based on a weak principle of causality that is in turn justified by a noncausal abduction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. (1995). Inference to the loveliest explanation. Synthese, 103, 251–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. (2018). Philosophical skepticism and the aims of philosophy. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 118(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H., Hitchcock, C., & Menzies, P. (Eds.). (2009). The Oxford handbook of causation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (2003). A version of internalist foundationalism. In L. BonJour & E. Sosa (Eds.), Epistemic justification (pp. 3–96). B. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnham, K. P., & Anderson, D. R. (2002). Model selection and multimodel inference (2nd ed.). Springer.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1956). The methodological character of theoretical concepts. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. I, pp. 38–76). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrier, M. (2003). Experimental success and the revelation of reality: The miracle argument for scientific realism. In P. Blanchard et al. (Eds.), Science, society and reality (pp. 137–161). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2007). Hunting causes and using them. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2005). The matrix as metaphysics. In C. Grau (Ed.), Philosophers explore the matrix (pp. 132–176). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Science, 36, 181–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2011). Abduction. In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (March 09, 2011) http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abduction/

  • Earman, J. (1986). A primer on determinism. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fales, E. (1990). Causation and universals. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. (1970). The orthodox view of theories: Remarks in defense as well as critique. In Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. IV). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2017). A theory of truthmaker content. Journal of Philosophical Logic, Part I, 46, 625–674, Part II: 6:675–702.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2008). The structure of theories. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of science (pp. 269–280). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D. M., & Woods, J. (2005). The reach of abduction. North Holland.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Gemes, K. (1994). A new theory of content I: Basic content. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 23, 595–620.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Gentner, D. (1983). Structure-mapping: A theoretical framework for analogy. Cognitive Science, 7, 155–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. (1981). Theory and evidence. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A. (1976). Ad hoc auxiliary hypotheses and falsificationism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 27, 329–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünwald, P. (2000). Model selection based on minimal description length. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 44, 133–152.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Haig, B. (2005). Exploratory factor analysis, theory generation, and scientific method. Multivariate Behavioral Research, 40(3), 303–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1951). The concept of cognitive significance: A reconsideration. Reprinted in Hempel (1965), ch. II.1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Reprinted in: Hempel (1965), pp. 245–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. (1976). Models and analogies in science. University of Notre Dame Press.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1998). What is abduction? The fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transactions of the Charles Sanders Peirce Society, XXXIV(3), 503–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C., & Rédei, M. (2021). Reichenbach’s common cause principle. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2021 Edition), plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/physics-Rpcc/>

  • Hitchcock, C., & Sober, E. (2004). Prediction versus accommodation and the risk of overfitting. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748). In S. Butler (Ed.), An inquiry concerning human understanding. Echo Library. 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J., & Josephson, S. (Eds.). (1994). Abductive inference. Cambridge University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Ketland, J. (2004). Empirical adequacy and ramsification. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 287–300.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2012). Science, metaphysics and method. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 31–51.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. Reprinted in Lakatos, I., Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, pp. 8–101). Cambridge University Press, 1978 (quoted therefrom).

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Reprinted in D. Papineau (1997, ed.), The philosophy of science (pp. 107–138), Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (1991). Inference to the best explanation. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mach, E. (1883). The science of mechanics. BiblioBazaar. 2009.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2001). Abduction, reason, and science. Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1865). System of logic (6th ed.). Parker, Son, and Bourn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minnameier, G. (2004). Peirce-suit of truth – Why inference to the best explanation and abduction ought not to be confused. Erkenntnis, 60, 75–105.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Minnameier, G. (2017). Forms of abduction and an inferential taxonomy. In L. Magnani & T. Bertolotti (Eds.), Springer handbook of model-based science (pp. 175–195). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mortimer, C. E. (1986). Chemistry. Wadsworth Publishing Company.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Moser, P. K. (1989). Knowledge and evidence. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (1998). Dispositions. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2018). Truth seeking by abduction. Springer.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2012). Metaphysics as modeling: The handmaiden’s tale. Philosophical Studies, 160, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (1997). Probabilistic reasoning in intelligent systems. Morgan Kaufmann.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1901). Scientific metaphysics. In C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Eds.), 1931–1955 Collected papers of Charles S. Peirce, Vol. VI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1903). Lectures on pragmatism. In C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Eds.), Collected papers of Charles S. Peirce, Vol V.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, E. W., Pargetter, R., & Jackson, F. (1982). Three theses about dispositions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 19, 251–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge University Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). What is mathematical truth? In I. H. Putnam (Ed.), Mathematics, matter and method (pp. 60–78). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.v. O. (1960). Word and object. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2016). Abduction, inference to the best explanation, and scientific practise: The case of Newton’s optics. In L. Magnani & C. Casadio (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology (pp. 259–277). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1931). The foundations of mathematics. Kegan Paul. (reprint 1978).

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2017). Explanation and explanationism in science and metaphysics. In M. Slater & Z. Yudell (Eds.), Metaphysics and the philosophy of science: New essays (pp. 162–191). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schippers, M., & Schurz, G. (2017). Genuine coherence as mutual confirmation between content elements. Studia Logica, 105(2017), 299–329.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schippers, M., & Schurz, G. (2020). Genuine confirmation and tacking by conjunction. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71(1), 321–352.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (1991). Relevant deduction. Erkenntnis, 35, 391–437.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2008). Patterns of abduction. Synthese, 164, 201–234.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2009). When empirical success implies theoretical reference: A structural correspondence theorem. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 101–133.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2014). Philosophy of science: A unified approach. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2015). Causality and unification. Theoria, 30(1), 73–95.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2016). Common cause abduction: The formation of theoretical concepts and models in science. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 24(4), 494–509.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2017). Interactive causes: Revising the Markov condition. Philosophy of Science, 84(3), 456–479.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2021). Abduction as a method of inductive metaphysics. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 98, 50–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G., & Gebharter, A. (2016). Causality as a theoretical concept: Explanatory warrant and empirical content of the theory of causal nets. Synthese, 193, 1071–1103.

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G., & Lambert, K. (1994). Outline of a theory of scientific understanding. Synthese, 101(1), 65–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G., & Weingartner, P. (2010). Zwart and Franssen’s impossibility theorem holds for possible-world-accounts but not for consequence-accounts to verisimilitude. Synthese, 172, 415–436.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Shalev-Shwartz, S., & Ben-David, S. (2014). Understanding machine learning. From theory to algorithms. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Shao, J. (1997). An asymptotic theory for linear model selection. Statistica Sinica, 7, 221–264.

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Shogenji, T. (2018). Formal epistemology and Cartesian skepticism: In defense of belief in the natural world. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., Premack, D., & Premack, A. J. (eds.) (1995). Causal cognition. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (2000). Causation, prediction, and search. MIT Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller, W. (1976). The structure and dynamics of scientific theories. Springer.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1988). Computational philosophy of science. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (1990). Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 87(11), 658–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (2001). Abductive, presumptive and plausible arguments. Informal Logic, 21, 141–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2016). Abductive philosophy. The Philosophical Forum, 47(3–4), 263–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2006). Theory-confirmation and history. In C. Cheyne & J. Worrall (Eds.), Rationality and reality (pp. 31–61). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Yu, S., & Zenker, F. (2018). Peirce knew why abduction isn’t IBE – A schema and critical questions for abductive argument. Argumentation, 32, 569–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was supported by the DFG (Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft), research unit FOR 2495.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gerhard Schurz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

Schurz, G. (2022). Theory-Generating Abduction and Its Justification. In: Magnani, L. (eds) Handbook of Abductive Cognition. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-68436-5_4-1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-68436-5_4-1

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-68436-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-68436-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Reference Intelligent Technologies and RoboticsReference Module Computer Science and Engineering

Publish with us

Policies and ethics