1 Introduction

The seminal paper of Hotelling (1929) describes a simple model of spatial competition in which two firms compete for consumers. There are many generalizations of the model that focus on different aspects of the problem, like the number of competitors, the pricing behavior of the firms, and/or the market structure. We consider a version in which firms want to maximize their market share by means of their location in the presence of negative network externalities. The externality can be interpreted as for example congestion: the larger the market share of a firm, the higher its expected waiting time, or as snobbery: the smaller the market share of a firm, the higher its prestige. This model applies particularly to products of which the price is fixed, such as newspapers or brand products, and to political competition as introduced by Downs (1957).

Hotelling’s location model considers a game between n firms on the unit interval. Consumers are assumed to be evenly distributed along the interval and want to visit exactly one firm. The play of the game is as follows. First, each firm simultaneously chooses a location, and second, each consumer visits the closest firm. Despite the simple structure of the game, the payoff function of a firm is often discontinuous. In order to circumvent this problem, Kohlberg (1983) proposed a modification in which consumers care about the travel time as well as the expected waiting time for service. The inclusion of these network effects into the model guarantees that the payoff function of each firm is continuous. Despite this desired feature, Kohlberg (1983) states that for \(n=3\) it is easy to verify that there is no equilibrium in which two firms locate in the same place, and proves that there is no equilibrium if the three firms locate at a different location. Then he concludes that the game has no equilibrium for more than two firms and refers to Kohlberg (1982) for a proof for an arbitrary number of firms. Kohlberg (1982) proves that for \(n>3\) no equilibrium exists if the locations of the firms are different. He then claims that it is easy to verify that in equilibrium all the firm locations must be different and concludes that the game has no equilibrium for more than two firms. The claim that in equilibrium no two firms locate in the same place is based on the result for \(n=3\). However, he does not provide any intuition why the claim should be correct for arbitrary n, especially because the unique equilibrium for two firms is such that both firms locate at the center of the market.

We assume that the network externality is linear in the number of consumers visiting a firm and show that the claim that all the firm locations must be different is incorrect for \(n\in \{4,6\}\). Our main results are as follows.

Results    First, we assume that the network externality is the same for all firms. Since the game played between firms and consumers involves an element of timing, we focus on subgame perfect Nash equilibria. We derive a necessary and sufficient condition under which a subgame perfect equilibrium exists for two, four and six firms. For four and six firms, we find that the network effect should be sufficiently large for a subgame perfect equilibrium to exist. We also show that the game has no subgame perfect equilibrium for three and five firms. Based on these results, we conjecture that the game has a subgame perfect equilibrium if and only if the number of firms is even and the network effects are sufficiently large.

Second, we characterize the locations of the firms in a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium. For four and six firms, we show that there are two firms that locate at the center of the market, which is in contrast to the claim of Kohlberg that no two firms locate in the same location. The equilibrium locations for four and six firms are also different from the equilibrium locations in Hotelling’s location model. It is well known that in Hotelling’s model the outside firms are always paired, whereas in the equilibria we find, this is not necessarily the case.

Third, we consider a more general setting in which the network externality can be different for different firms. We say that two firms are asymmetric if the network effect for the two firms is different. We provide a necessary and sufficient condition under which a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium exists for three firms. A subgame perfect equilibrium exists if the network effect is the same for two out of three firms, and the effect is sufficiently larger for the third firm. This explains the lack of equilibria for three symmetric firms.

Fourth, we provide an example of a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium in which, counter-intuitively, a firm with a larger network effect obtains a larger market share than a firm with a smaller network effect due to their locations.

Related literature    Hotelling’s model is primarily used to explain product differentiation or the lack thereof. The original result found by Hotelling (1929) is that in the case of a duopoly, firms want to locate in the middle of the market and minimize differentiation. Eaton and Lipsey (1975) assume that prices are fixed and extend the analysis to multiple firms and different market structures. They argue that firms have a tendency to create local clusters, and minimum differentiation is just a special case of a local cluster for two firms. The principle of minimum differentiation was criticized by d’Aspremont et al. (1979) by showing that no pure price equilibrium exists if locations are sufficiently close. They show that under quadratic transportation costs, firms want to maximize differentiation. Osborne and Pitchik (1987) characterize a mixed strategy pricing equilibrium for linear transportation costs in which firms have substantial differentiation.

Closest to ours is Kohlberg (1983) who introduces negative network externalities into Hotelling’s location model. He shows that there are no equilibria in which all firms locate at different locations. Palma and Leruth (1989) consider a model in which firms first choose a capacity, and second, set a price. Their way of modelling congestion corresponds to our way of modelling externalities. Navon et al. (1995) focus on the pricing behavior of firms for fixed locations in the presence of negative or positive network externalities. Negative network effects tend to lessen competition and increase prices, whereas positive network effects make competition fiercer and lead to lower prices. A similar analysis and conclusion is given in Grilo et al. (2001) for quadratic instead of linear transportation costs. Ahlin and Ahlin (2013) consider a duopoly with strategic pricing and negative network externalities, and show that differentiation decreases with network effects. Lambertini and Orsini (2013) show that even in the presence of network externalities, switching costs can be used to eliminate the incentive to undercut prices such that the minimum differentiation principle is restored.

There are also models that consider fixed locations on a circle, like Salop (1979), and study price competition with network externalities. Navon et al. (1995) assume that transportation costs are linear, whereas Heikkinen (2014) assumes that transportation costs are quadratic. Friedman and Grilo (2005) consider a model with externalities, where each consumer’s utility rises when similar consumers buy the same good and falls when sufficiently dissimilar consumers buy the good.

Other recent work on Hotelling’s model considers graphs, see Pálvölgyi (2011), Fournier and Scarsini (2014), Fournier (2016), finite sets of locations, see Núñez and Scarsini (2016) and Núñez and Scarsini (2017), and optimal interval division, see Tian (2015).

The organization of this paper is as follows. Section 2 explains the basic model with linear network externalities and provides some preliminary results. In Sect. 3, we consider the model with symmetric firms. Section 4 generalizes the setting and allows firms to be asymmetric. Most of the proofs are relegated to the Appendix.

2 Preliminary results

2.1 The model

Let \(N=\{1,\ldots ,n\}\), where \(n\ge 2\), be the set of firms. Each firm sells a homogeneous product for a fixed price. The goal of each firm is to maximize its market share. We assume that consumers are uniformly distributed on the interval [0, 1]. Each consumer purchases one product. In order to do so, the consumer has to visit the location of one of the firms and incurs transportation costs. We normalize the cost of travel to one per unit distance. In addition, each consumer incurs waiting costs when visiting a firm depending on the amount of consumers that visit that firm. So the total costs for a consumer \(z\in [0,1]\) of visiting firm \(i\in N\) with location \(x_i\in [0,1]\) and market share \(s_i\in [0,1]\) are

$$\begin{aligned} |x_i-z|+w_i(s_i), \end{aligned}$$

where \(w_i:[0,1]\rightarrow \mathbb {R}_+\). We assume that each consumer chooses a firm so as to minimize his total costs. Kohlberg (1983) assumes that \(w_i\) is the same strictly increasing continuous function for each firm \(i\in N\). We assume that \(w_i\) is linear. Moreover, we allow \(w_i\ne w_j\) for some \(i,j\in N\). An interpretation is that firms might have different speeds with which consumers are served.

The game proceeds in two stages. In the first stage, each firm i simultaneously selects a location \(x_i\). These simultaneous choices constitute a vector of locations \(x = (x_1,\ldots ,x_n)\) of the firms.

In the second stage, the consumers simultaneously choose a firm based on these locations. More formally, let \(X=[0,1]^n\) denote the collection of all possible vectors of firm locations. A choice function is a measurable function \(f : X \times [0,1] \rightarrow N\) that, for each consumer \(z \in [0, 1]\) and every vector \(x \in X\) of locations, assigns firm f(xz) to consumer z. In other words, given the vector x of locations of firms, consumer z will visit firm f(xz) according to choice function f.

A strategy profile (of the firms and the consumers) is a pair (xf), where x is a vector of locations and f is a choice function.

Given a strategy profile (xf), the payoffs for the firms and the consumers are defined as follows. Define \(f_i^{-1}(x) = \{ z \in [0,1] \mid f(x,z) = i \}\) for all \(i\in N\). Let \(s_i(x,f)\) for all \(i\in N\) be the Lebesgue measure of the set \(f_i^{-1}(x)\)Footnote 1 and define \(s(x,f) = (s_i(x,f))_{i\in N}\). We refer to \(s_i(x,f)\) as the market share of firm i. The total costs for a consumer at location \(z \in [0,1]\) of visiting firm \(i\in N\) are

$$\begin{aligned} C_{z,i}(x,f)=|x_i-z|+a_i\cdot s_i(x,f), \end{aligned}$$

where \(a_i\in \mathbb {R}_+\) is the latency coefficient of firm i. We say that firm \(i\in N\) is less efficient than firm \(j\in N\) if \(a_i > a_j\). Each consumer seeks to minimize his total costs, while each firm aims to maximize his market share.

2.2 Subgame perfect Nash equilibrium

Since consumers are reacting to the locations chosen by the firms, the game played between firms and consumers involves an element of timing: first firms choose their locations, and subsequently consumers make decisions based on the locations chosen by the firms. Therefore we use subgame perfect Nash equilibrium as the natural solution concept.

Definition 1

A strategy profile (xf) is a subgame perfect Nash equilibrium (SPE) if the following two conditions are satisfied:

  1. (i)

    for all \(i\in N\), \(s_i(x,f)\ge s_i\left( (x'_i,x_{-i}),f\right) \) for all \(x'_i\in [0,1]\).

  2. (ii)

    for all \(x\in X\) and all \(z\in [0,1]\), \(C_{z,f(x,z)}(x,f)\le C_{z,i}(x,f)\) for all \(i\in N\).

Kohlberg (1983) refers to the subgame perfect Nash equilibria of the game specified above as equilibria, or sometimes Cournot–Nash equilibria, because he only considers choice functions that minimize costs for each of the consumers for every possible vector of locations of the firms. Thus, in Kohlberg (1983), condition (ii) of our definition is hardwired into the model itself.

The following example motivates why we focus on subgame perfect Nash equilibrium and not merely on Nash equilibrium.

Fig. 1
figure 1

An example of a Nash equilibrium which is not subgame perfect

Example 1

Assume that \(n=2\), \(a_1=0\) and \(a_2=1\).

Consider the following choice function. For all \(x \in X\) and \(z \in [0,1]\), define

$$\begin{aligned} f(x,z)={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1 &{}\quad \text{ if } z\le \frac{5}{6},\\ 2 &{}\quad \text{ otherwise, } \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

(see Fig. 1). Then (xf) is not an SPE, since condition (ii) in Definition 1 only holds for \(x=(\frac{1}{2},\frac{2}{3})\). We will see in Lemma 3 that there is no choice function f such that (xf) is an SPE. However, notice that the strategy profile (xf) is a Nash equilibrium, neither the firms nor the consumers have an incentive to deviate unilaterally. In fact, we will see that for each \(x\in X\) there is a choice function f that minimizes costs for all users and thus, for each \(x\in X\), there is a strategy profile that is a Nash equilibrium, by defining the choice function in a similar way as above.

The following result of Kohlberg (1983) is useful for the upcoming analysis. We omit the proof.

Lemma 1

(Kohlberg 1983) Let \(a_i>0\) for all \(i\in N\). For each vector of locations x, there are unique market shares s(xf) such that \(C_{z,f(x,z)}(x,f) \le C_{z,i}(x,f)\) for all \(z \in [0,1]\) and all \(i \in N\) for some choice function f.

Lemma 1 implies that each vector of locations has unique corresponding market shares. Notice that this does not imply that the corresponding cost minimizing choice function is unique. For example, if \(n=2\), \(a_1=a_2\) and \(x_1=x_2\) then every choice function that yields a partition of [0, 1] such that both firms have a market share of 1 / 2 minimizes costs for consumers.

2.3 Properties of SPE

In this section we derive a few properties of SPE that are useful in the analysis in the remainder of this paper. The next result follows from the costs minimization of the consumers.

Lemma 2

Given \(x\in X\), let f satisfy \(C_{z,f(x,z)}(x,f) \le C_{z,i}(x,f)\) for all \(z\in [0,1]\) and all \(i\in N\).

  1. (a)

    If \(x_i=x_j\) for some \(i,j\in N\), then \(C_{z,i}(x,f)= C_{z,j}(x,f)\) for all \(z\in [0,1]\).

  2. (b)

    If \(x_i< x_j\) for some \(i,j\in N\), then one of the following three statements is true.

    1. (i)

      \(C_{z,i}(x,f)=C_{z,j}(x,f)\) for all \(z\in [0,x_i]\) and \(C_{z,i}(x,f)>C_{z,j}(x,f)\) for all \(z\in (x_i,1]\).

    2. (ii)

      \(C_{z,i}(x,f)<C_{z,j}(x,f)\) for all \(z\in [0,x_j)\) and \(C_{z,i}(x,f)=C_{z,j}(x,f)\) for all \(z\in [x_j,1]\).

    3. (iii)

      There is some \(y\in (x_i,x_j)\) such that \(C_{z,i}(x,f)<C_{z,j}(x,f)\) for all \(z\in [0,y)\), \(C_{y,i}(x,f)=C_{y,j}(x,f)\) and \(C_{z,i}(x,f)>C_{z,j}(x,f)\) for all \(z\in (y,1]\).

Proof

See Appendix.

Given \(x\in X\), the above Lemma implies, among other things, that, even though there may not be a unique choice function that minimizes costs for consumers, there is a unique cost minimizing choice function \(f_x^*\) that assigns intervals of consumers to firm locations in a monotonic way. That is, if firm i is located to the left of firm j, then the interval of consumers assigned to firm i is to the left of the interval of consumers assigned to firm j.

The choice function \(f_x^*\) is constructed as follows. Let the profile of firm locations \(x\in X\) be given. Take a permutation \(\sigma \) of the firms such that \(x_{\sigma (1)}\le \cdots \le x_{\sigma (n)}\). Define \(z_0(x)=0\) and \(z_{\sigma (i)}(x)=\sum _{j=1}^i s_{\sigma (j)}(x,f)\) for some cost minimizing choice function f and all \(i\in N\). We define choice function \(f_x^*\) by \(f_{x,\sigma (i)}^{*-1}(x)=[z_{\sigma (i-1)}(x),z_{\sigma (i)}(x))\) for all \(i\in N\) and all \(x\in X\), and \(f_x^*(x,1)=\sigma (n)\).

Next we argue that Lemma 2 implies that if (xf) is an SPE, then \((x,f_x^*)\) is also an SPE. Let (xf) be an SPE. Suppose we have a choice function f that yields a partition such that there are two subintervals of consumers \([a_1,b_1)\) and \([a_2,b_2)\) with \(b_1\le a_2\), so that the consumers in \([a_1,b_1)\) visit firm i and the consumers in \([a_2,b_2)\) visit firm j with \(i>j\). For simplicity, assume that \(b_1-a_1=b_2-a_2\). By Lemma 2, the consumers in \([a_1,b_1)\) and the consumers in \([a_2,b_2)\) are indifferent between visiting firm i or j [case (a), (b)(i), or (b)(ii) of Lemma 2 applies]. So the choice function \(f'\) that assigns consumers \([a_1,b_1)\) to firm j, consumers \([a_2,b_2)\) to firm i, and all other consumers to the same firm as in f, is also an SPE. If we continue this process we end up with \(f_x^*\).

Since we are merely interested in existence of SPE, we only consider the choice function \(f_x^*\) (essentially we are back to the setting in Kohlberg 1983). For simplification, we write x instead of \((x,f_x^*)\) in the remainder of this paper. We define s(x), z(x) and \(C_{z,i}(x)\) for all \(x\in X\), all \(z\in [0,1]\) and all \(i\in N\) as before.

Let x be an SPE. Without loss of generality assume that \(x_1\le \cdots \le x_n\). In order to find the market share \(s_i(x)\) of each firm \(i\in N\), we have to solve the following system of equations which by Lemma 1 has a unique solution. Recall that \(z_i(x)=\sum _{j=1}^i s_j(x)\). For \(i=1,\ldots ,n-1\),

$$\begin{aligned} |x_i-z_i(x)|+a_i\cdot s_i(x)=|x_{i+1}-z_i(x)|+a_{i+1}\cdot s_{i+1}(x), \end{aligned}$$
(1)

and \(\sum _{i=1}^n s_i(x)=1\). The next result states some characteristics of subgame perfect Nash equilibria.

Lemma 3

Let x be an SPE. Then:

  1. (i)

    \(s_i(x)>0\) for all \(i\in N\).

  2. (ii)

    \(x_i\in [z_{i-1}(x),z_i(x)]\).

  3. (iii)

    \(x_1=s_1(x)\) and \(x_n=1-s_{n-1}(x)\).

  4. (iv)

    \(\left| \{i\in N\mid x_i=y\}\right| \le 2\) for all \(y\in [0,1]\).

  5. (v)

    if \(x_i=x_j\) for some \(i,j\in N\), then \(a_i=a_j\).

Proof

See Appendix.

3 Symmetric firms

Assume that all firms have an equal latency coefficient, i.e. \(a_i=a\) for all \(i\in N\). If \(a=0\) this is Hotelling’s location model and if \(a>0\) this is a special case of Kohlberg’s model.

For \(a=0\), Eaton and Lipsey (1975) prove the following results. We omit the proofs.

Theorem 1

(Eaton and Lipsey 1975) Let \(a=0\).

  1. (a)

    For \(n=2,4,5\), there is a unique SPE.

  2. (b)

    For \(n=3\), there is no SPE.

  3. (c)

    For \(n\ge 6\), there is an infinite number of SPEs.

For \(a>0\), Kohlberg (1982) proves the following result.

Theorem 2

(Kohlberg 1982) Let \(a>0\) and \(n>2\). There is no SPE in which \(x_1<\ldots <x_n\), \(z_1(x)=x_1\), \(z_i(x)\in (x_i,x_{i+1})\) for all \(1<i<n-1\) and \(z_{n-1}(x)=x_n\).

Proof

See Appendix.

However, Kohlberg (1982) states that the nonexistence result is more general by claiming that in an SPE all the firm locations must be different. We provide examples with \(n\in \{4,6\}\) and a sufficiently large for which an SPE exists, and in which two firms choose the same location. For \(n\in \{3,5\}\) the claim is valid as there are no SPEs.

3.1 Even number of firms

3.1.1 Two firms

Assume that \(n=2\) and \(a>0\). The following theorem is due to Kohlberg (1983). We omit the proof.

Theorem 3

(Kohlberg 1983) An SPE exists for all \(a>0\). The SPE is given by \(x=\left( \frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2}\right) \) and \(s(x)=\left( \frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2}\right) \).

3.1.2 Four firms

Assume that \(n=4\) and \(a>0\).

Theorem 4

An SPE exists if and only if \(a\ge 2\cdot (2+\sqrt{5})\).Footnote 2 If an SPE exists, it is given by

$$\begin{aligned} x=\textstyle \left( \frac{1+a}{2+4a},\frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2},\frac{1+3a}{2+4a}\right) \;and\; s(x)=\textstyle \left( \frac{1+a}{2+4a},\frac{a}{2+4a},\frac{a}{2+4a},\frac{1+a}{2+4a}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Proof

See Appendix.

Remark 1

Even though firms are symmetric, their market shares need not be equal.

Example 2

Let x be an SPE. By Theorem 4, we have that \(x\rightarrow \left( \frac{1}{4},\frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2},\frac{3}{4}\right) \) as \(a\rightarrow \infty \) (see Fig. 2). The locations of the firms differ from the equilibrium locations for four firms found by Eaton and Lipsey (1975).

Fig. 2
figure 2

Outcome of the SPE for four symmetric firms as \(a\rightarrow \infty \)

3.1.3 Six firms

Assume that \(n=6\) and \(a>0\).

Theorem 5

An SPE exists if and only if \(a\ge 29.8873\).Footnote 3 If an SPE exists, it is given by

$$\begin{aligned} x&=\textstyle \left( \frac{1+2a+a^2}{2+6a+6a^2},\frac{1+3a+2a^2}{2+6a+6a^2}, \frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2},\frac{1+3a+4a^2}{2+6a+6a^2},\frac{1+4a+5a^2}{2+6a+6a^2} \right) \;and\\ s(x)&=\textstyle \left( \frac{1+2a+a^2}{2+6a+6a^2},\frac{a+a^2}{2+6a+6a^2}, \frac{a^2}{2+6a+6a^2},\frac{a^2}{2+6a+6a^2},\frac{a+a^2}{2+6a+6a^2},\frac{1+2a+a^2}{2+6a+6a^2}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Proof

See Appendix.

Example 3

Let x be an SPE. By Theorem 5, we have that \(x\rightarrow \left( \frac{1}{6},\frac{1}{3},\frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2},\frac{2}{3},\frac{5}{6}\right) \) as \(a\rightarrow \infty \) (see Fig. 3). The locations of the firms differ from the equilibrium locations for six firms found by Eaton and Lipsey (1975).

Fig. 3
figure 3

Outcome of the SPE for six symmetric firms as \(a\rightarrow \infty \)

3.2 Odd number of firms

3.2.1 Three firms

Assume that \(n=3\). The following result is due to Kohlberg (1983). We omit the proof.

Theorem 6

(Kohlberg 1983) For all \(a>0\), there is no SPE.

3.2.2 Five firms

Assume that \(n=5\).

Theorem 7

For all \(a>0\), there is no SPE.

Proof

See Appendix.

3.3 Discussion

We have seen that in the symmetric setting there is a unique subgame perfect equilibrium for two firms, independent of the value of a, and that there is no subgame perfect equilibrium for three firms, also independent of the value of a. These results are in line with the results of Hotelling’s location model. However, for more than three firms, we have either discovered new equilibrium locations (for four and six firms) or no equilibria at all (for five firms). Particularly, the existence of SPEs for four and six firms is surprising, showing that the claim of Kohlberg, that all the firm locations must be different, is incorrect (see Figs. 2, 3).

Our results suggest that an SPE exists if and only if the number of firms is even and the latency coefficient sufficiently large, but we have not been able to find a proof. Therefore we state the following conjecture.

Conjecture 1

Let \(a_i=a\) for all \(i\in N\). An SPE exists if and only if \(n=2k\) for some \(k\in \mathbb {N}\) and a is sufficiently high. The SPE is unique and given by \(x_i=1-x_{2k+1-i}=\frac{(1+a)^k}{2((1+a)^k-a^k)}\cdot \left( 1-\left( \frac{a}{1+a}\right) ^i\right) \) and \(s_i(x)=s_{2k+1-i}(x)=\frac{a^{i-1}\cdot (1+a)^{k-i}}{2((1+a)^k-a^k)} \text{ for } \text{ all } i\in \{1,\ldots ,k\}\).

4 Asymmetric firms

In this section, we relax the assumption that all firms have an equal latency coefficient. Recall that this setting is not considered by Kohlberg (1983), because he assumes that firms are symmetric.

4.1 Two firms

Assume that \(n=2\).

Theorem 8

An SPE exists if and only if \(a_1=a_2\).

Proof

Suppose that an SPE exists. Let x be an SPE. Then by Lemma 3 (iii), \(x_1=s_1(x)\) and \(x_2=1-s_2(x)\). Since \(s_1(x)+s_2(x)=1\), we have \(x_1=x_2\) and thus by Lemma 3 (iv), \(a_1=a_2\).

Suppose that \(a_1=a_2\). By Theorem 3, \(x=\left( \frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2}\right) \) and \(s(x)=\left( \frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2}\right) \) forms an SPE.

4.1.1 Three firms

Assume that \(n=3\). The first lemma shows that, similar to what Kohlberg (1983) proves for symmetric firms, there is no SPE where all three firms choose a different location.

Lemma 4

Let x be an SPE. Then \(x_1=x_2\) or \(x_2=x_3\).

Proof

See Appendix.

The main result for three firms is as follows.

Theorem 9

An SPE exists if and only if (a) \(a_1=a_2\) and \(a_3\ge a_2+2\), or (b) \(a_2=a_3\) and \(a_1\ge a_2+2\).

For (a), the SPE is given by

$$\begin{aligned} x=\textstyle \left( \frac{a_3}{1+a_2+2a_3},\frac{a_3}{1+a_2+2a_3},\frac{2a_3}{1+a_2+2a_3}\right) \;and\; s(x)=\textstyle \left( \frac{a_3}{1+a_2+2a_3},\frac{a_3}{1+a_2+2a_3},\frac{1+a_2}{1+a_2+2a_3}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

For (b), the SPE is given by

$$\begin{aligned} x=\textstyle \left( \frac{1+a_2}{1+2a_1+a_2},\frac{1+a_1+a_2}{1+2a_1+a_2},\frac{1+a_1+a_2}{1+2a_1+a_2}\right) \;and\; s(x)=\textstyle \left( \frac{1+a_2}{1+2a_1+a_2},\frac{a_1}{1+2a_1+a_2},\frac{a_1}{1+2a_1+a_2}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Proof

See Appendix.

Example 4

Assume that \(a_1=a_2=0\), \(a_3=2\) and let x be an SPE. By Theorem 9, we have that \(x=\left( \frac{2}{5},\frac{2}{5},\frac{4}{5}\right) \) (see Fig. 4).

Fig. 4
figure 4

Outcome of an SPE with three firms

4.2 Four firms

Assume that \(n=4\). The following example illustrates an equilibrium in which there is a less efficient firm that obtains a larger market share due to its location.

Example 5

Assume that \(a_1=a_2=0\), \(a_3=3\frac{2}{3}\), and \(a_4=4\frac{2}{5}\). We claim that \(x=(\frac{121}{310},\frac{121}{310},\frac{121}{155},\frac{55}{62})\) is an SPE (see Fig. 5). The locations of the firms are different from the locations found in Theorem 4. Also \(s_3(x)=\frac{33}{310}<\frac{7}{62}=s_4(x)\).

Fig. 5
figure 5

SPE with four asymmetric firms

In order to prove that x is an SPE, it is sufficient to show that firm 2 does not want to deviate to the right, firm 3 does not want to deviate to the left nor to the right, and firm 4 does not want to deviate to the left.

Since market shares are piecewise linear in the location of firm 2, we show that firm 2 has no incentive to locate at \(x'_2=x_3\): \(s_2(x'_2,x_{-2})=\frac{121}{310}\). Then we show that firm 2 has no incentive to locate at \(x''_2=x_4\): \(s_2(x''_2,x_{-2})=\frac{103}{310}\). Since \(1-\frac{103}{310}<\frac{55}{62}\), there is also no incentive to locate as rightmost firm.

Observe that firm 3 could only improve by being the leftmost or rightmost firm. Suppose firm 3 locates as leftmost firm at \(x'_3=s_3(x'_3,x_{-3})\). Then \(s_3(x'_3,x_{-3})=\frac{363}{4340}\). Suppose firm 3 locates as rightmost firm at \(x''_3=1-s_3(x''_3,x_{-3})\). Then \(s_3(x''_3,x_{-3})=\frac{2268}{22475}\). Since \(s_3(x'_3,x_{-3})<s_3(x)\) and \(s_3(x_{-3},x''_3)<s_3(x)\), firm 3 has no incentive to deviate.

Observe that firm 4 could only improve by being the leftmost firm. Suppose firm 4 locates as leftmost firm at \(x'_4=s_4(x'_4,x_{-4})\). Then \(s_4(x'_4,x_{-4})=\frac{121}{1674}\). Since \(s_4(x'_4,x_{-4})<s_4(x)\), firm 4 has no incentive to deviate.

4.3 Discussion

The examples for three and four firms show that the set of equilibria increases if we allow for asymmetries between the firms. Moreover, these new equilibria bear surprising features, for example, a less efficient firm might have a larger market share due to its location (see Example 5), that do not exist in the symmetric setting. However, a full characterization of these equilibria remains an open question.