1 Introduction

Weighted quasi-arithmetic means are important concept for mathematical theory such as the mean value theorems, and it is a fundamental tool for subjective estimation regarding information in management science, artificial intelligence and so on. Weighted quasi-arithmetic means of an interval are given mathematically by aggregation operations (Kolmogorov [4], Nagumo [6] and Aczél [1]). Bustince et al. [2] discussed aggregation operations on two-dimensional OWA operators, and Labreuche and Grabisch [5] demonstrated Choquet integral for aggregation in multicriteria decision making, and Torra and Godo [7] studied continuous WOWA operators for defuzzification. In micro-economics, subjective estimations with preference relations are formulated as utility functions (Fishburn [3]). From the view point of utility functions, Yoshida [8, 9] have studied the relations between weighted quasi-arithmetic means on an interval and decision maker’s behavior regarding risks. In one-dimensional cases, for twice continuously differentiable strictly increasing functions \(\varphi , \psi : [a,b] \mapsto {\mathbb {R}}\) as decision makers’ utility functions and a continuous function \(\omega : [a,b] \mapsto (0,\infty )\) as a weighting function, weighted quasi-arithmetic means \(\mu \) and \(\nu \) on a closed interval [ab] are real numbers satisfying

$$\begin{aligned} \varphi (\mu ) \int _{a}^{b} \, \omega (x) \, dx = \int _{a}^{b} \varphi (x) \, \omega (x) \, dx, \end{aligned}$$
(1.1)
$$\begin{aligned} \psi (\nu ) \int _{a}^{b} \, \omega (x) \, dx = \int _{a}^{b} \psi (x) \, \omega (x) \, dx \end{aligned}$$
(1.2)

in the mean value theorem for integration. Then it is said that decision making with utility function \(\varphi \) is more risk averse than decision making with utility function \(\psi \) if \(\mu \le \nu \) for all closed intervals [ab]. Its equivalent condition is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\varphi ''}{\varphi '} \le \frac{\psi ''}{\psi '} \end{aligned}$$
(1.3)

on \({\mathbb {R}}\) (Yoshida [10, 11]).

Yoshida [12] introduced weighted quasi-arithmetic means on two-dimensional regions, which are related to multi-object decision making. In this paper, using decision makers’ utility functions we discuss relations between risk averse/risk neutral/risk loving conditions and the corresponding weighted quasi-arithmetic means on two-dimensional regions. In this paper we compare two decision makers’ behaviors regarding risks by the weighted quasi-arithmetic means on two-dimensional regions and we give a characterization by their utility functions.

In Sect. 2 we introduce weighted quasi-arithmetic means on two-dimensional regions and we discuss their risk averse conditions. For two utility functions f and g on two-dimensional regions, we introduce a concept that decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g. Further we derive a necessary condition where decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g on two-dimensional regions, and we investigate the condition by several examples. In Sect. 3 we give sufficient conditions for the results in Sect. 2 when utility functions are quadratic.

2 Weighted Quasi-arithmetic Means on Two-Dimensional Regions

Let \({\mathbb {R}}= (- \infty , \infty )\) and let a domain D be a non-empty open convex subset of \({\mathbb {R}}^2\), and let \(\mathcal{R}(D)\) be a family of closed convex subsets of D. Denote by \(\mathcal{L}\) a family of twice continuously differentiable functions \(f : D \mapsto {\mathbb {R}}\) which is strictly increasing, i.e. \(f_x>0\) and \(f_y>0\) on D, and denote by \(\mathcal{W}\) a family of continuous functions \(w : D \mapsto (0,\infty )\). For a closed convex set \(R \in \mathcal{R}(D)\), weighted quasi-arithmetic means on region R with utility \(f \in \mathcal{L}\) and weighting \(w \in \mathcal{W}\) are given by a subset \(M^{f}_{w}(R)\) of region R as follows.

$$\begin{aligned} M^{f}_{w}(R) = \left\{ (\tilde{x},\tilde{y}) \in R \mid f(\tilde{x},\tilde{y}) \iint _{R} w(x,y) \, dx \, dy = \iint _{R} f(x,y) w(x,y) \, dx \, dy \right\} . \end{aligned}$$
(2.1)

Then we have \(M^{f}_{w}(R) \ne \emptyset \) since f is continuous on R and

We introduce the following natural ordering on \({\mathbb {R}}^2\).

Definition 2.1

(A partial order \(\preceq \) on \({\mathbb {R}}^2\)).

  1. (i)

    For two points \((\underline{x},\underline{y}), (\overline{x},\overline{y}) (\in {\mathbb {R}}^2)\), an order \((\underline{x},\underline{y}) \preceq (\overline{x},\overline{y})\) implies \(\underline{x} \le \overline{x} \ \text{ and } \ \underline{y} \le \overline{y}\).

  2. (ii)

    For two points \((\underline{x},\underline{y}), (\overline{x},\overline{y}) (\in {\mathbb {R}}^2)\), an order \((\underline{x},\underline{y}) \prec (\overline{x},\overline{y})\) implies \((\underline{x},\underline{y}) \preceq (\overline{x},\overline{y})\) and \((\underline{x},\underline{y}) \ne (\overline{x},\overline{y})\).

  3. (iii)

    For two sets \(A,B (\subset {\mathbb {R}}^2)\), an order \(A \preceq B\) implies the following (a) and (b):

    1. (a)

      For any \((\underline{x},\underline{y}) \in A\) there exists \((\overline{x},\overline{y}) \in B\) satisfying \((\underline{x},\underline{y}) \preceq (\overline{x},\overline{y})\).

    2. (b)

      For any \((\overline{x},\overline{y}) \in B\) there exists \((\underline{x},\underline{y}) \in A\) satisfying \((\underline{x},\underline{y}) \preceq (\overline{x},\overline{y})\).

Let a closed convex region \(R \in \mathcal{R}(D)\) and let a weighting function \(w \in \mathcal{W}\). We define a point \((\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)\) on region R by the following weighted quasi-arithmetic means:

(2.2)
(2.3)

Hence, \((\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)\) is called an invariant risk neutral point on R with weighting w (Yoshida [12]). We separate the space \({\mathbb {R}}^2\) as follows. Let \(R_{w,-}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = \{ (x,y) \in {\mathbb {R}}^2 \mid (x,y) \prec (\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R) \} = \{ (x,y) \in {\mathbb {R}}^2 \mid x \le \overline{x}_R, \ y \le \overline{y}_R, (x,y) \ne (\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R) \}\) and \(R_{w,+}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = \{ (x,y) \in {\mathbb {R}}^2 \mid (\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R) \prec (x,y) \} = \{ (x,y) \in {\mathbb {R}}^2 \mid x \ge \overline{x}_R, \ y \ge \overline{y}_R, (x,y) \ne (\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R) \}\). Then \(R_{w,-}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) denotes a subregion of risk averse points and \(R_{w,+}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) denotes a subregion of risk loving points. Let \(R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = R_{w,-}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \cup R_{w,+}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \cup \{ (\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R) \}\). Now we introduce the following relations between decision maker’s behavior and his utility.

Definition 2.2

Let a utility function \(f \in \mathcal{L}\) and let a rectangle region \(R \in \mathcal{R}(D)\).

  1. (i)

    Decision making with utility f is called risk neutral on R if

    $$\begin{aligned} f(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R) \iint _{R} w(x,y) \, dx \, dy = \iint _{R} f(x,y) w(x,y) \, dx \, dy \end{aligned}$$
    (2.4)

    for all density functions w.

  2. (ii)

    Decision making with utility f is called risk averse on R if

    $$\begin{aligned} f(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R) \iint _{R} w(x,y) \, dx \, dy \ge \iint _{R} f(x,y) w(x,y) \, dx \, dy \end{aligned}$$
    (2.5)

    for all density functions w.

  3. (iii)

    Decision making with utility f is called risk loving on R if

    $$\begin{aligned} f(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R) \iint _{R} w(x,y) \, dx \, dy \le \iint _{R} f(x,y) w(x,y) \, dx \, dy \end{aligned}$$
    (2.6)

    for all density functions w.

Example 2.1

Let a domain \(D=(-0.5,1.25)^2\) and a region \(R=[0, 1]^2\), and let a weighting function \(w(x,y)=1\) for \((x,y) \in D\). Then an invariant neutral point is \((\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)=(0.5,0.5)\) and \(R_{w,-}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = [0,0.5]^2 \setminus \{ (0.5,0.5) \}\) and \(R_{w,+}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = [0.5,1]^2 \setminus \{ (0.5,0.5) \}\). Let us consider two utility functions \(f(x,y)=-x^2-y^2+3x+3y\) and \(g(x,y)=2x^2+2y^2-5x-5y\) for \((x,y) \in D\). Then by Yoshida [12, Example 3.1(i), Lemma 2.2] decision making with utility function f is called risk averse on R with weighting w, and decision making with utility function g is also called risk loving on R with weighting w. Hence the corresponding weighted quasi-arithmetic means \(M^{f}_{w}(R)\) and \(M^{g}_{w}(R)\) are ordered by the order \(\preceq \) in a restricted subregion \(R_{w}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = R_{w,-}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \cup R_{w,+}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \cup \{ (\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R) \}\). However they can not be ordered on a subregion \(R \setminus R_{w}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) (Fig. 1).

Fig. 1.
figure 1

\(M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) (\(f(x,y)=-x^2-y^2+3x+3y, g(x,y)=2x^2+2y^2-5x-5y\), \(R=[0,1]^2\))

It is natural that the order \(\preceq \) should be given between weighted quasi-arithmetic means \(M^{f}_{w}(R)\) of risk averse utility f and weighted quasi-arithmetic means \(M^{g}_{w}(R)\) of risk loving utility g in Example 3.1. Therefore when we compare weighted quasi-arithmetic means \(M^{f}_{w}(R)\) and \(M^{g}_{v}(R)\), we discuss it on the meaningful restricted subregion \(R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\). Hence we introduce the following definition regarding the comparison of utility functions.

Definition 2.3

Let \(f,g \in \mathcal{L}\) be utility functions on D. Decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g if it holds that

$$\begin{aligned} M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \end{aligned}$$
(2.7)

for all weighting functions \(w \in \mathcal{W}\) on D and all closed convex regions \(R \in \mathcal{R}(D)\).

Example 2.2

Let a domain \(D=(-0.5,1.25)^2\) and a region \(R=[0, 1]^2\), and let a weighting function \(w(x,y)=1\) for \((x,y) \in D\). Then an invariant neutral point is \((\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)=(0.5,0.5)\) and \(R_{w,-}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = [0,0.5]^2 \setminus \{ (0.5,0.5) \}\) and \(R_{w,+}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = [0.5,1]^2 \setminus \{ (0.5,0.5) \}\). Let us consider two utility functions \(f(x,y)=-x^2-y^2+3x+3y\) and \(g(x,y)=-2x^2-2y^2+5x+5y\) for \((x,y) \in D\). Then decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g as we see the relation (2.7) in Fig. 2.

Fig. 2.
figure 2

\(M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) (\(f(x,y)=-x^2-y^2+3x+3y, g(x,y)=-2x^2-2y^2+5x+5y\), \(R=[0, 1]^2\))

Now we give a necessary condition for (2.7), i.e. decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g.

Theorem 2.1

Let \(f,g \in \mathcal{L}\) be utility functions on D. If decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g, then it holds that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{ h^2 f_{xx} + 2r hk f_{xy} + k^2 f_{yy} }{ h f_x + k f_y } \le \frac{ h^2 g_{xx} + 2 rhk g_{xy} + k^2 g_{yy} }{ h g_x + k g_y } \end{aligned}$$
(2.8)

on D for all positive numbers h and k and all real numbers r satisfying \(-1 \le r \le 1\).

From Theorem 2.1 we can easily obtain the following result, which is corresponding to [12, Theorem 3.1(i)].

Corollary 2.1

Let \(f,g \in \mathcal{L}\) be utility functions on D. If decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g, then it holds that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{f_{xx}}{f_x} \le \frac{g_{xx}}{g_x} \quad {and} \quad \frac{f_{yy}}{f_y} \le \frac{g_{yy}}{g_y} \quad {on} \ D. \end{aligned}$$
(2.9)

Equation (2.8) in Theorem 2.1 gives a detailed relation between f and g rather than (2.9). A parameter r in necessary condition (2.8) depends on the shapes of closed convex regions \(R \in \mathcal{R}(D)\). Now we investigate several examples with different shapes of regions R.

Example 2.3

(Rectangle regions). Let h and k be positive numbers.Let rectangle regions

$$\begin{aligned} R^\mathrm{Rect}_{h,k}(a,b,t) = [a,a+ht] \times [b,b+kt] \end{aligned}$$
(2.10)

for \((a,b) \in D\) and \(t>0\). Denote a family of rectangle regions by \(\mathcal{R}^\mathrm{Rect}_{h,k}(D) = \{ R^\mathrm{Rect}_{h,k}(a,b,t) \mid R^\mathrm{Rect}_{h,k}(a,b,t) \subset D, \, (a,b) \in D, \ t>0 \} (\subset \mathcal{R}(D))\), (Fig. 3).

Corollary 2.2

If utility functions \(f,g \in \mathcal{L}\) satisfy \(M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) for all weighting functions \(w \in \mathcal{W}\) on D and all rectangle regions \(R \in \mathcal{R}^\mathrm{Rect}_{h,k}(D)\), then it holds that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{ h^2 f_{xx} + k^2 f_{yy} }{ h f_x + k f_y} \le \frac{ h^2 g_{xx} + k^2 g_{yy} }{ h g_x + k g_y} \end{aligned}$$
(2.11)

on D.

Example 2.4

(Oval regions). Let h and k be positive numbers. Let oval regions

$$\begin{aligned} R^\mathrm{Oval}_{h,k}(a,b,t) = \left\{ (x,y) \in {\mathbb {R}}^2 \left| \frac{(x-a)^2}{h^2} + \frac{(y-b)^2}{k^2} \le t^2 \right. \right\} \end{aligned}$$
(2.12)

for \((a,b) \in D\) and \(t>0\). Denote a family of oval regions by \(\mathcal{R}^\mathrm{Oval}_{h,k}(D) = \{ R^\mathrm{Oval}_{h,k}(a,b,t) \mid R^\mathrm{Oval}_{h,k}(a,b,t) \subset D, \, (a,b) \in D, \ t>0 \} (\subset \mathcal{R}(D))\), (Fig. 3).

Corollary 2.3

If utility functions \(f,g \in \mathcal{L}\) satisfy \(M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) for all weighting functions \(w \in \mathcal{W}\) on D and all oval regions \(R \in \mathcal{R}^\mathrm{Oval}_{h,k}(D)\), then it holds that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{ h^2 f_{xx} + k^2 f_{yy} }{ h f_x + k f_y} \le \frac{ h^2 g_{xx} + k^2 g_{yy} }{ h g_x + k g_y} \end{aligned}$$
(2.13)

on D.

Fig. 3.
figure 3

Rectangle region \(R^\mathrm{Rect}_{h,k}(a,b,t)\) and oval region \(R^\mathrm{Oval}_{h,k}(a,b,t)\)

Example 2.5

(Triangle regions). Let h and k be positive numbers. Let triangle regions

$$\begin{aligned} R^\mathrm{Tri}_{h,k}(a,b,t) = \left\{ (x,y) \in {\mathbb {R}}^2 \left| x \ge a, \, y \ge b, \, \frac{x-a}{h} + \frac{y-b}{k} \le t \right. \right\} \end{aligned}$$
(2.14)

for \((a,b) \in D\) and \(t>0\). Denote a family of triangle regions by \(\mathcal{R}^\mathrm{Tri}_{h,k}(D) = \{ R^\mathrm{Tri}_{h,k}(a,b,t) \mid R^\mathrm{Tri}_{h,k}(a,b,t) \subset D, \, (a,b) \in D, \ t>0 \} (\subset \mathcal{R}(D))\), (Fig. 4).

Corollary 2.4

If utility functions \(f,g \in \mathcal{L}\) satisfy \( M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \) for all weighting functions \(w \in \mathcal{W}\) on D and all triangle regions \(R \in \mathcal{R}^\mathrm{Tri}_{h,k}(D)\), then it holds that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{ h^2 f_{xx} - hk f_{xy} + k^2 f_{yy} }{ h f_x + k f_y} \le \frac{ h^2 g_{xx} - hk g_{xy} + k^2 g_{yy} }{ h g_x + k g_y} \end{aligned}$$
(2.15)

on D.

Example 2.6

(Parallelogram regions). Let h and k be positive numbers. Let parallelogram regions

$$\begin{aligned} R^\mathrm{Para}_{h,k}(a,b,t) = \{ (x,y) \mid |k(x-a)-3h(y-b) | \le 4hkt, \, |3k(x-a)-h(y-b) | \le 4hkt \} \end{aligned}$$
(2.16)

for \((a,b) \in D\) and \(t>0\). Denote a family of parallelogram regions by \(\mathcal{R}^\mathrm{Para}_{h,k}(D) = \{ R^\mathrm{Para}_{h,k}(a,b,t) \mid R^\mathrm{Para}_{h,k}(a,b,t) \subset D, \, (a,b) \in D, \ t>0 \} (\subset \mathcal{R}(D))\), (Fig. 4).

Corollary 2.5

If utility functions \(f,g \in \mathcal{L}\) satisfy \(M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) for all weighting functions \(w \in \mathcal{W}\) on D and all parallelogram regions \(R \in \mathcal{R}^\mathrm{Para}_{h,k}(D)\), then it holds that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{ h^2 f_{xx} + \frac{3}{5} hk f_{xy} + k^2 f_{yy} }{ h f_x + k f_y} \le \frac{ h^2 g_{xx} + \frac{3}{5} hk g_{xy} + k^2 g_{yy} }{ h g_x + k g_y} \end{aligned}$$
(2.17)

on D.

Fig. 4.
figure 4

Triangle region \(R^\mathrm{Tri}_{h,k}(a,b,t)\) and parallelogram region \(R^\mathrm{Para}_{h,k}(a,b,t)\)

Example 2.3 (Rectangle regions) and Example 2.4 (Oval regions) are cases where \(r=0\) in (2.8), and Example 2.5 (Triangle regions) and Example 2.6 (Parallelogram regions) are cases where \(r=-\frac{1}{2}\) and \(r=\frac{3}{10}\) respectively in (2.8).

3 A Sufficient Condition

Let \(f,g \in \mathcal{L}\) be utility functions on an open convex domain D. Theorem 2.1 gives a necessary condition that decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g. In this section, we discuss its sufficient condition. For a utility function \(f \in \mathcal{L}\), its Hessian matrix is written by

$$\begin{aligned} H^f(x,y) = \left( \begin{array}{cc} f_{xx}(x,y) &{} f_{xy}(x,y) \\ f_{yx}(x,y) &{} f_{yy}(x,y) \end{array} \right) \end{aligned}$$
(3.1)

for \((x,y) \in D\). The the following proposition gives a sufficient condition for (2.8) in Theorem 2.1.

Proposition 3.1

Let \(f,g \in \mathcal{L}\) be utility functions on D. Then the following (i) and (ii) hold.

  1. (i)

    Matrices

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{f_x(x,y)} H^f(x,y) {-} \frac{1}{g_x(x,y)} H^g(x,y) \ {and} \ \frac{1}{f_y(x,y)} H^f(x,y) - \frac{1}{g_y(x,y)} H^g(x,y) \end{aligned}$$
    (3.2)

    are negative semi-definite for all \((x,y) \in D\) if and only if a matrix

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{h f_x(x,y) + k f_y(x,y)} H^f(x,y) - \frac{1}{h g_x(x,y) + k g_y(x,y)} H^g(x,y) \end{aligned}$$
    (3.3)

    is negative semi-definite for all \((x,y) \in D\) and all positive numbers h and k.

  2. (ii)

    If (3.2) are negative semi-definite at all \((x,y) \in D\), then (2.8) holds on D for all positive numbers h and k and all real numbers r satisfying \(-1 \le r \le 1\).

From Proposition 3.1 implies that the condition (3.2) is stronger than the condition (2.8), however (3.2) is easier than (2.8) to check in actual cases. In this paper, utility functions \(f (\in \mathcal{L})\) are called quadratic if the second derivatives \(f_{xx}\), \(f_{xy}\) and \(f_{yy}\) are constant functions. When utility functions are quadratic, the following theorem gives a sufficient condition for what decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g.

Theorem 3.1

Let utility functions \(f, g \in \mathcal{L}\) be quadratic on D. If

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{f_x(x,y)} H^f(x,y) - \frac{1}{g_x(x,y)} H^g(x,y) \quad {and} \quad \frac{1}{f_y(x,y)} H^f(x,y) - \frac{1}{g_y(x,y)} H^g(x,y) \end{aligned}$$
(3.4)

are negative semi-definite at all \((x,y) \in D\), then decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g, i.e.

$$ M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} $$

for all weighting functions \(w \in \mathcal{W}\) and all closed convex regions \(R \in \mathcal{R}(D)\).

Now we give an example for Theorem 3.1.

Example 3.1

(Quadratic utility functions). Let a domain \(D=(-0.5,1.5)^2\) and a region \(R= [0, 1]^2\), and let a weighting function \(w(x,y)=1\) for \((x,y) \in D\). Then an invariant neutral point is \((\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)=(0.5,0.5)\) and \(R_{w,-}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = [0,0.5]^2 \setminus \{ (0.5,0.5) \}\) and \(R_{w,+}^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} = [0.5,1]^2 \setminus \{ (0.5,0.5) \}\). Let us consider two quadratic utility functions \(f(x,y)=-2x^2-2y^2+2xy+8x+8y\) and \(g(x,y)=-x^2-y^2+xy+5x+5y\) for \((x,y) \in D\). Then f and g are increasing on D, i.e. \(f_x(x,y)=-4x+2y+8>0\), \(f_y(x,y)=2x-4y+8>0\), \(g_x(x,y)=-2x+y+5>0\) and \(g_y(x,y)=x-2y+5>0\) on D. Their Hessian matrices are

$$\begin{aligned} H^f(x,y) = \left( \begin{array}{rr} -4 &{} 2 \\ 2 &{} -4 \end{array} \right) \quad \text{ and } \quad H^g(x,y) = \left( \begin{array}{rr} -2 &{} 1 \\ 1 &{} -2 \end{array} \right) . \end{aligned}$$
(3.5)

Let A(xy) and B(xy) by \(A(x,y)=\frac{1}{f_x(x,y)} H^f(x,y) - \frac{1}{g_x(x,y)} H^g(x,y)\) and \(B(x,y)=\frac{1}{f_y(x,y)} H^f(x,y) - \frac{1}{g_y(x,y)} H^g(x,y)\) for \((x,y) \in D\), and then we have

$$\begin{aligned} A(x,y) = \frac{1}{-4x+2y+8} \left( \begin{array}{rr} -4 &{} 2 \\ 2 &{} -4 \end{array} \right) - \frac{1}{-2x+y+5} \left( \begin{array}{rr} -2 &{} 1 \\ 1 &{} -2 \end{array} \right) , \end{aligned}$$
(3.6)
$$\begin{aligned} B(x,y) = \frac{1}{2x-4y+8} \left( \begin{array}{rr} -4 &{} 2 \\ 2 &{} -4 \end{array} \right) - \frac{1}{x-2y+5} \left( \begin{array}{rr} -2 &{} 1 \\ 1 &{} -2 \end{array} \right) . \end{aligned}$$
(3.7)

We can easily check A(xy) and B(xy) are negative definite for all \((x,y) \in D\). From Theorem 3.1, decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g on R and it holds that \(M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) for all weighting functions \(w \in \mathcal{W}\) (Fig. 5).

Fig. 5.
figure 5

\(M^{f}_{w}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)} \preceq M^{g}_{v}(R) \cap R_w^{(\overline{x}_R,\overline{y}_R)}\) (\(f(x,y)=-2x^2-2y^2+2xy+8x+8y, g(x,y)=-x^2-y^2+xy+5x+5y\), \(R=[0, 1]^2\))

Concluding Remark. When utility functions are quadratic, Theorem 3.1 gives a sufficient condition where decision making with utility f is more risk averse than decision making with utility g. It is an open problem whether (3.2) is a sufficient condition when utility functions are not quadratic but more general.