1 Introduction

In early February 1989, rumors raged the streets of East Berlin that the Schießbefehl had been suspended—the order to shoot anyone trying to cross the border. Seeing his chance, twenty-year-old Chris Gueffroy approached the fences of the Berlin Wall. But the rumors were just that. Gueffroy became the 67th and last person to be shot at the Berlin Wall (Hertle and Nooke 2009, 18–25). Gueffroy was killed by a hierarchical group. Three years later, GDR soldiers as well as party leaders were convicted of manslaughter and murder.

Many groups—businesses, government agencies, or military organizations—are hierarchical.Footnote 1 Hierarchical groups lay off employees, deport immigrants, and kill in wars. This paper concerns the question of how individuals in such groups can be responsible.Footnote 2 I argue that difference-making, as defined by List and Menzies (2009), provides a promising partial ground of such individual responsibility: Individual responsibility is grounded in the difference individuals make.

Understanding responsibility in hierarchical groups is relevant for business, organizational, and military ethics. It is crucial for issues in just war theory—such as the permissibility of retributive operations, or for post-war justice and reconciliation. Moreover, accounts of responsibility in hierarchical groups may support dogmatic development in criminal law.Footnote 3 Hierarchical groups are a common topic in legal philosophy (Roxin, 1963, 2011; Smidt, 2000; Kutz, 2000, Chap. 5; Danner and Martinez 2005; May, 2005; Weigend, 2011; Eldar, 2013; DeFalco, 2013). In moral philosophy, debates on collective responsibility have instead concentrated on joint actions, pairs of individuals, or the corporate responsibility of a group as a whole (French, 1979; Pettit, 2007; List and Pettit 2011; Isaacs, 2011; Bazargan-Forward, 2017).Footnote 4 This paper provides metaphysical foundations for extant accounts in philosophy of law, it complements accounts in philosophy by exploring the control condition of responsibility and couching the proposal in an alternative causal framework, and it emphasizes a role for individual responsibility in certain collective contexts.Footnote 5

The paper is structured as follows. In Sect. 2, I start with a motivating puzzle, characterize hierarchical groups, and delineate the topic. I then discuss existing solutions to this puzzle in Sect. 3. Next, in Sect. 4, I build on the characteristics of hierarchical groups from Sect. 2 to offer an account of how difference-making can partially ground individual moral responsibility. I discuss limitations and implications of this account in Sect. 5.

To avoid confusion: By “responsibility” and its cognates I mean retrospective moral responsibility. Philosophers have put forth a good variety of analyses of responsibility (Watson, 1996; Smith, 2006; Shoemaker, 2011). But in this paper, I am concerned with what grounds responsibility (the grounding question) rather than with what responsibility is (the analytical question).Footnote 6 What I say should be compatible with various existing analyses of responsibility.Footnote 7 In particular, my account is compatible with understanding responsibility as praise- or blameworthiness.

This paper is on one partial ground of responsibility: the control condition (in contrast to the epistemic condition, or other conditions that there may be).Footnote 8 We are not responsible for everything we do. We are responsible at most for some aspects and consequences of our conduct—things that we have done or that we refrained from doing. I will use “agency” as the name of some such relation that, put metaphorically, circumscribes responsibility’s reach by identifying those things for which someone might be responsible, and that hence partially grounds moral responsibility.Footnote 9 As Rosen (2010) remarks: For which consequences agents are (not) responsible is a question “about which philosophers have been strangely silent.”Footnote 10 This agency relation—that someone did something, is the agent of something, or exercised agency with respect to some consequence—is only a partial ground of moral responsibility in two respects. First, the agency relation is only one ground of responsibility among several others (such as those captured by the epistemic condition). Second, some argue that the agency relation grounds responsibility only sometimes (that someone is an agent of something is neither necessary nor sufficient for their responsibility).Footnote 11

2 Hierarchical groups

The case of Chris Gueffroy illustrates hierarchical groups in practice. But hierarchical groups are also theoretically interesting. Consider a simple case: A commander has several soldiers under her command. She orders these soldiers to shoot an innocent victim. And they comply. Each soldier goes to their station; the soldier whose station the victim passes first shoots the victim. How can we explain everyone’s responsibility?

It seems natural to explain everyone’s individual responsibility in terms of their causal contribution, their control, or more broadly, their agency. But doing so is not as straight-forward as it may seem. There are two families of theories of causation: production theories and dependence theories (cf. Hall, 2004). Roughly, the former see causes as mechanisms that produce their effect through a local transfer of some force, such as billiard balls hitting each other or a lightning setting a tree on fire. The latter theories instead see causes in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions on which the effects depend. Sometimes these theories arrive at different conclusions—the presence of oxygen and the absence of rain are causes of the tree catching fire on dependence theories, but not on production theories. In this case of a commanded killing, however, both kinds of theories are hard pressed to explain everyone’s responsibility.

When we turn to production theories of causation, such as “such as mark-transfer theories and conserved-quantity-transfer theories,” then, Bazargan-Forward (2017, 111) observes, “what [a superior] does might not count as causally contributing to [a subordinate’s] wrongful act.”Footnote 12 Production theories of causation are hence hard pressed to explain why the commander is responsible.

Dependence theories of causation, by contrast, have easy answers for why the commander is responsible. Since the commander is a “sine qua non … [this] provides a prima facie basis for regarding [the commander] as at least somewhat morally responsible” (Bazargan-Forward, 2017, 111). But dependence theories are instead hard pressed to explain why subordinates are responsible. For example, the victim’s death does not counterfactually depend on any subordinate’s conduct. It is a case of redundant causation: If one subordinate had resisted the order, another solider would have shot the victim instead. Thus, at least on simple counterfactual dependence, no soldier is an agent of the victim’s death (cf. Lawson, 2011, 240).

To make matters worse, if there are more than two levels in the hierarchy, the victim’s death does not counterfactually depend on our commander’s order either. If there is a commander above our commander and other commanders left and right, our commander’s conduct is also redundant: If she had refused to give the order to shoot the victim, another commander would have. Hierarchical groups have such redundancies on almost every level.

In sum, whether and how agency grounds responsibility in hierarchical groups is considered somewhat of a puzzle in the literature. This is not to suggest that there is a yet unsolved or overlooked theoretical problem to which I offer the first solution.Footnote 13 To the contrary. Theories of causation generally, and the debate on collective responsibility specifically, already offer relevant solutions (I discuss some below). This paper applies one theory from the former to contribute an alternative account to the latter.

2.1 Characteristics

In this simple case as well as in the case of Chris Gueffroy, hierarchical groups exhibit three relevant characteristics: asymmetry, control, and redundancy (cf. Buchanan, 1996; Prosecutor v. Katanga and Chui 2008).

First, hierarchical groups have asymmetric authority relations (formally, a partial order): Some are superiors to subordinates (or they occupy a “higher level”), and they can direct their subordinates, but not usually the other way around.Footnote 14 This hierarchy enables a vertical division of labor: Superiors give directives that are typically incomplete, or at least not maximally specific.Footnote 15 Hence, subordinates can—within limits—carry them out in more than one way.Footnote 16 By contrast, many existing accounts of shared agency assume forms of equal or symmetric cooperation, or a horizontal division of labor as seen in sports teams, mobs, committees, or juries (e.g. Bratman, 2014, 7, 85).

Second, along the lines of this asymmetric structure, we find a functional dependence. Subordinates not only ought to respond to their superiors, but they in fact generally do respond to superiors in certain ways. This is because individuals higher up have some degree of control or influence over their subordinates.Footnote 17

Third, hierarchical groups often exhibit a certain degree of redundancy to ensure that the directives of superiors are carried out. Typically, redundancy in hierarchical groups is achieved by associating several subordinates with each superior. In result, the structure of a hierarchical group, of the kind considered here, looks like a pyramid or an inverted tree. At the top is one node from which subordinate nodes spring that, in turn, serve as superiors to further subordinates, and so forth.Footnote 18

2.2 Responsibility

Hierarchical groups exhibit three phenomena relating to responsibility. Not only are, first, superiors responsible but so are, second, subordinates. In the case of the Berlin Wall shootings, those up the chain of command who issued the order to shoot are responsible, as well as the soldiers who carried out the order.Footnote 19 Third, at least in some cases, responsibility can be increasing; that is, superiors can, in some sense, be more responsible than their subordinates.Footnote 20 “Can be” because responsibility may increase in some groups and in some cases but not in others.Footnote 21

Many defend increasing responsibility (cf. May, 1992, 123; 2005, 154; Isaacs, 2011, 115). And the phenomenon can also be seen in criminal law: The commanders in the Berlin Wall shootings, for example, received longer sentences. For an even clearer statement, consider the case of Adolf Eichmann. When a court in Jerusalem sentenced Eichmann to death in December 1961, it recognized that in hierarchical groups, responsibility tends to increase with hierarchy.

[T]he extent to which any one of the many criminals were close to, or remote from, the actual killer of the victim, means nothing as far as the measure of his responsibility is concerned. On the contrary, in general, the degree of responsibility increases as we draw further away from the man who uses the fatal instrument with his own hands and reach the higher ranks of command (The Attorney General v. Eichmann, 1961, 197).

Increasing responsibility can be seen also in private organizations. For example, the vice-president of a corporation that produces landmines is, in some sense, more responsible than its shipping clerk (Kutz, 2000, 158; Lawson, 2011, 240).

All this suggests that the three characteristics and three phenomena delineate a domain of hierarchal groups that is broader than military organizations and extends at least to some private corporations. However, an account developed for this domain does not extend to unorganized groups (which might have a structure, albeit of a different kind), or mobs, who lack this combination of asymmetric structure, function, and organized redundancy.

3 Existing work

An account of responsibility in hierarchical groups needs to make sense of the three phenomena. It should explain the individual responsibility of superiors and subordinates and explain increasing responsibility. Concentrating on the agency relation to ground moral responsibility, a central challenge is to give an account that is unified (in that it is characterized by the same criteria for all individuals in a hierarchy). Moreover, an account should distinguish individual contributions. A superior and a subordinate seem responsible on somewhat different grounds: A commander, for example, is responsible, in part, because she gave an order. A soldier is responsible because they carried out or did not resist this order. Finally, an account should scale, that is, it should be applicable to hierarchical groups with many levels. Meeting these desiderata is a theoretical challenge—after all, as more levels of hierarchy are involved, the initial intuitive clarity of talking of “individual contribution” is soon lost.

Several authors have tackled this challenge. Christopher Kutz, Larry May, as well as Tracy Isaacs, and Matthew Braham and Martin van Hees put forward accounts that could be applied to the three phenomena (Kutz, 2000, Chap. 5; May, 2005, Chap. 8; Isaacs, 2011, Chap. 4; Braham and van Hees 2009; 2012). But each of them either concentrates on agents’ intentions and the epistemological condition of responsibility not on individual agency as a ground of individual responsibility (Kutz and May), or their account doesn’t extend to hierarchical groups (Braham and van Hees), or it can’t clearly distinguish the different contributions or outcomes associated with individuals on different levels in the hierarchy (Isaacs).

Kutz explains increasing responsibility with facts about agents’ intentions.Footnote 22 A superior is more responsible than a subordinate because a superior has an “executive intention” whereas a subordinate only has a “subsidiary intention” (Kutz, 2000, 160 my emphasis). Both participate in the action of the group—this the limited extent to which the control condition comes in—but the difference in their responsibility is explained by a difference in their intention: by “the attitudes they take towards the success of the activity” (Kutz, 2000, 159).Footnote 23 In fact, Kutz explicitly opposes explaining increasing responsibility as having to do with agency (2000, 52), and others agree (Lawson, 2011, 240–42). Isaacs (2011, 118) observes similarly that “Kutz detaches individual responsibility from causal contribution.” Thus, Kutz’ proposed answer to the puzzle of who is responsible for a commanded killing doesn’t rely on individual agency at all. It concentrates almost entirely on individuals’ intentions and doesn’t seek to incorporate the intuitive idea that someone’s responsibility depends on what they did.

May, like Kutz, concentrates on agents’ intentions. He investigates subordinate responsibility primarily with an eye to intent (May, 2005, 125–27); defends “a special intent requirement” for superior responsibility (2005, 139); and understands hierarchical groups generally in analogy with conspiracies (2005, 143). Occasionally, May relates superior and subordinate responsibility to the control condition (cf. 1987, 89–106; 2005, 139–48); contending that superiors’ responsibility is grounded in negligent omissions (2005, 142).

My account differs from—and improves on—May’s in two main ways. First, I don’t think superiors are responsible mainly because of their negligence or their omissions. Superiors are responsible for giving directives at least much as they are for failing to act. My account captures this active agential role of superiors (and subordinates). A second difference between May’s proposed solution and my account is that May seeks to hold individuals responsible for collective actions.Footnote 24 After all, May’s overall interest is in explaining why heads of state are responsible for crimes against humanity, such as genocides, seen as collective actions. My account, instead, concentrates on individual responsibility for individual actions and spells out how superiors and subordinates differently contribute to some outcome.

Likewise does the account developed by Tracy Isaacs. Isaacs concentrates on individual responsibility for individual actions in hierarchical groups, and she seeks to explain the three phenomena via the control condition of responsibility (2011, Chap. 4). Her account takes as a theoretical primitive that for each basic action there is a set of action descriptions, such that any individual action can be re-described in terms of any of its causal consequences (2011, 100–101).Footnote 25 Isaacs uses this to explain how individuals are responsible in, even if not for, collective actions: A superior is individually responsible in the collective action of killing an innocent victim because her action of ordering to kill this victim can be redescribed as this victim being killed by a subordinate.

But this approach has two main problems. First, it is not clear how it distinguishes superiors’ and subordinates’ differential contribution to some outcome. Both individual actions can, likewise, be described in terms of the same causal consequence: the victim’s death. Second, and more fundamentally, it is unclear how the set of action descriptions for a given action is to be delimited. Without further restrictions on how actions can be described, an agent would be an agent of too many consequences (I discuss how my account addresses such a problem towards the end of Sect. 4.1). But we need to limit what individuals are agents of. To avoid circularity, any account based on action descriptions needs a certain theory of causation or an independent theory of action individuation (see Bratman, 2006).Footnote 26

My account rests on theoretical underpinnings that avoid these problems. My account offers explicit conditions to identify—and limit—what individuals are agents of (it moreover explicates some assumptions about action individuation, in Sect. 4.3). In this way, my account develops what an account that starts with action descriptions presupposes.

Finally, Braham and van Hees (2009; 2012) develop an account of individual responsibility in collective settings that likewise centers on the agential condition. Their account of agency is based on the NESS test—another way of understanding “difference making”—which they formalize using game theory.Footnote 27 However, their account does not extend to hierarchical groups. Individuals in hierarchical groups “play” conditional strategies: Subordinates perform certain actions, if so directed by a superior. But the NESS test cannot deal with such conditional intentions or strategies (Braham and Hees 2009, 615).Footnote 28 Moreover, the account that I develop is based on the machinery of possible-world semantics, which, at least to some, might be a preferable theoretical approach (because of its greater generality, simplicity, or some other theoretical virtue). For instance, my account has resources to address the so-called Queen of England problem (e.g. Menzies, 2011; Himmelreich, 2023). Analogous solutions for Braham’s and van Hees’ account have not yet been developed (2009, n. 7).

4 Agency and responsibility in hierarchical groups

To explain responsibility in hierarchical groups, let’s expand on the earlier motivating case by adding some details: Anne, a military commander, directs her team to shoot an innocent victim, Collin. The team consists of several soldiers, Bert, Ben, Bob, and some others. Each is dispatched to a post and each of them is sufficiently motivated to follow Anne’s directives, although each may comply for different reasons. Bert’s post is the one that Collin passes first. Bert knows that if he were not to shoot, then someone else would. Bert also believes with good reason that he would be faced with mildly severe sanctions if he disobeyed Anne’s order. Bert goes ahead and shoots Collin.

Yet, the description of this case still leaves some things open. It does not specify how many soldiers are in Anne’s team, what motivates the soldiers, and what sanctions are in store for Bert. But for present purposes, these aspects do not matter very much. What matters is that Anne gives a command to kill an innocent victim (by assumption, a moral wrong). If Anne gives the command, then someone will shoot and kill Collin. Collin would die even if Bert were not to shoot.Footnote 29 Moreover, in contrast to subordinates operating some murderous machine that requires each to do their part to bring about Collin’s death at all, this case involves no joint action or horizontal division of labor but only vertical division of labor (at least as far as the act of shooting Collin is concerned). In other words, Bert or any of the other soldiers would shoot Collin individually, they don’t shoot Collin together. However, neither Anne nor any of her soldiers have a fully exculpating excuse. Concerning the looming sanctions and the soldiers’ motivations, it suffices to assume that the sanctions for anyone refusing to follow directives are mildly severe. That is, the sanctions are sufficiently harsh to dispose subordinates’ compliance and yet sufficiently bearable to not excuse them for their conduct. Moreover, the model case is silent about the group’s normative context. Bert’s responsibility overall depends on the normative structure within which the group operates; in particular, on Anne’s authority and hence whether her directives give soldiers a reason to act (cf. Estlund, 2007; Crawford, 2007). But the issue here is not whether someone is responsible but only one aspect of why they are when they are. Finally, this model case does not clearly exhibit increasing responsibility (I return to this phenomenon later). In sum, even though this model case above involves vast simplifications and leaves many things open, it should resemble paradigmatic cases, like the Berlin Wall shootings, in crucial respects.

The account that I put forward consists of two parts.Footnote 30 The first part consists of dependence conditions to spell out the idea that individuals make a difference to some outcome. This part of the account is stated in terms of two conditionals. The second part concerns the individuation of outcomes. I formalize the intuitive idea that superiors control a course of events only in broad strokes. Subordinates, in comparison, exercise more fine-grained control over what happens, given that the coarse-grained direction has already been fixed. Accordingly, the hierarchy of individuals is associated with a hierarchy of outcomes. This second part comes in to explain subordinates’ responsibility as well as to scale up the account (roughly: just as there is someone in case Bert fails to carry out Anne’s directives, there might be someone to play Anne’s role in case she fails to carry her superior’s directives).

4.1 Superiors’ responsibility

To explain superiors’ responsibility, we only need the following first part of the account. Consider again the case of Anne ordering Collin to be shot by someone. Two things seem to be the case. First, had Anne not given a directive to shoot Collin, then he would not have been shot.Footnote 31 Furthermore, if Anne were to give the directive to shoot Collin—that is, even if the situation were slightly different in some ways but Anne were to give the directive to shoot Collin—then Collin would still be shot. This is an instance of two conditions that Lewis (1973b) initially calls “causal dependence”—I will refer to them as the negative and positive conditional respectively. The negative conditional captures that had Anne not given the order, then Collin would not have been shot (at least not on her order). The positive conditional captures that Anne can ensure that Collin is shot. In a way, each of the two conditionals represents a different aspect of agency. The positive conditional represents the idea of agency as implementation, as an individual seeing to it that something will be the case. The negative conditional, by contrast, represents the idea of agency as prevention.

The negative conditional is a subjunctive counterfactual conditional. We can evaluate whether it is true using standard semantics for counterfactuals, such as that by Lewis (1973a). This semantics builds on the construction of representing different possibilia, such as possible worlds, ordered by increasing distance to the actual world. The negative counterfactual for the given case of Anne is true if in all nearby worlds in which Anne does not give the directive to shoot Collin, it is the case that Collin is not shot.Footnote 32

The positive conditional should also be read as a subjunctive conditional, but it is not a counterfactual conditional. The statement in the antecedent—that Anne gives the order—is actually true. The idea behind reading this conditional as a subjunctive conditional is that we want to examine whether the outcome of Collin being shot depends on Anne’s directive robustly. Will Collin be shot in all relevantly similar situations in which Anne gives the order? To capture this robust dependence between Anne giving the directive and the outcome of Collin being shot, we can still rely on a kind of counterfactual reasoning: We ask the question of whether these two things, the directing and the shooting, co-occur reliably under changes in circumstances. To answer this question, the semantics for counterfactuals can be used, if the semantics is suitably amended. The amendment needed is that other possibilities may be as close to the actual world as the actual world is to itself (Lewis, 1973a, 29). In effect, conditional statements with true antecedents—such as the positive conditional—are evaluated relative to a set of nearby possible worlds that may contain more possibilities than only the actual world.Footnote 33

Agency in hierarchical groups is defined by these two conditions—the conditions of “difference-making” as I propose to understand it here. An individual makes a difference to some outcome if and only if, given the amended semantics, the positive and negative conditionals are true. Anne is responsible for Collin’s death (partly) in virtue of her making a difference to it. This is an example of how superiors’ agency grounds superiors’ responsibility.

To state this definition of agency in full generality, let a be an individual—in this case Anne—and let i be an intention of a.Footnote 34 Alternatively, it could be said that i stands for a directive that a gives. But if the proposal should be generalized beyond contexts of directives, i needs to be an intention or an intention-like mental state of a. Finally, let x be some outcome that actually occurs.Footnote 35 Agency in hierarchical groups is then defined as the following dependence. The individual a makes a difference to x if and only if, if a were not to have i, then x would not occur; conversely, if a were to have i then x would occur. Agency, or difference-making, with respect to an outcome is defined as this dependence of an outcome on an agent’s intention.

This combination of negative and positive conditional should be familiar to many, since this is how Lewis (1973b, 563) initially defines causal dependence, before setting the positive conditional aside. This raises at least two questions. First, what is the purpose of the first, the positive, conditional? Second, how are well-known under-generation problems with the second, the negative, conditional avoided?

First, the role of the positive conditional is to limit individuals’ agency. If agency were only defined by the negative conditional, then any agent who makes a difference to one thing would be the agent of far too many things. Lewis (1987, 184–88) discusses the case of writing a reference letter for a student. With only the negative conditional, by writing a strong letter for a student, Lewis would make a difference not only to his student getting the job, but also to several other candidates not getting the job, to them pursuing different careers, to them meeting their partners, to their children being born and passing away. This may or may not be an acceptable implication for a theory of causation, it is not for a theory of agency.Footnote 36 Lewis thus suggests that the relevant relation needs to be one that is insensitive to circumstances. The positive conditional, evaluated within the amended semantics, is one way of spelling out Lewis’ suggestion (see Woodward, 2006 for a related proposal).Footnote 37

Of course, one might argue, insofar as we are ultimately interested in responsibility (and not just agency), superiors’ responsibility could be limited in a different way than by limiting their agency. Other conditions of responsibility, and specifically the epistemic condition, could be used to limit superiors’ responsibility (cf. Rosen, 2010, 433) and to avoid this over-generation problem that motivates the positive conditional. In this sense, the positive conditional seems under-motivated.Footnote 38

The epistemic condition certainly is one limit on an agent’s responsibility (and likewise a partial ground of responsibility)—ignorance sometimes excuses. But the positive conditional has a role to play insofar as the epistemic condition can’t limit responsibility in all relevant cases.Footnote 39 An agent may foresee consequences of their action without being responsible for them. Edward the knife sharpener sharpens Giulia’s kitchen knives. He foresees that she might cut herself. She does. He’s the only sharpener in town. Had Edward not sharpened the knife, Giulia wouldn’t have cut herself. But Edward is not responsible. This or similar cases of “intervening agency” suggest limiting responsibility also via agency. After all, the point of partially grounding responsibility in agency is to account for the idea that an agent is responsible at most for consequences of her own conduct, or outcomes that are “glued” to her in some way (Rosen, 2010, 422). The positive conditional allows us to say that Edward is not an agent of Giulia’s injury, but that Anne is an agent of Collin’s death;Footnote 40 or that Lewis is an agent of writing a reference letter, but not of some rejected candidate meeting their partner.

Second, the negative conditional raises a problem of too little agency (or: an under-generation problem) whereas the positive conditional is motivated by avoiding a problem of too much agency (or: an over-generation problem). Specifically, suppose that if Anne had not ordered Collin’s death, someone else, say Ashley, would have. In fact, this should be so insofar as hierarchical groups have built-in redundancy. But then the second conditional seems false: Even if Anne had not ordered Collin’s death, Ashley would have, and Collin would still die. This, I take it, is an instance of the well-known problem of redundant causation, or of a Frankfurt case with a counterfactual intervener.Footnote 41

This problem arises when we think about Anne as a subordinate. Anne, although a superior to Bert and Ben, is—together with Ashley—a subordinate to someone else (because the group might have more than two levels). As far as this objection of redundant causation is concerned, Anne’s position is like Bert’s. Anne’s order and Bert’s shooting are similarly redundant. Collin would have died even if Bert had not shot (Ben would have). Likewise, an order to shoot Collin would have been given even if Anne had not given it (Ashley would have). Let’s thus move on to subordinates’ responsibility and return to the objection of redundant causation there. Here is just the very short answer: Following Peter van Inwagen (1983, 171–74), “Collin’s death” should be distinguished into different events, such as Collin dying from Bert’s shot, or him dying from Anne’s order, etc. Hence, the backup commander Ashley, or the backup soldier Ben, do not make a difference to these results.

4.2 Subordinates’ responsibility

To explain subordinates’ responsibility—and to address this problem that all individuals in a hierarchical group are redundant but still make a difference—I need to introduce the second part of the account of agency in hierarchical groups: the individuation of outcomes.

Subordinates do not seem to make a difference because if they were not to follow a directive given to them, someone else would. Bert does not make a difference to Collin’s death because, although the relevant positive conditional is true, the negative conditional is false. The positive conditional is true because Bert can make it the case that Collin dies reliably. In all relevantly similar situations, in which Bert intends to follow Anne’s directive to shoot Collin, he goes ahead and shoots, and Collin dies. Yet, the negative conditional is false. Bert cannot prevent Collin’s death. If Bert were to refuse Anne’s directive, Bob or some other soldier in the team would go ahead and shoot Collin and Collin would die regardless. In this way, it is not up to Bert whether or not Collin dies. This leaves something to explain. On what grounds, then, is Bert responsible? I contend that there is something to which Bert makes a difference.

Although it is not up to Bert whether or not Collin dies, it is up to Bert whether or not he is the one who shoots Collin. If Bert were to refuse Anne’s directive, then Collin would be shot by Ben, not by Bert. The result to which Bert makes a difference is thus not whether Collin dies, or whether Collin is shot, but whether Collin is shot by Bert.Footnote 42 For this outcome the negative conditional is true: If Bert were not to follow Anne’s directive, then Collin would not be shot by Bert. Bert thus makes a difference to one outcome (that he, and not someone else, shoots Collin) but not another (that Collin is shot). In short, what Bert does, in virtue of which he might be responsible, is that he shoots Collin. Thus, subordinates’ responsibility can be explained by distinguishing different outcomes.

We distinguish the outcome that Collin is shot from the outcomes that Collin is shot by Bert, and that Collin is shot by someone else. A similar line of reasoning is due to van Inwagen (1983, 171): That Caesar is murdered, that Caesar is stabbed, and that Caesar is poisoned are three different outcomes (or states of affairs).Footnote 43 That Caesar is poisoned and that he is stabbed each entail that he is murdered. The outcomes that he is poisoned and that he is stabbed are more fine-grained outcomes than that Caesar is murdered. Likewise, that Collin is shot by Bert, and that Collin is shot by someone else each entail that Collin is shot; and the first two outcomes (shot by Bert, shot by someone else) are more fine-grained than the outcome that Collin is shot. This idea can be made more precise if, following van Inwagen, we think of outcomes as sets of possible worlds. The more coarse-grained outcome that Collin is shot is represented by the set of all possible worlds in which Collin is shot, regardless of who shoots.Footnote 44 By contrast, the more fine-grained outcome of Collin being shot by Bert is represented by the subset of all possible worlds in which Collin is shot and in which, furthermore, the bullet that hit Collin came from the gun in Bert’s hand.Footnote 45 More generally, an outcome is more fine-grained than another if it is its proper subset. Hence, it also makes sense to talk of outcomes being nested, with fine-grained outcomes being “nested in” coarse-grained outcomes.Footnote 46

By thinking of outcomes as being represented by sets of possible worlds, the account becomes scalable. An outcome is fine-grained compared to another if it is its proper subset. Just as a hierarchical group has many levels (structured by the partial order of some authority relation), so outcomes have levels (structured by the partial order of the proper subset relation). The hierarchy of the group is thus mirrored in a hierarchy of outcomes. For each level in the hierarchy there is a corresponding level of grain of outcomes to which an individual at that level makes a difference.Footnote 47 A high-level individual in the hierarchy makes a difference to a corresponding coarse-grained outcome, a subordinate makes a difference to a fine-graining of this outcome. When hierarchical groups are conceived in this way—as a hierarchy of individuals, each of whom makes a difference to an outcome in a corresponding hierarchy of nested outcomes—then individual contributions become discernible.

This scalability now gives us the resources to consider Anne as a subordinate. The outcome to which Anne makes a difference is that Collin is shot on her order. If she were to give this order, Collin would be shot. If she were not to give this order, Collin might still be shot, but not on her order. If she were not to give this order, then Collin would not be shot on her order. That Collin is shot on her order (rather than on someone else’s)—this is the outcome to which Anne makes a difference.

Anne does not make a difference to the outcome to which Bert makes a difference, namely, that Collin is shot by Bert. This is because, by assumption, if Anne were to give the order to shoot Collin, then someone would shoot Collin, but it is not the case that Bert follows Anne’s order in all nearby possible worlds.Footnote 48 The outcome that Collin is shot by Bert is something that Anne can prevent (the negative conditional is true) but not something she can implement (the positive conditional is false).Footnote 49

One might object that this entails the implausible view that, because she does not make a difference to this outcome, Anne is not responsible for the outcome that Collin is shot by Bert. Suppose (a) that Anne knows that Bert is going to carry out her order, or only (b) that she knows that he is likely to carry out the order. Either way, it seems that, intuitively, when she gives the order to shoot Collin, she would be responsible for the outcome that Collin is shot by Bert—but the account here denies this.Footnote 50

Before considering this objection, note that in one version, (a), the imagined case seems inconsistent. By assumption, Anne does not make a difference to the outcome that Collin is shot by Bert.Footnote 51 Yet, or so goes the case, Anne knows that Bert is going to be the one who shoots. This is inconsistent, insofar as knowledge is factive but Bert is not necessarily going to be the one who shoots. Given only that someone is going to shoot, but that this might not be Bert, Anne might give the order in the (mistaken) belief that Bert is going to shoot. Admittedly, Anne’s responsibility might change between having a mistaken belief (that Bert will shoot) instead of a correct belief (that someone will shoot), but not in a way inconsistent with the account here.

To the other version of the objection, (b), I see two responses. First, the intuitive-seeming judgment that Anne is responsible for the outcome that Collin is shot by Bert might be denied. For example, internalists about responsibility contend that agents are responsible only for their attitudes or quality of their will (e.g. Scanlon, 2015, 96)—if they are responsible for anything at all. Zimmerman (2002, 568 emphasis in original) argues “whether there is something for which one is responsible is immaterial; all that matters, fundamentally, is whether one is responsible.” Notably, internalists arrive at this view after reflecting on cases, just like ours, about control, luck, or “tracing” consequences back to the agent (e.g. Zimmerman, 2002; Khoury, 2012; 2018). Their view is consistent with my account. There is a difference between the reasons for and the objects of someone’s responsibility. My account concerns only the grounds of someone’s responsibility. These grounds explain why someone is responsible (they are reasons), which does not entail that someone is responsible for these grounds (they are not the objects).

Second, the response that I favor: We could accommodate this intuitive judgment (that Anne is responsible for the outcome that Collin is shot by Bert) to some degree by “redirecting” it without changes to the account. Per my account, Anne does not make a difference to Collin being shot by Bert, but she makes a difference to an outcome in which it is highly likely that Collin is shot by Bert.Footnote 52 What the intuitive judgment picks up on in saying that “Anne is responsible for the outcome that Collin is shot by Bert”, that is, what makes this judgment look plausible, is in fact just that Anne is responsible for the outcome that it is highly likely that Collin is shot by Bert. That is, the objection’s judgment rests on claims about likely consequences or about normative facts (e.g. the wrongness of Anne’s action), not on a judgment about ontology and metaphysics that discriminates different entities for which Anne’s is responsible. In this sense, the account here can accommodate a claim in the vicinity of the initial intuitive judgment of the objection.

To take stock: On the one hand, we have the two conditionals that define when individuals make a difference to an outcome. On the other hand, I distinguished a fine-grained outcome, that Collin is shot by Bert, and a more coarse-grained outcome that Collin is shot on Anne’s orders. Together, this explains how both Anne and Bert are each an agent of some outcome that entails Collin’s death. Bert makes a difference to the more fine-grained outcome, which thereby (partially) grounds his responsibility. Likewise, Anne, considered as a subordinate, makes a difference to the outcome that Collin is shot on her order (as opposed to the order of Ashley, Anne’s backup) and this hence (partially) grounds Anne’s responsibility.

The account may appear contrived with descriptions such as “the outcome that Collin is shot by Bert.” But it captures a very natural idea: Hierarchical groups constrain and enable individuals at the same time. Bert can decide not to shoot, but whether Collin is shot is not up to him. Anne can choose not to give the order, but whether such an order is given is not up to her. Subordinates can choose their role in how a directive plays out—but play out it will. They act within a sphere of possibility that is circumscribed from above. When subordinates comply, what they bring about typically entails the objective of the directive they received, even if whether this objective is achieved is not up to them. These intuitive ideas are formalized by a simple set-theoretic construction of nested outcomes. The canonical names or descriptions of these outcomes might appear contrived or overwrought, but the larger ideas behind them should be rather clear and intuitive.Footnote 53

4.3 Increasing responsibility

Michael Walzer discusses increasing responsibility in a way that resonates with these ideas. Walzer observes that “we regard soldiers under orders as men whose acts are not entirely their own and whose liability for what they do is somehow diminished” (1977, 309). Walzer suggests that, compared to their superiors, soldiers lack agency. To explain increasing responsibility, it seems natural to explore this further: How should we understand that “what [soldiers] do is somehow diminished” and that their acts are “not entirely their own”?

I hypothesize that when comparing superiors and subordinates, a change in responsibility can be explained, at least in part, by a respective change in agency. When we assume that moral responsibility is not a brute fact but that facts about responsibility are grounded in other facts, then there must be something about these grounding facts that explains increasing responsibility, that is, why responsibility increases with hierarchy: Moral responsibility is partially grounded in agency. If agency increased with hierarchy, then it could explain why responsibility increases with hierarchy. By discerning individual contributions and comparing them to another, we can see that agency increases with hierarchy and that thereby responsibility may increase with hierarchy.Footnote 54

Before attempting to explain increasing responsibility, the concept of “degrees of responsibility” should be cleared up (cf. Braham and Hees 2009, 325). First, a note on terminology. What I say about “degrees” can be expressed similarly in terms of “worse actions.” More substantively, I suggest representing degrees of responsibility as a function of those facts that ground responsibility. Of those facts that ground responsibility, some concern agency, some concern what the agent believes or knows, and others concern what the agent intends—relating to the agential condition, the epistemic condition, and the agent’s intentions or quality of will.Footnote 55 Degrees of responsibility reflect this metaphysical structure of responsibility. The function that represents degrees of responsibility should represent in its components these conditions of responsibility. An agent’s degree of responsibility for an outcome is a function of the agent’s contribution to this outcome, the agent’s beliefs about the consequences, and the agent’s intentions. But how can responsibility be represented as a graded concept permitting of degrees at all?

Responsibility can be graded whenever it is implicitly comparative.Footnote 56 Degrees of responsibility are constructed by comparing one agent’s responsibility for a fine-grained outcome with another agent’s responsibility for a coarse-grained outcome. First, degrees of agency are normed to 1, or “full agency,” for some agent and an outcome to which this agent makes a difference. Call this the index outcome and index agent respectively. This index agent can be an idealized or hypothetical agent. The index agent makes a difference, or controls, whether or not the index outcome occurs. The index agent is furthermore supposed to have all relevant information about the situation (for simplicity, we set aside the intentional condition). As a matter of stipulation, the index agent—with full control and full information—has full responsibility for this outcome. With this idealization, the index agent’s degree of responsibility with respect to this outcome is normed to 1.

Second, similarly to responsibility simpliciter, the degree to which one is responsible depends on the degree to which the grounding facts are in place. One is responsible for an outcome to the extent that one has agency over it, one foresaw it, and intended it. Whenever one of the components of degrees of responsibility decreases, relative to the index agent, an agent is responsible to a lesser degree. Focusing on agency only, I assume that degrees of responsibility are monotonically decreasing in agency.Footnote 57 Suppose another agent foresaw the same index outcome but lacked full agency over it. That is, this other agent had the same information as the index agent but made a difference only to an outcome nested in the index outcome. In this case she would not have full responsibility. A decrease in the control condition (agency only over a nested outcome), all other things being equal, leads to a decrease in the degree to which she is responsible compared to the index agent with full agency and full information. Any agent who has less than full agency and less than full information with respect to this outcome has a degree of responsibility less than 1. In technical terms, the function representing degrees of responsibility depends monotonically on its components of agency and information. Inversely, responsibility increases with hierarchy.

These constructions allow only for very limited comparisons. Comparisons are possible only between a superior and subordinates.Footnote 58 Or, similarly, between the index agent and the agents who make a difference to outcomes nested within the index outcome. The constructions of degrees of responsibility exploit the idea that agents of fine-grained outcomes have in one sense less control than agents of more coarse-grained outcomes.Footnote 59 The agential component of this function is then defined only on the outcomes nested within this more coarse-grained outcome. The account does not define or speak to comparisons between agents whose outcomes are not nested.

Another limitation is that, besides agency and information, all other grounds of responsibility are set aside. How exactly information and the other grounds are measured and how all grounds interact as components to compose an overall measure of degrees of responsibility cannot be answered here. Other explanations of why responsibility increases with hierarchy are not ruled out. Thus, the phenomenon is only that responsibility sometimes increases with hierarchy; I do not claim that responsibility always increases. In fact, we can think of situations in which responsibility decreases with hierarchy. In some groups, superiors might be responsible to a lesser degree than their subordinates.Footnote 60 Hence, it is not the case that agents who make a difference to a nested outcome—such as subordinates—always have less responsibility than their superiors. Neither is it the case that superiors could generally reduce their responsibility by giving more specific orders (and thus make a difference to a more fine-grained outcome). And in some groups no one may have full responsibility. I discuss some of these and other cases before concluding.

We can now apply these technical constructions to illustrate increasing responsibility in hierarchical groups. Consider again the case of Anne and Bert who are both involved in bringing about Collin’s death. The coarse-grained index outcome, for comparing Anne and Bert, is Collin’s death due to Anne’s orders. Anne, as the index agent, counts as having “full agency” over this outcome in this comparison. Lesser degrees of agency are assigned to the agents of the more fine-grained, nested outcomes. Specifically, Bert, the agent of the nested outcome (that Collin is shot by Bert), has only partial agency with respect to the index outcome (that Collin’s is shot on Anne’s orders).Footnote 61 Hence, Anne’s responsibility is greater than Bert.

These two ideas—the idea of degrees of agency (as comparing agency between two outcomes, whereas one is nested within the other) and that of degrees of responsibility (defined as a function that is monotonically increasing in agency)—together explain how responsibility increases with hierarchy.Footnote 62 It follows from these constructions that when other conditions of responsibility are set aside, then the degree of responsibility increases as the degree of agency increases. And since the degree of agency increases with hierarchy, responsibility may increase with hierarchy.

The construction on how responsibility increases with agency can moreover be extended to a case like the following.Footnote 63 Assume, again, our model case of Anne and her soldiers; but suppose now that two types of guns are available to Anne’s soldiers, “normal” guns and “brutal” guns. Brutal guns inflict greater pain and a slower death. Suppose now that another of Anne’s subordinates, Bill, can reliably get Bert to pick a brutal gun rather than a normal gun.Footnote 64 Say, Bill is always in the armory at the same time and chooses to stand in the way of Bert getting to the normal guns. In other words, Bill makes a difference to whether Collin is killed by Bert with a brutal gun (as opposed to a normal gun). Bert knows that there are two types of guns and what they are and chooses to not go around Bill to get to a normal gun. I take it that the pre-theoretic judgment is that Bill is not responsible; and if he is at all responsible, then he is less responsible than Bert (after all, it is Bert who shoots Collin).

The present account can make good sense of this case. First, the account can explain why Bill might be responsible (if he makes a difference to a relevant outcome) but the account does not entail that Bill is responsible. Agency is only a partial ground but not a sufficient condition, let alone a full explanation, for someone’s responsibility. Second, the account entails only the claim that, if Bill is responsible at all (assuming he and Bert have the same information), then Bill is responsible to a lesser degree than Bert. The account identifies in what sense Bill has less agency than Bert—he makes a difference to a more fine-grained outcome (which gun Bert uses)—which hence grounds his lesser responsibility. The account thus extends to some further and interesting cases.

5 Observations, limitations, and extensions

So far, I have concentrated on the case of Anne, Bert, and other soldiers in Anne’s team. I have taken this case as a model under the assumption that a theory developed for this model can be extended to more complex cases. More complex cases will involve groups with more than two levels, any number of subordinates for a given superior, and the possibility to resist directives. More complex cases will also have groups that combine vertical and horizontal elements. A corporation, for example, is headed by a board of directors instead of having one individual at the top. Such a board is a horizontal group. Even a group agent could occupy any node in the hierarchy tree. In contrast, the group in our model case is strictly hierarchical, that is, the authority relation that represents the group’s structure relates only individuals. Only individuals occupy the nodes in the hierarchy tree. One individual is at the top and she is connected to all other group members individually via a path in the authority relation.

The simplifications of the model case should not affect the generality of the account presented here. They do not in principle stand in the way of extending this account to more complex cases. In considering Anne in her role as a subordinate, I already discussed how the proposal can scale to more levels. Before closing, to both to clarify the account and to connect it to related topics, I want to illustrate some other ways in which this theory of agency in hierarchical groups may extend to more complex cases and related discussions in the literature. I discuss three issues: ignorance, individual responsibility, and collective responsibility.

5.1 Ignorance and plausible deniability

Responsibility does not always increase with hierarchy. This is because responsibility is only partially grounded in agency and hence agency is by itself not sufficient for moral responsibility. All conditions of responsibility matter. Given how action, knowledge, and intent come together, one may argue, that responsibility sometimes decreases with hierarchy. Some groups shape their internal dissemination of information strategically to absolve superiors of their moral responsibility. Subordinates may deliberately withhold information from superiors knowing that if their superiors were to have this information, the superiors would be responsible. So, subordinates may arrange things hoping that their superiors, despite their agency but because of their ignorance, might not be responsible, or cannot be held responsible.Footnote 65 This is sometimes called plausible deniability. The idea is, of course, that pleading ignorance avoids responsibility. It is doubtful that this is the case (cf. Kutz, 2000, 157).

In other cases, responsibility may decrease with hierarchy because disseminating relevant information to the top is not feasible. Consider a military group. Soldiers in the field often know better than their commanders what is going on. Yet, given the conditions of battle, this information cannot travel upwards. In result, the group is control-heavy at the top but information-heavy at the bottom. In technical terms, the degree of information is inversely related to the degree of agency. Although agency increases with hierarchy, information may decrease. Crucially, in contrast to plausible deniability, there is no intention here to avoid sending information up the hierarchy. And hence, at least in some cases, finding anyone who is fully morally responsible in such a group might be hard. Moral responsibility requires agency and information to come together in some sense. Although the individual contributions to the collective outcome may be discernible, if agency and information do not sufficiently line up, then agents might escape responsibility, or so one may argue.

These suggestions that responsibility might decrease with hierarchy should not hide the fact that information, hierarchies, and responsibility interact in complex ways. Whether and when ignorance diminishes responsibility is not relevant for the account presented here. The account can accommodate judgments either way. Where information diminishes with hierarchy, thinking of degrees of responsibility as this account suggests—as a function that has the grounds of responsibility as components—can be useful and extended to investigations into the epistemic condition of responsibility in hierarchical groups. At any rate, even if responsibility decreases with ignorance and hierarchy, ignorant superiors will escape responsibility of only one kind (the one discussed here). They might still need to take responsibility, be answerable, or perhaps can still be held responsible (depending on the theory of responsibility).

5.2 Individual responsibility and command responsibility

My account suggests that in hierarchical groups individuals are responsible. In a strictly hierarchical group, we can discern the individual contributions to some overall outcome. Even if a subordinate cannot make a difference to a coarse-grained outcome, she, via a fine-grained outcome, still makes a difference as to how this outcome comes about. Subordinates are agents of nested outcomes. Given that the individuals have the relevant information, they can be individually responsible in virtue of their individual contributions. In a strictly hierarchical group, for each individual there is an outcome to which that individual makes a difference. Moreover, in a strictly hierarchical group, there are only individuals making a difference to outcomes. I do not deny that also hierarchical groups might have corporate responsibility.Footnote 66 Rather, this corporate responsibility need not be a “remainder of responsibility” (Dempsey, 2013, 343), and it does not result from a “deficit in the accounting books” (Pettit, 2007, 194).Footnote 67

An important application for an account of individual responsibility in hierarchical groups is command responsibility. “Command responsibility” names a family of doctrines in criminal law based on which superiors are held responsible for actions performed on their command. The development of such doctrines goes back to the conviction of the Japanese general Tomoyuki Yamashita for the Manila massacre in 1946 (Walzer, 1977, Chap. 19; Smidt, 2000; Danner and Martinez 2005). Subsequent to the Second World War, several different doctrines of command responsibility have been developed. German criminal law, for example, developed the doctrine of indirect perpetration (Roxin, 1963, 2011; Weigend, 2011).

This account of agency in hierarchical groups relates to doctrines of command responsibility in two ways. First, by explaining superiors’ responsibility, this account of agency in hierarchal groups vindicates an idea close to the basic tenet of command responsibility.Footnote 68 Commanders are related to the outcome for which they are responsible in a way that grounds their responsibility for these outcomes. Second, the account also highlights the limits of commanders’ responsibility. Although commanders may make the difference with respect to a coarse-grained outcome, they still lack the ability to fine-tune (which lies with their soldiers). In other words, commanders lack the implementation aspect of agency. Moreover, commanders may also be lacking (the possibility of) information about the consequences of their order. This kind of ignorance may also affect their responsibility. When responsibility is seen as a function of agency and information, then commanders may be long on agency (at least as prevention, if not as implementation) but short on information. Assuming the validity of plausible deniability (that ignorance undermines responsibility), this may pose a challenge to founding the legal doctrine of command responsibility on moral responsibility.

Finally, reflecting on doctrines of command responsibility brings out an important limitation of the account of hierarchical groups presented here. The present account is concerned only with agency within a hierarchical structure, not with agency over this structure. Superiors are not seen as being the ones who set up the organization and design the procedures by which it operates. The power structure is taken as given. Yet power over an organization is a crucial aspect of command responsibility. This is an aspect on which my account is silent and that needs to be developed another day.

5.3 Mutiny as a collective action

It is now time to relax one assumption I made earlier about the model case. Let us assume a mutiny is possible. In contrast to my earlier assumption that it is certain that Collin will be shot by someone when Anne gives the order, let us say that Collin being shot is only overwhelmingly likely. There is also the small possibility that no one will shoot. Collin might survive. But Collin would survive only when each soldier in the team refused to follow Anne’s order. Note how the situation resembles that of a collective action: Suppose five of us need to rescue a child drowning at the beach and all five of us are needed to get it done. We need to get our act together. Individually none of us can ensure that the child is rescued. If we fail to get our act together, then we might be individually responsible for not taking the appropriate steps towards a collective action, and collectively we might be responsible for not rescuing the child (Collins, 2012). We can now see how a similar collective action problem befalls the team of soldiers.

What are soldiers in our model case responsible for? A mutiny is a collective action. Because one person is enough to frustrate the effort to resist Anne’s order, each soldier would have to resist her order. Hence, individually each soldier might be responsible for not taking appropriate steps towards a collective resistance, and collectively the soldiers might be responsible for the omission of not resisting Anne’s order together (this depends on a theory of responsibility in horizontal groups).

Throughout this paper I have assumed a kind of local determinism according to which Collin is shot when Anne directs he be shot, and according to which a bullet hits Collin fatally when Bert pulls the trigger. But in reality, luck is involved. In reality, actions are risky. Technically, we can represent risk by thinking of probabilistic outcomes. The outcome that Collin is shot, to which Anne makes a difference, includes not only worlds in which Collin is shot, but also some few worlds in which there is a mutiny. Likewise, the outcome that Collin is shot by Bert includes also some few worlds in which Bert misses his target. Of course, more would have to be said on how my account extends to such probabilistic outcomes.

6 Conclusion

Many groups—banks, ministries, corporations, or military organizations—are hierarchical groups structured by authority. Who is responsible for the conduct of such a group?

Responsibility has many grounds. I concentrated on the partial ground of control, causation, or agency. Agency identifies the things in virtue of which an individual may be responsible. Agency explains why we are responsible for our own actions but usually not for those of others. A theory of agency in hierarchical groups is an important building block of a wider theory of responsibility in hierarchical groups. The central challenge to theories of responsibility in collective contexts is to discern who brought about what and who, accordingly, can be held responsible for what.

In this paper, I have done three things. First, I contrasted hierarchical groups to flat groups by identifying three characteristics of hierarchical groups: asymmetry, control, and redundancy. Second, I described three phenomena that any account of hierarchical groups needs to explain: superiors’ responsibility, subordinates’ responsibility, and increasing responsibility. Third, I put forward a theory of agency in hierarchical groups that consists of two parts. The first part is an agency relation that relates individuals to outcomes. Individuals stand in this relation when something is up to them, when they make a difference: when they can both robustly bring about and prevent an outcome. In spelling this out, I have relied on an existing account of difference-making, due to List and Menzies (2009). The second part is a proposal about the individuation of outcomes. I suggested distinguishing outcomes contrastively. Outcomes can be nested in other outcomes and a superior can make a difference to a coarse-grained outcome while subordinates make a difference to nested, fine-grained outcomes. These two parts of the theory explain the first two phenomena, superiors’ responsibility and subordinates’ responsibility. The third phenomenon, increasing responsibility, can be explained by constructing a comparative measure of degrees of responsibility that is increasing in agency. Responsibility may increase with agency, setting other things aside, because agency increases with hierarchy.

More work is needed to couch this view within existing theories. Foundations need to be explored to theories below. How does this theory of agency relate to the metaphysics of causation and, more broadly, to the philosophy of action? Lines must be drawn to theories above. Would such a theory of responsibility in hierarchical groups buttress or undermine existing doctrines in criminal law? Finally, connections need to be established left and right. How do the intentional and the epistemic condition of responsibility interact with the agency condition? The unification that I attempted for responsibility in hierarchical groups is only one colorful piece in the large mosaic of theories.