The European case law of recent years has demonstrated the key relevance of the principle of the rule of law to the ‘functioning of the EU as a whole’.Footnote 1 Challenges to the rule of law by Member States have come centre stage in political debates,Footnote 2 the press,Footnote 3 and academia.Footnote 4 Most referred to are the measures taken in Poland and Hungary connected to the national judiciaries. However, the Court of Justice (ECJ) and Treaties have long highlighted the importance of the rule of law. Already in 1986, the ECJ declared that the (then) ‘European Economic Community is a Community based on the rule of law’.Footnote 5 According to Article 2 of the Treaty on European Union (TEU), the rule of law is one of the values on which the European Union (EU) is founded. It is thus not only a criterion for accession,Footnote 6 but is also given ‘concrete expression’Footnote 7 throughout EU law. The latter has been made clear by the ECJ in its contemporary case law on judicial independence, according to which ‘compliance by a Member State with the values enshrined in Article 2 TEU is a condition for the enjoyment of all of the rights deriving from the application of the Treaties to that Member State.’Footnote 8

One trait common to the constitutional traditions of Europe is the lack of a definition of the rule of law by constitutions or by courts.Footnote 9 However, various actors have attempted to define the core tenets of the rule of law. In EU law, for instance, the definition of the rule of law for the purposes of the December 2020 Rule of Law Conditionality RegulationFootnote 10 is based on the existing case law of the Court of Justice (ECJ),Footnote 11 and.

‘refers to the Union value enshrined in Article 2 TEU. It includes the principles of legality implying a transparent, accountable, democratic and pluralistic law-making process; legal certainty; prohibition of arbitrariness of the executive powers; effective judicial protection, including access to justice, by independent and impartial courts, also as regards fundamental rights; separation of powers; and non-discrimination and equality before the law.Footnote 12


This Regulation ‘provides the first comprehensive all-encompassing definition of the rule of law adopted by the EU legislator’.Footnote 13 Thus, as demonstrated by Pech, the rule of law is a well-established principle of EU law that the ECJ case law, the Commission, and the EU legislators have defined.Footnote 14

This non-exhaustive list is united by what this principle seeks protection from – the arbitrary exercise of power. Likewise, ‘Abhorrence of arbitrariness is a major theme that runs through all the rule of law writing through the centuries’Footnote 15 and can hence be considered the core of the rule of law.

But from whom does the rule of law protect? ‘The ideal of "the rule of law, not of men"' calls upon us to strive to ensure that our law itself will rule (govern) us, not the wishes of powerful individuals’.Footnote 16 Still, in an era where private actors are increasingly powerful, we must ask: which ‘powerful individuals’? This article argues that it is not just public but also private actors that hold sufficient power over individuals to trigger rule of law-related obligations. Indeed, individuals, corporations and other non-State actors may exercise power over various aspects of society, the economy, and politics, presenting numerous risks, including political influence, corruption, and lack of accountability. If the EU is to be considered based on the rule of law, it must at a minimum require Member States to preclude private actors from arbitrarily wielding their power over weaker individuals. The idea of limiting the ability for private actors to arbitrarily exercise power they hold vis-à-vis others is already part of the underlying fabric of various areas of law: fundamental rights, consumer protection and competition law, and labour law, for instance. Thus, it appears that the rule of law is not just about the tethering of public power, despite widespread assumptions to the contrary.Footnote 17

The article is structured as follows. Section 1 elaborates on the relationship between law, power, and arbitrariness. Sections 2 and 3 highlight two different rule of law narratives. Whereas the former establishes that the traditional rule of law narrative is about protecting the interests of private actors from public actors, Sect. 3 deals with the capacity of the rule of law to provide protection from the arbitrary use of private power, particularly by business actors in the areas of fundamental rights, consumer protection and competition law, and labour law. As will be seen, however, this does not mean that the law goes far enough to provide protection in these areas. Furthermore, in Sect. 4 it will be shown that there are areas falling outside the law or in which private actors are able to influence the law in ways that can still be conceived of as exercises of arbitrary power, suggesting that rule of law protection against such power is insufficient, highlighting the example of lobbying in this respect. Section 5 concludes.

Thus, it becomes apparent that the EU rule of law principle is much broader than generally portrayed, with its substance (non-arbitrariness) already inspiring how the law readjusts the balance of power between powerful and less powerful private actors and/or controls the exercise of power by the more powerful. Still, it is time to explicitly acknowledge this private dimension of the rule of law, which arguably requires the EU and Member States to provide far greater protection against the exercise of private power than is currently available. Just as the EU has a long way to go yet towards cleaning up the rule of law backsliding in the Member States, so too must it make increased efforts to remedy rule of law deficits in relationships between private parties.

1 The Rule of Law, Power, and Arbitrariness

This enunciation of various principles stemming from the rule of law as a definition for the rule of law is typical. Perhaps it is considered so obvious that it often goes without saying, yet these principles all go back to the issues of the ability of one party to exercise power arbitrarily over another. To preclude arbitrary exercises of power is why we need legality, legal certainty, effective judicial protection, the separation of powers, and non-discrimination and equality before the law. Otherwise, we would live in a society in which power could be wielded to trample over the rights and interests of others. Non-arbitrariness prevents this. Thus, as demonstrated on multiple occasions by Krygier, the problem that the rule of law seeks to address is power, particularly arbitrary uses thereof liable to interfere with the rights and interests of others,Footnote 18 including but not limited to fundamental rights and democracy.Footnote 19

But what do we mean by ‘power’ and ‘arbitrariness’? As the rule of law is concerned with ‘citizens’ interest in non-domination’,Footnote 20 the type of power the rule of law is predominantly concerned with is power over – i.e. ‘the power of the strong over the weak’.Footnote 21 This type of power stands in opposition to the other forms of power traditionally encompassed by power analyses – i.e. power to, power with, or power within. Hence, the rule of law concerns itself with the power of particular actors over weaker actors. In terms of what the arbitrary exercise of power would look like, one can look to the two forms identified by Krygier:

It can refer to power at its source – to what extent is the power of the power-wielder subject, as Philip Pettit puts it, ‘just to the arbitrium, the decision or judgement of the [power-wielding] agent; the agent was in a position to choose it or not choose it, at their pleasure’? We also speak of power being exercised arbitrarily where it is received, if those subject to it have no way of knowing how or when or why it will hit them, or with what. It is the job of rule-of-law institutions, among others, to diminish arbitrium in the exercise of power, at both ends.Footnote 22

The arbitrary exercise of power: A case law illustration

As an illustration of both power and the arbitrary exercise thereof that has been deemed incompatible with the rule of law, one can look to the recent case law of the ECJ concerning the independence of national courts, where the Court confirmed that judicial independence ‘gives concrete expression to the value of the rule of law’.Footnote 23 In these cases, other State branches undermined the independence of national courts. A core issue was often whether judges were subject to non-circumscribed executive or legislative discretion (i.e. arbitrariness), as demonstrated in a working paper with [to be added after peer-review].

In sum, in the Polish preliminary references Independence of the Supreme Court and Judges’ Retirement Age, measures providing for executive discretion to extend judicial terms that were not circumscribed by an independent advisory body constituted a failure to fulfil the judicial independence obligation contained in Article 19(1) TEU.Footnote 24 Likewise, in the AK and Others (Poland), AB and Others (Poland), and Repubblika (Malta) preliminary rulings the lawfulness of measures pertaining to judicial appointments also turned on the issue of executive discretion.Footnote 25

It appears from this case law that measures are discretionary — thus facilitating arbitrary decision-making — where (i) the measures are not governed by objective and verifiable criteria and (ii) the decision-makers do not have to provide reasons for their decisions.Footnote 26 In Independence of the Supreme Court the judicial term extension was considered ‘discretionary inasmuch as its adoption is not, as such, governed by any objective and verifiable criterion and for which reasons need not be stated.’Footnote 27 Similarly, in Judges’ Retirement Age the Court highlighted that the term extension criteria were ‘too vague and unverifiable’ (and hence not based on objective criteria) and that ‘the minister’s decision is not required to state reasons’.Footnote 28 In Repubblika, the ECJ noted firstly, that the Prime Minister’s exercise of their power to make judicial appointments was ‘circumscribed by the requirements of professional experience which must be satisfied by candidates for judicial office, which [were] laid down in … the Constitution’Footnote 29; hence, their decisions were subject to objective criteria. Next, even though the Prime Minister could appoint candidates not forwarded by the existing independent advisory body, this seemed remedied by the executive’s ‘obligation to state reasons’.Footnote 30 From these cases, one can observe that the Court’s definition of discretion in this respect relates to the lack of objective criteria or duty to give reasons. However, an actor may save such executive discretionary measures from constituting a breach of judicial independence where the measure can ‘be challenged in court proceedings’.Footnote 31

Nevertheless, even if the executive has discretion and their decision is not subject to judicial review, the measure may still be saved from constituting a breach of judicial independence by the presence of an advisory body. This will only be the cases where (i) that body is itself independent from the external influence of the executive or legislature, (ii) the ‘opinion is delivered on the basis of criteria which are both objective and relevant’, and (iii) the opinion ‘is properly reasoned’.Footnote 32 Further, even where that advisory body is not independent, again the discretion of the executive and non-independence of the advisory body may be saved by the possibility of judicial review according to AB and Others, where the Court reasoned that if the advisory body in the appointment process was not independent, ‘the existence of a judicial remedy… would be necessary in order to help safeguard the process of appointing the judges’.Footnote 33

Based on the above, the EU rule of law principle requires that power be exercised at least according to objective and verifiable criteria and that the power-holder give reasons for their decisions. In the event that these requirements are not fulfilled, the relevant measure can only be compatible with the rule of law if certain guardrails are in place, such as an independent advisory body or the possibility of judicial review.

While this case law gives an idea of what the rule of law concretely requires in situations involving public actors, it tells us nothing of what it requires when private actors are involved. However, as we shall see in subsequent sections, the requirements laid down by the Court to protect the rule of law can inspire the creation of concrete obligations for private actors. The role of private actors under the rule of law narrative is the focus of the following two sections. Section 2 explores the ‘traditional’ rule of law narrative, which focuses on the protection of private (including business) actors from the arbitrary exercise of public power. By contrast, Sect. 3 explores the possibility of a rule of law principle that requires States to protect individuals from the arbitrary exercise of power by other private actors.

2 The Traditional Rule of Law Narrative: Protection from Public Power

Traditional rule of law narratives focus on protecting subjects of a given legal order from the arbitrary use of power by public actors.Footnote 34 When private actors are part of this narrative, the discussion often relates to how States can use the rule of law to protect business actors from the arbitrary use of public power,Footnote 35 for the benefit of the economy as a whole. Like the Magna Carta was an ‘effort of nobles to use law to restrain kings’,Footnote 36 the rule of law is said to facilitate ‘successful conduct of trade, investment and business’.Footnote 37 This conception, therefore, frames the rule of law as placing duties on the State while granting rights to business actors.

On this reading, one associates the rule of law with the protection of business interests through legal certainty,Footnote 38 systems of contract law,Footnote 39 property rights,Footnote 40 and ‘effective justice systems’,Footnote 41 thereby facilitating a stable economic environment for business dealings, such as investment and contracts.Footnote 42 The protection of business is framed as the primary purpose of the EU Justice Scoreboard, before the interests of EU citizens.Footnote 43 Thus, the relevance of the rule of law to private actors is limited in the traditional rule of law narrative to thinking about how to protect private interests — especially business interests — from the arbitrary exercise of public power.

Yet private actors can themselves be powerful. Thus, we turn to a less conventional rule of law narrative: one of protection from private actors.

3 Rule of Law as a Protection Against Private Power

As meticulously demonstrated by Sempill, private actors can possess the same characteristics as those with which the traditional rule of law narrative takes issue with respect to public actors — tyranny, arbitrariness, slavishness, and corruption.Footnote 44 Thus, in recent years scholars have challenged the legitimacy of framing the rule of law as a principle limited to the ‘tempering’Footnote 45 of public power.Footnote 46 On this reading, obligations based on the rule of law are passed on to those with the capacity to cause various types of harm through the arbitrary exercise of the power they possess in relation to another private party. It is then not only public actors that have rule of law-related obligations.

If we agree that, according to the principle of the rule of law, States should temper private power, what might this look like in the EU? Firstly, the rule of law in Article 2 TEU as given concrete expression throughout EU law would bind the Member States as signatories to the Treaties to ensure that both public and private power cannot be used arbitrarily on the domestic and EU levels. The rule of law therefore requires establishing inter alia legal provisions and institutions to temper public power. However, given the possibility of the arbitrary exercise of power by private parties, it should also entail establishing such provisions and institutions to temper private power. Thus, a State or the Union itself cannot be based on the rule of law in the sense of Article 2 TEU if private actors could cause harms equivalent to those prevented by the law in respect to public actors.

If it is accepted that the EU rule of law principle may bind Member States at the EU and national levels to ensure that private power over individuals is not exercised arbitrarily, lessons can be learned from the above ECJ case law example on judicial independence. Indeed, the rule of law would then require Member States to ensure that private parties exercise their power according to objective and verifiable criteria and that these actors give reasons for their decisions. A failure to fulfil either of these criteria may be saved by the presence of an independent advisory body or (more relevant in the case of private actors) by the possibility of judicial review.

As will be seen in the following section, the Member States acting at the Union level have already effectively taken steps towards enshrining a rule of law principle that protects individuals from the arbitrary exercise of power. This is different from saying that this protection is sufficient, however. Through various means, private actors still regularly exercise their powers arbitrarily in ways that affect the interests and alter the situation of individuals. Such deficiencies can only be addressed if the aforementioned duty of Member States and the Union to ensure private actors uphold the rule of law is itself complied with, by ensuring that rule of law considerations are formally incorporated into decision-making processes related to measures regulating private actors.

4 EU Law as Already Tempering the Power of Private Actors

As observed by Adenitire, the core facets of national legal systems already reflect the notion of the rule of law as constraining private power: ‘Ordinary criminal law, tort law, contract law, and private law more generally fulfil the rule of law’s basic idea of constraining arbitrary power between private persons.’Footnote 47 EU law, too, already provides protection from some of the most egregious consequences of the arbitrary exercise of private power. Indeed, the research underlying this piece identified various examples as being at their core about tempering private power or tempering both public and private power. These examples demonstrate that EU law already goes a considerable way to protecting individuals — as fundamental rights-holders, as consumers, and as workers — from the arbitrary exercise of private power. Indeed, European societies would look radically different without fundamental rights that bound private actors, consumer protection and competition law, and labour law. It would be a Union in which fundamental rights would not truly exist and consumers and workers could be subject to the most grievous forms of exploitation.

The Protection of Individuals as Individuals: Fundamental Rights,Footnote 48

Fundamental rights are an important area in which Member States have laid down objective and verifiable criteria for the exercise of private power, coupled with the possibility of judicial review by independent bodies.

The basis for obligations on private parties to respect the fundamental rights of other private parties (i.e. in ‘horizontal’ situations) in the EU varies. At the most basic level, international law contains obligations for States to ensure that private actors respect the fundamental rights of individuals.Footnote 49 Positive obligations on private actors are largely absent from the ECJ’s fundamental rights jurisprudence, instead preferring a state liability approach.Footnote 50 But in its contemporary case law the ECJ has confirmed the ‘direct horizontality’ of fundamental rights as general principles of EU law,Footnote 51 as well as that of certain provisions of the Charter.Footnote 52 The Court has otherwise resorted to ‘indirect horizontality’, requiring that national law be interpreted consistently with the protection of fundamental rights.Footnote 53 All of these avenues of fundamental rights protection in horizontal situations are at their core about tempering the power of private actors to impede these rights, whether it is achieved directly by binding those private actors by fundamental rights standards or indirectly by effectively obliging state actors to create laws and policies that constrain the ability of private actors to harm such rights. Thus, ideas related to the rule of law as a notion applicable to private power play a part in underpinning the scope of fundamental rights regimes. Moreover, many rights in vertical relationships require the State to protect private actors from other private parties, including both civil and political but also social and economic rights.Footnote 54

However, whether EU and national law sufficiently temper private actors' ability to impede fundamental rights is another question. Gaps still exist in the horizontal protection of fundamental rights. Business actors continue to commit human rights violations across the EU Member States.Footnote 55 For instance, in a 2019 report the EU Fundamental Rights Agency (FRA) identified 155 incidents of fundamental rights abuses by business actors over a seven-year period.Footnote 56 Yet according to the FRA, challenges especially exist regarding access to effective remedies when violations by business actors do occur.Footnote 57 Victims must identify the relevant court, may fear stigmatisation or reprisals, and may be restricted for financial reasons from seeking judicial remedies.Footnote 58

Moreover, the Venice Commission is of the opinion that ‘The substance of the rule of law as a guiding principle for the future has to be extended… to activities of private actors whose power to infringe individual rights has a weight comparable to state power’.Footnote 59 One can envision a broad range of such ‘activities’. However, this seems considerably circumscribed by the Venice Commission’s consideration that such activities are limited to tasks that ‘formerly have been the domain of state authorities’.Footnote 60 In the area of fundamental rights, there are plentiful private activities that were not formerly the domain of public authorities but that involve a private power comparable to state power in terms of the ability to infringe fundamental rights. For instance, and as seen in the following sections, private business actors may possess a significant degree of power over individuals when they engage with them as consumers and as workers.

The Protection of Individuals as Consumers: Consumer Protection and Competition Law

The consumer protection and competition law dimensions of the EU internal market facilitate the internal market by protecting the rule of law. Indeed, both areas are in essence about tempering the power of private actors vis-à-vis individuals as consumers. For consumer protection,Footnote 61 this has been confirmed numerous times throughout the case law in which the ECJ has stated that ‘the system of protection introduced by [the Unfair Terms in Consumer Contracts Directive] is based on the idea that the consumer is in a weak position vis-à-vis the seller or supplier, as regards both his bargaining power and his level of knowledge’Footnote 62 Thus, Weatherill writes that, ‘And so the directive aims to replace the formal balance that the contract establishes between the rights and obligations of the parties with an effective balance that reestablishes equality between those parties.’Footnote 63 The same can apply to the other core pieces of EU consumer contract legislation — the Consumer Rights Directive, the Sale of Goods Directive, and the Unfair Commercial Practices Directive.Footnote 64Footnote 65 The CFR also establishes a commitment to consumer protection, providing that ‘Union policies shall ensure a high level of consumer protection.’Footnote 66

The protection of consumers as the consumer as the weaker party also underpins EU competition law. While competition law is part of the internal market structure and hence also protects market integration, the primary basis for contemporary enforcement is its consumer welfare objective. The EU consumer welfare objective protects both static and dynamic efficiency in a long-term sense. Effectively, all areas of competition law — prohibitions of anticompetitive agreement, abuses of dominance, and merger regulation — are concerned with market power. For instance, the idea underpinning Article 102 of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union (TFEU) – the abuse of dominance prohibition – is that where undertakings dominate a market, they are particularly well-placed to harm consumers. They may do so indirectly — e.g. by pushing competitors out of the market through practices such as loyalty rebates, margin squeezes or exclusive dealing — or directly — most notably through excessive pricing.

Both consumer protection and competition law are therefore about private actors and their power vis-à-vis consumers. Specifically, these legal areas constrain undertakings' ability to exercise power over individuals arbitrarily. The law itself lays down objective and verifiable criteria that preclude the possibility of undertakings exercising their powers arbitrarily vis-à-vis consumers and provides the possibility of judicial review, demonstrating how rule of law ideas already form part of the establishment and functioning of the internal market. Indeed, if markets are entirely lawless and undertakings are able to exercise power completely arbitrarily, the internal market idea falls apart.

Thus, EU consumer and competition law make a start at reigning in certain emanations of arbitrary power that may harm consumer interests in particularly egregious ways.

The Protection of Individuals as Workers: Labour Law

Finally, in the employment context the law also recognises that particularly stark power imbalances arise that need readjusting. Legislators understand the worker-employer relationship as a horizontal relationship of particular significance in this respect. Lawmakers have enshrined labour rights in various human rights documents, including the CFR. The Charter’s Title IV (Solidarity) protects a range of rights, such as the right of collective bargaining and action, fair and just working conditions, or protection against unjustified dismissal.Footnote 67 Thus, individuals are also protected as workers under EU labour law from certain arbitrary exercises of power by employers.

For instance, the changes brought to the Posted Workers Directive by Directive 2018/957 prevent workers from the posted State from being subject to lower rates of pay of a home State when they are posted to a host State,Footnote 68 where they are posted for longer than a month.Footnote 69 It likewise ensures equality of treatment e.g. for maximum work periods and minimum rest periods as well as minimum paid annual leave.Footnote 70 These EU rules prevent specific forms of exploitation of the power imbalance between workers and employers. The same is true of other directives of EU labour law – for example, the Directive on Transparent and Predictable Working Conditions. Under the latter, the employer is obliged to provide certain information: e.g. on the duration and conditions of the probationary period (if any), the amount of paid leave, notice periods for termination, and details related to remuneration and work pattern.Footnote 71

Again, however, limits remain on how far EU or Member State law have been willing to go to protect workers from arbitrary exercises of power. When it comes to decisions that can fundamentally alter the workers’ situations — such as redundancies and transfers of companies — worker participation rights are limited to information and consultation. For collective redundancies, employers must begin consultations ‘in good time with a view to reaching an agreement’.Footnote 72 They must notify workers of inter alia the reasons for the redundancies and the number and categories of workers to be made redundant.Footnote 73 Similarly, for transfers of undertakings, where the transfer envisages measures related to employees, the employer must consult employee representatives with a view to reaching an agreement in good time.Footnote 74 Representatives of employees are to be informed inter alia of the date, reasons for, and implications of the transfer, as well as any measures envisaged related to employees.Footnote 75 The more general Directive 2002/14 establishing a general framework for informing and consulting employees also limits worker participation to information and consultation,Footnote 76 as the title suggests.

Beyond this, none of the Directives attempt to reign in the power of employers vis-à-vis employees in situations that can significantly affect their lives. Thus, like fundamental rights, consumer protection, and competition law, certain areas of labour law can be seen as being underpinned by a rule of law notion that protects individuals from the arbitrary exercise of private power. However, in some areas of EU labour law, such as collective redundancies and company transfers, the law only takes minor steps towards reigning in the ability to exercise this power.

These examples demonstrate that EU law already embodies the idea that the rule of law does require protection from private actors. This is not to say that EU law goes far enough in protecting individuals as fundamental rights holders, consumers, and workers from the arbitrary exercise of power. This can be attributed to the fact that rule of law considerations are not formally incorporated into the decision-making procedures leading up to such measures. Moreover, there are also areas in which power is held by private actors that extend beyond this remit and is wielded arbitrarily, such as in politics.Footnote 77 The following section focuses on this example and demonstrates that lobbying regulation in the EU focuses on transparency, but that this does not suffice to temper the arbitrary exercise of private power.

5 Areas of Arbitrary Private Power and the Rule of Law

Lobbying is an activity that can affect all three categories of individuals — as fundamental rights holders, consumers, or workers. It may thus stand in tension with the rule of law.Footnote 78 In the EU, there is also substantial room for lobbyists to arbitrarily exercise their capacity to lobby and powers that derive therefrom. Here it is argued that problems of arbitrary exercises of power may arise where corporations act outside or in breach of the law or are able to influence the law.

Corporate political activity (CPA) has been part of the European law-making process for decades. As forwarded with [to be added after peer-review], business actors played a pivotal role in the constitutionalisation of the internal market project. This constitutionalisation started with their use of the preliminary ruling procedure in the foundational years of the European Economic Community to force Member States to comply with the Treaty obligations of negative integration. In the 1980s and 1990s, business interests then played significant parts in securing the content of the Single European Act and thus the establishment of the internal market itself, and in convincing Member States to comply with the 1992 liberalisation agenda. Member States did not establish formal procedures to ensure that certain private actors did not play an outsized role in the law-making process. They did not establish objective and verifiable criteria in this respect, and no reasons were given for decisions; this was not counter-balanced by the presence of an independent advisory body nor the possibility of judicial review. Thus, from its outset the very core of the European Union — the internal market — was based on the arbitrary wielding of substantial private power.

A few decades later, when considerable opacity still exists as to the role of powerful private actors in the EU decision-making process, how much has changed?

To be sure, the role of private actors in EU law-making and policymaking has become more formalised. But greater formalisation does not necessarily mean greater compliance with rule of law principles. Evidence still suggests that business actors play an outsized role in Commission Expert Groups, with Chalmers concluding ‘that expert group membership is largely a function of superior resources’.Footnote 79 For instance, Gornitzka and Sverdrup found that ‘groups representing business and enterprise are the most frequent participants in the Commission expert groups (present in 29 per cent of the groups)’.Footnote 80 What is the Commission doing to ensure that those private actors with superior resources are not able to exercise the power they have in Commission expert groups arbitrarily? At present, it appears that there is nothing: no requirements that these groups take decisions according to objective and verifiable criteria, no requirements to give reasons for their decisions. This room for arbitrariness is not safeguarded by the presence of an independent advisory panel, nor are their decisions amenable to judicial review.

The situation becomes starker when one looks at the mechanisms designed to address lobbying practices. Research undertaken by media outlets, civil society groups, and academicsFootnote 81 assessing particular sectors has documented numerous instances of apparent influence by corporate actors over EU legislation. These actors achieve such successes through lobbying. What does EU law do to ensure that, through lobbying, private actors are unable to wield their power over others arbitrarily? In essence, the Union institutions have sought to shine greater light on these processes that undermine the EU rule of law, particularly through the Transparency Register. But transparency does not necessarily mean less arbitrary decision-making where it does not entail greater accountability.

The Transparency Register rules are limited to disclosure. Commercial and non-commercial interests who lobby the Parliament, Council and Commission must be members of the Register. Indeed, according to the 2021 Interinstitutional Agreement, the Register covers ‘activities carried out by interest representatives with the objective of influencing the formulation or implementation of policy or legislation, or the decision-making processes’ of the aforementioned EU institutions ‘or other Union institutions’.Footnote 82

In terms of the information available on the Register, one gets only a superficial snapshot of the lobbying activities that take place. The Register website provides lists of meetings, contributions to public consultations and roadmaps, participation in EU ‘structures and platforms’ (i.e. Parliament and Commission groups) and other ‘forums and platforms’. The disclosed activities are presumed to be ‘legitimate and necessary’.Footnote 83 However, without more detailed information about the content of these interactions, who is to say whether that is in fact the case?

This limited information directly conflicts with the principle of openness articulated in the Treaties, according to ‘which the Union's institutions, bodies, offices and agencies shall conduct their work as openly as possible.’Footnote 84 As highlighted in Regulation 1049/2001 regarding public access to documents and acknowledged by the ECJ, openness ‘enables citizens to participate more closely in the decision-making process and guarantees that the administration enjoys greater legitimacy and is more effective and more accountable to the citizen in a democratic system’.Footnote 85 This principle is interlinked with the rule of law, in that in a system with a strong rule of law, openness allows the public to access information about the decision-making processes of those in power and to hold them accountable for their actions. This, in turn, helps to reinforce the rule of law by ensuring that individuals are not able to use their power to evade the law. On the flip side, a lack of transparency in government decision-making processes can prevent the public from holding officials accountable, which can undermine the rule of law.

To ensure that private actors are not exercising power arbitrarily, one might go even further than ensuring greater openness by limiting the range of lobbying activities that can be engaged in, thus targeting not just disclosure but the content of lobbying itself. An EU founded on the rule of law that recognises the importance of this principle for governing the activities of private actors would require more than mere disclosure of lobbying activities. Tempering the capacity of private interests to exercise their power arbitrarily over others would mean either limiting their lobbying capacity in the first place or ensuring that equal opportunity exists to hear other voices.

6 Conclusion

In recent years, the rule of law has taken centre stage in EU constitutional law, in light of the trampling on this value by particular Member States. This context has given the ECJ ample opportunity to clarify what the rule of law requires, including non-discretionary decision-making unless circumscribed by particular guardrails. It has become clear from this case law and the definitions provided by EU policymakers that the EU rule of law is concerned with the arbitrary exercise of power. The traditional rule of law narrative frames the rule of law as being fundamental for the protection of private interests, including business interests, from the arbitrary exercise of public power. However, the issue of the compatibility of the exercise of private power with the rule of law is less discussed. Yet the arbitrary exercise of private power can do as much damage to individuals as that by public power and should therefore be considered of equal importance. The concentration of private power in particular areas is why EU law already makes a certain effort to constrain the arbitrary exercise of private power vis-à-vis individuals as fundamental rights holders, as consumers, and as workers. From these observations, a teleological interpretation of Article 2 TEU can be argued for, which would understand the EU rule of law as binding the EU and Member States to ensure that private actors cannot arbitrarily exercise power over individuals.

In light of the foregoing, it can be asked whether the EU or the Member States go far enough in fulfilling such obligations. In view of the deficits identified in this piece with respect to fundamental rights and the protection of consumers and workers, as well as the disproportionate and untransparent access granted by the EU to powerful private actors in the law-making process, the answer must be no. Thus, although rule of law-related ideas evidently inspire the existence of such rules in the first place, we can observe the effects of the lack of their formal incorporation into decision-making procedures leading up to such measures. In what other areas are there glaring deficits in the law in terms of its protection of individuals from the arbitrary exercise of private power, and how can these be remedied? Looking beyond protection from public power, scholars and public actors must more critically reflect and debate the obligations of the EU and Member States stemming from the rule of law.

Although the current level of protection may not go far enough to protect the interests of individuals, solutions can be inspired by the rule of law principle rooted in non-arbitrariness as discussed in this piece. In particular, when it appears that private power may be capable of being exercised arbitrarily, it can be asked whether legislators can lay down objective criteria on which decisions must be based or whether they can oblige private powers to provide reasons for decisions to reduce this arbitrariness. If not, it can be pondered whether an independent body is capable of advising the relevant decision or whether the decision is subject to judicial review.

Only once the real risks associated with the concentration and arbitrary exercise of private power are addressed and recognised can the EU live up to its claim that it is based on the rule of law.