Skip to main content

How Do We Think about the Unknown? The Self-Awareness of Ignorance as a Tool for Managing the Anguish of Not Knowing

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Embodied, Extended, Ignorant Minds

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 463))

Abstract

This chapter offers a revision of the concept of ignorance discussed in recent models of abduction. Both ignorance preservation (GW-schema) and the tentative explanationism (AKM-schema) will be reanalyzed from an ecological and distributed perspective on cognition, instead coherent with the so-called EC-Model of abduction. We are convinced that a successful revision of the notion of ignorance in both AKM-schema and GW-schema of abduction can be exactly realized thanks to the EC-model. These theories present ignorance as an absence that occurs when the agents cannot reach useful explanations of a phenomenon in their epistemic environment. This absence surprises them, and this emotion triggers agents’ abductive reasoning, which, in turn, mitigates their ignorance. Abduction offers the agents a guessed “provisional” hypothesis capable to solve the ignorance-problem. However, both the state of being ignorant of something and the mitigation of not-knowing are complex processes. If we describe the agents as parts of cognitive systems, we can see them as engaged with the so-called affordances, which always provide qualitative and procedural information capable to help and trigger abductive inferential processes. We will argue that when a possible relation with the fact, which is investigated is unknown, and so affordances are absent – and consequently “unknown” – the lack of available knowledge is absolute. When this happens, the agent is compelled to abduce from an unknown affordance: In this case, it is the agents’ self-awareness of their ignorance that plays a role of a helpful tool. The reached full self-awareness of the complete ignorance at stake triggers unusual chances that favor exceptional abductive inferential processes capable to manage the cognitive situation. At the same time, the agent may experience these cases characterized by unknown affordances with a high degree of anguish. Indeed, the hypothesis will be more strongly supported by the motivation and will of the agent than by the cognitive role played by commonly accepted data and will be formed by unusual intuitions and data considered strange or exceptional. We will illustrate that in these cases, the management of anxiety – and control of it – is committed to general principles of research integrity related to the role of cognizant’s responsibility for his own actions.

It was a green stone head of the demon Pazuzu, personification of the southwest wind. Its dominion was sickness and disease. The head was pierced. The amulet’s owner had worn it as a shield.

W. P. Blatty, 1971

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Kierkegaard’s already stressed the role of anguish as “dizziness of freedom.” According to him, anguish opens the possibility of freedom, understood as a possibility, an expression that refers to the experience of absolute freedom of choice. Kierkegaard proposes the example of looking into an abyss: in this, a person will feel fear the possibility of falling and throwing himself off the cliff. Taking personal responsibility for our actions (to jump or not into the abyss) leads to self-consciousness (Kierkegaard, 1980: 61).

  2. 2.

    Cf. infra., Sect. 9.3.2. for the meaning of this concept. For the moment, the reader can roughly understand it as a worldview.

  3. 3.

    The classical schematic representation of abduction is expressed by what Gabbay and Woods (2005) call AKM-schema, which is contrasted to their own (GW-schema), which we are explaining in this section. For A they refer to Aliseda (1997, 2006), for K to Kowalski (1979), Kakas et al. (1993), Kuipers (1999), for M to Magnani (2001), and Meheus et al. (2002). A detailed abductive structure illustration of the AKM schema is given in an article written by Magnani (2009, Chap. 2, Sect. 2.1.3).

  4. 4.

    Woods recently acknowledged the importance of the knowledge-enhancing character of abduction in Woods (2021).

  5. 5.

    Particularization refers here to the mechanisms that govern the application in science of the meanings and values generally shared in a society (contextual meanings and values) (c.f., Longino, 1983).

  6. 6.

    We use the term “cosmovision” to refer to the unified image of the world that arises from the biological and sociocultural interpretation of the environment. While a “worldview” is based on perception, a “cosmovision” arises from living together in a society with other people, so it encompasses both its biological and sociocultural aspects (Magnani et al., 2021).

  7. 7.

    Here Feyerabend is quoting Rozental (1967: 117).

  8. 8.

    Some of these external constraints were considered by Peirce as quickly performed by “instinctive” strategies, which would occur before conceptualization, when hypotheses are instantly reached by humans.

References

  • Aliseda, A. (1997). Seeking explanations: Abduction in logic, philosophy of science and artificial intelligence. PhD dissertation (ILLC Dissertation Series 1997-4). Institute for Logic, Language and Computation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aliseda, A. (2006). Abductive reasoning: Logical investigations into discovery and explanation. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arfini, S. (2019). Ignorant cognition. A philosophical investigation of the cognitive features of non-knowing. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1964). Analytica priora et posteriora (W. D. Ross, Ed.). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balistier, T. (2000). The Phaistos Disc. An account of its unsolved mystery. Verlag Dr Thomas Balistier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blatty, W. P. (1971). The exorcist. Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cannizzaro, S., & Anderson, M. (2016). Culture as habit, habit as culture: Instinct, habituescence, addiction. In D. West & M. Anderson (Eds.), Consensus on Peirce’s concept of habit. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2003). An outline of a theory of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 15(2), 181–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colli, G. (1978). La nascita della filosofia. Adelphi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhoux, Y. (2000). How not to decipher the Phaistos Disc: A review. American Journal of Archaeology, 104, 597–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg, J. M. (2008). The Phaistos Disk: One hundred year old hoax? Minerva (July/August), 9–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1967). On the improvement of the sciences and the arts, and the possible identity of the two. In R. S. Cohen & M. W. Wartofsky (Eds.), Proceedings of the Boston colloquium for the philosophy of science 1964/1966 (Boston studies in the philosophy of science, Vol. 3) (pp. 387–415). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, M., & Wood, J. (2005). The reach of abduction. Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godart, L. (1990). The Phaistos Disc: The enigma of an Aegean script. Itanos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosser, M. (1979). The discovery of Neptune. Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann, M. H. G. (1999). Problems with Peirce’s concept of abduction. Foundations of Science, 4(3), 271–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1987). The meaning of truth. In William James. Writings 1902–1919. The varieties of religious experience; Pragmatism; A pluralistic universe; The meaning of truth; some problems of philosophy; Essays (pp. 821–978). Literary Classics of the United States, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1992). The Will to believe and other essays in popular philosophy. A psychology: Briefer course, the will to believe, talks to teachers and to students, essays (pp. 445–704). Literary Classics of the United States, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kakas, A., Kowalski, R. A., & Toni, F. (1993). Abductive logic programming. Journal of Logic and Computation, 2(6), 719–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kapitan, T. (1997). Peirce and the structure of abductive inference. In N. Houser, D. D. Roberts, & J. van Evra (Eds.), Studies in the logic of Charles Sanders Peirce (pp. 477–496). Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kierkegaard, S. (1980). The concept of anxiety. Asimple pshychologically orienting deliberation on the dogmatic issue of hereditary sin (R. Thompte & A. B. Anderson, Trans.). Princenton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kompridis, N. (2006). Critique and disclosure: Critical theory between past and future. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kowalski, R. A. (1979). Logic for problem solving. Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kowalski, R. A. (1994). Logic without model theory. In D. M. Gabbay (Ed.), What is a logical system? (pp. 35–71). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. A. F. (1999). Abduction aiming at empirical progress of even truth approximation leading to challenge for computational modelling. Foundations of Science, 4, 307–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1983). Beyond “Bad Science”. Science, Technology, and Human Values, 8(1), 7–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2001). Abduction, reason and science: Processes of discovery and explanation. Kluwer, Plenum.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2009). Abductive cognition: The epistemological and eco-cognitive dimensions of hypothetical reasoning. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2017). The abductive structure of scientific creativity. An essay on the ecology of cognition. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2021a) Abduction as “Leading Away”. In: J. R. Shook & S. Paavola (Eds,), Abduction in cognition and action (Studies in applied philosophy, epistemology and rational ethics, Vol. 59). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2021b). Discoverability. The urgent need of an ecology of human creativity. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L., Sans Pinillos, A., & Arfini, S. (2021). Language: The “ultimate artifact” to build, develop, and update worldviews. Topoi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meheus, J., Verhoeven, L., Van Dyck, M., & Provijn, D. (2002). Ampliative adaptive logics and the foundation of logic-based approaches to abduction. In L. Magnani, N. J. Nersessian, & C. Pizzi (Eds.), Logical and computational aspects of model-based reasoning (Applied Logic Series, Vol. 25) (pp. 39–71). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paavola, S. (2005). Peircean abduction: Instinct or inference? Semiotica, 153(1/4), 131–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, W. (2017). Abduction in context. The conjectural dynamics of scientific reasoning.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1958). In C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Ed.), Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Vol. 1–6). Harvard University Press, 1931–1935; (Vol. 7–8) (A. W. Burks Ed.). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1924). Meno. In Laches, Protagoras, Meno, Euthydemus (W. R. M. Lamb, Trans.). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (2002). The logic of scientific discovery. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1995). Peirce on abduction, plausibility, and efficiency of scientific inquiry. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Essays in the history of philosophy (pp. 309–326). Avebury. Rosenfeld, L. (Ed). (1967). Niels Bohr. His life and work as seen by his friends and colleagues. North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sans Pinillos, A. (2017). El lado epistemológico de las abducciones: La creatividad en las verdades-proyectadas. Revista Iberoamericana De Argumentación, 15, 77–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1966). L’existentialisme est un humanisme. Les Éditions Nagel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, C. (1996). Abductive reasoning in archaeology. Philosophy of Science, 63(2), 278–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1988). Computational philosophy of science. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Frassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thomson, E., & Rosch, E. (2017). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2011). Recent developments in abductive logic. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 240–244. Essay Review of Magnani, L. (2009). Abductive cognition. The epistemological and eco-cognitive dimensions of hypothetical reasoning. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2021). Four grades of ignorance-involvement and how they nourish the cognitive economy. Synthese, 198, 3339–3368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Younger, J. G. (2007). The Mycenaen Bard: The evidence for sound and song. In S. P. Morris & R. Laffineur (Eds.), Epos: Reconsidering Greek epic and Aegean Bronze Age Archaeology: Proceedings of the 11th International Aegean Conference/11e Rencontre égéenne internationale, Los Angeles, UCLA – The J. Paul Getty Villa, 20–23 April 2006. Université de Liège, Histoire de l’art et archéologie de la Grèce antique; University of Texas at Austin, Program in Aegean Scripts and Prehistory, pp. 71–78.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Research for this article was supported by the PRIN 2017 Research 20173YP4N3-MIUR, Ministry of University and Research, Rome, Italy.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alger Sans Pinillos .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Sans Pinillos, A., Magnani, L. (2022). How Do We Think about the Unknown? The Self-Awareness of Ignorance as a Tool for Managing the Anguish of Not Knowing. In: Arfini, S., Magnani, L. (eds) Embodied, Extended, Ignorant Minds. Synthese Library, vol 463. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-01922-7_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics