Skip to main content

Analytic Philosophy of Language (Wittgenstein, Sellars, Quine, Davidson, Kuhn)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbuch Richard Rorty

Abstract

In this chapter we focus on Rorty’s core commitments with respect to language, and consider their role in Rorty’s stormy relations to mainstream analytic philosophy. Further, we bring out key features of Rorty’s position by tracing his engagement with Wittgenstein, Sellars, Quine, Davidson, and Kuhn.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 149.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    “With the examples of Aquinas and Hegel before him, any philosopher who can neither distinguish away, nor aufheben, his opponent’s heuristic terms may fairly be judged to be incompetent. The existence of such incompetence […] is the only reason for ever losing a philosophical argument” (Rorty 1961b, p. 299).

  2. 2.

    Herman Cappelen makes openly reference to Rorty: Though in Rorty’s time “conceptual engineering” was not a topic, Cappelen states that Rorty uses his points for “somewhat tangential purposes.” “Rorty is, at least on one reading, saying that old school philosophy should be replaced by conceptual engineering“ (Cappelen 2018, p. 69).

  3. 3.

    Rorty is aware to be an idiosyncratic reader. Regarding his appropriation of Davdison’s thought, he states: “I should remark that Davidson cannot be held responsible for the interpretation I am putting on his views, nor for the further views I extrapolate from his.” (Rorty 1989, p. 10 n. 3)

  4. 4.

    See on this in detail the chapter on realism, antirealism, and antirepresentationalism.

References

  • Cappelen, Herman. 2018. Fixing language. An essay on conceptual engineering. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1984a. On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. In Inquiries into truth and interpretation, 183–198. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1984b. What metaphors mean. In Inquiries into truth and interpretation, 245–264. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 2001. Three varieties of knowledge. In Subjective, intersubjective, objective, 205–220. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 2005. A nice derangement of epitaphs. In Truth, language, and history, 89–107. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, Michael. 1996. Origins of analytical philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas. 1962. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, Steven. 2019. Pragmatism, objectivity, and experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis-Kraus, Gideon. 2003. An interview with Richard Rorty. https://believermag.com/an-interview-with-richard-rorty/?fbclid=IwAR02LWwhyWLC08Ssn_tLQQs4u8V1mrB1t8b20ekNyL2A8uw1UHcimG2ZYmg. Accessed on 08.06.2020.

  • Penelas, Federico. 2010. ¿Es posible la filosofía analítica postrortiana? In Presente y futuro de la Filosofía, Eds. Alejandro Cassini und Laura Skerk, 61–79. Editorial de la Facultad de Filosofía y Letras Universidad de Buenos Aires.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1951. Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review 60:20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1960. Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1990. Pursuit of truth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1961a. Pragmatism, categories, and language. Philosophical Review 70:197–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1961b. Recent metaphilosophy. Review of Metaphysics 15(2):299–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1967. The linguistic turn. Essays in philosophical method. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1970. Wittgenstein, privileged access, and incommunicability. American Philosophical Quarterly 7:192–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1972. Indeterminacy of language and truth. Synthese 23:443–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1982. The world well lost. In Consequences of pragmatism. Essays: 1972–1980, 1–18. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1989. Contingency, Irony, and solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1991. Unfamiliar Noises. Hesse and Davidson on Metaphor. In Objectivity, relativism, and truth. Philosophical papers, Vol. I, 162–172. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1992a. Introduction: Metaphilosophical difficulties of linguistic philosophy. In The linguistic turn. Essays in philosophical method. With two retrospective essays, Eds. Richard Rorty, 1–39. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1992b. Twenty-five years after. In The linguistic turn. Essays in philosophical method. With two retrospective essays, Eds. Richard Rorty, 371–374. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1998a. Davidson between Tarski and Wittgenstein. Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 30(88): 49–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1998b. Introduction. In Truth and progress. Philosophical papers, Vol. III, 1–15. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2007a. Analytic and conversational philosophy. In Philosophy as cultural politics. Philosophical papers, Vol. IV, 120–130. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2007b. Philosophy as cultural politics. Philosophical papers, Vol. IV. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2007c. Wittgenstein and the linguistic turn. In Philosophy as cultural politics. Philosophical papers, Vol. IV, 160–175. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, Wilfrid. 1997. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staten, Henry. 1986. Rorty’s circumvention of Derrida. Critical Inquiry 12(2): 453–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Recommended Literature for Further Reading

  • Gross, Neil. 2008. Richard Rorty: The making of an American philosopher. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Gross’s official biography also gives an account of the biographical side of Rorty’s relation to analytic philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penelas, Federico. 2010. ¿Es posible la filosofía analítica postrortiana? In Presente y futuro de la Filosofía, Eds. Alejandro Cassini und Laura Skerk, 61–79 Editorial de la Facultad de Filosofía y Letras Universidad de Buenos Aires. Penelas shows that one can be an analytic philosopher and insist on argumentation as method, while still attending to Rorty’s meta-philosophical believes by interpreting Rorty’s concept of redescription as a dialectic-argumentative method.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandbothe, Mike. 2003. Davidson and Rorty on truth. In A house divided: Comparing analytic and continental philosophers, Eds. Carlos Prado, 235–258. Amherst: Humanities Press. Sandbothe provides a meticulous reconstruction of Rorty’s and Davidson’s discussions over the years regarding the concept of truth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voparil, Chris, und Richard Bernstein, Eds. 2010. The Rorty reader. Oxford: Blackwell. Especially illuminating are Chris Voparil’s introduction and Rorty’s papers in Part II “Conversations with Analytic philosophy”.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yvonne Huetter-Almerigi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden GmbH, ein Teil von Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Huetter-Almerigi, Y., Ramberg, B.T. (2023). Analytic Philosophy of Language (Wittgenstein, Sellars, Quine, Davidson, Kuhn). In: Müller, M. (eds) Handbuch Richard Rorty. Springer VS, Wiesbaden. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-16253-5_67

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-16253-5_67

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer VS, Wiesbaden

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-658-16252-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-658-16253-5

  • eBook Packages: Social Science and Law (German Language)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics