1 Introduction

Reliabilism is motivated by a compelling thought: we care about the reliability of the sources of our beliefs. After all, epistemic norms are plausibly truth-oriented in some way or another, and so how frequently our belief-forming methods deliver the truth is of paramount importance. This intuitive thought has yielded a variety of reliabilist theories which purport to solve many epistemological problems. However, reliabilism faces a number of significant difficulties, as has been well-recognized for decades. In order to solve many of these difficulties, I will propose a new reliabilist theory of justification.

My new theory adds a novel condition for justification. It is inspired by the same intuitive notion just mentioned: that we care about how we form beliefs. It is a kind of coherence condition, but the kind of coherence I am after is distinct from previous proposals in that it focuses on the coherence of belief sources or methods, rather than on sets of beliefs. As I will argue, this new method coherence condition solves a number of extant problems for reliabilism. Most importantly, it provides a solution to epistemic circularity and bootstrapping objections. Although I have a favored version of this new theory of justification, what I will provide is really a schema for creating new reliabilist theories incorporating this novel condition. .

2 Reliabilism and Epistemic Circularity

2.1 Reliabilism and Reliabilisms

Reliabilism seeks to explain the justification of a belief in terms of that belief’s history. To paraphrase Alvin Goldman’s classic “process reliabilist” account, a belief is justified iff it is caused by a reliable belief-forming process (1979). This is an externalist theory, requiring only that the subject actually use a reliable method. It does not require that the subject knows, or can offer an argument to justify, that the method is reliable. Nor does it require the subject to have evidence for what she believes (though many reliable methods will utilize such evidence).Footnote 1

There have been a variety of different reliabilist theories, besides Goldman’s influential version.Footnote 2 These views differ regarding how they understand belief-formation, and subsequently in what the appropriate target is for evaluation of reliability. Thus, what distinguishes such views is their characterization of the way beliefs are formed. For instance, Goldman focuses on cognitive processes, while Ernest Sosa’s virtue reliabilist view focuses on virtues or competences, understood as dispositions of the subject (2007, 2009).Footnote 3

Reliabilism provides an attractive account of justification. It is intuitively well-motivated, parsimonious, and allows for solutions to numerous problems in epistemology. It solves the epistemic regress problem (i.e., the Agrippan trilemma), as reliabilist justification for a belief need make no appeal to other beliefs.Footnote 4 Moreover, it gives us a principled way of articulating a Moorean response to the skeptic.Footnote 5 Reliabilism is also consonant with both scientific and everyday practice. People are concerned with reliability of witness testimony, and in general with the reliability of their sources of belief. Scientists are concerned with the reliability of tests and experimental methods.

Despite these advantages, reliabilism is faced with a slew of difficult problems and objections. The new coherence condition I propose here will solve some of these problems. This condition is applicable to any view of reliabilism, and so I will largely attempt to remain neutral on the appropriate characterization of belief formation, and will speak neutrally in terms of belief-forming methods or sources.

The notion of “justification” at issue here is knowledge-level justification, sometimes called “warrant.” It is the kind of justification relevant to knowledge, though for Gettier reasons it is not all that distinguishes true belief from knowledge.Footnote 6

2.2 Two Kinds of Epistemic Circularity

The first problems for reliabilism to concern us involve epistemic circularity. There are two kinds of epistemic circularity objections to reliabilism. These two types are not always distinguished, and it is true they are related. However, many solutions offered to one do not serve as solutions to the other. My method coherence condition is motivated in large part as an attempt to solve both of these circularity worries.

The first epistemic circularity problem was pressed forcefully by Fumerton (1995).Footnote 7 I will call this direct circularity, as it involves direct appeal to a method in justifying itself. It arises from the question of how we can justify a higher-order belief that a particular method is reliable. Reliabilism does not require that a subject, in order for her belief to be justified, know whether a method is reliable. Nor does she need to provide a reason for treating it as reliable. Thus, the theory seems to allow for a facile, circular justification of a method via application to itself. Compatible with reliabilist justification, the subject can form a belief that her method is reliable by using that very method. For instance, a subject could form the belief that a particular visual method is reliable by the use of this very visual method. On a reliabilist account, this higher-order belief would be justified as long as this visual doxastic method is actually reliable. Yet it seems viciously circular to suggest that we can justify the reliability of a particular method by appealing to that same method. “You cannot use perception to justify the reliability of perception!” (Fumerton 1995, p. 177). The same point applies to induction. What reason do we have to think that past experience is a guide for future experience? We have only the reliability of inductive inference, but this reliability is exactly what is at issue. Since this procedure seems much like begging the question, it seems we are engaging in a fallacious procedure when we use a particular method to justify its own reliability.

Furthermore, Fumerton points out, reliabilism not only allows such a procedure, it seems that the reliabilist must permit it use when inquiring into the reliability of a method. “There is no conceptual basis for the reliabilist to get cold feet when epistemological questions are raised to the next level up. Either reliability alone is sufficient or it is not” (1995, p. 178). If induction really is reliable, then according to reliabilism there is no reason why it should not be utilized to form a justified belief about the reliability of induction. This, of course, is meant to sound absurd. The suggestion is we are really no closer to understanding justification after the reliabilist account. Fumerton claims “there is no philosophically interesting concept of justification or knowledge that would allow us to use a kind of reasoning to justify the legitimacy of using that reasoning” (Fumerton 1995, 178). Epistemic circularity is vicious, and this casts doubt on the ability of reliabilism to explain justification.

The purported viciousness of direct circularity is well illustrated by the example of the person who gazes into a crystal ball to predict the future (Sosa 2007). Let us agree that in our world, at least, crystal gazing is not a reliable method for forming beliefs. So, of course, reliabilism does not suffer from the difficulty of countenancing justified crystal gazing. However, the crystal gazer can appeal to reasoning that is identical to the kind of circular reasoning that Fumerton has argued is allowed by reliabilism. The gazer can form the belief that crystal gazing is reliable by gazing into his crystal. To put some flesh on the case:

Crystal Ball Gazer Case Al is a fortune teller, and gazes into his crystal ball to form beliefs about the future. One day, Larry challenges Al on his justification for this. Al peers into his crystal ball, and the ball tells him that “gazing into a crystal ball is a reliable way to form beliefs.” And on this basis he forms the belief that crystal ball gazing is reliable. Al tells Larry “As long as my crystal ball is reliable, then my belief in its reliability is justified. And my crystal ball is reliable, it just told me so!”

Al uses the same kind of circular reasoning that reliabilism must allow. Per reliabilism, the reliable perceiver can, merely by appeal to perception, justify her belief in the reliability of perception. Similarly, Al the gazer can, merely by (direct) appeal to crystal ball gazing, “justify” his belief that gazing is reliable. And this similarity of reasoning, (especially the similarity from the inside) looks bad for reliabilism.

A second kind of circularity worry, known as the “bootstrapping” or “easy knowledge” problem, was first leveled by Vogel (2000) and Stewart Cohen (2002). Vogel articulates the bootstrapping problem with what he calls the “Gas Gauge” example (Vogel 2000, p. 612).Footnote 8 In its mature form (modified from Vogel 2008, p. 518):

Gas Gauge Case Roxanne’s car has a reliable gas gauge. She has never investigated the gauge or others like it; she has no information whatsoever on the subject. Rather, Roxanne automatically forms beliefs about the level of gas in the car’s tank simply by consulting the gauge. For example, if the gauge reads “F” she immediately and directly forms the belief that the car’s tank is full. Given that the gauge is reliable, it seems clear that Roxanne’s belief that the car’s tank is full is formed by a reliable process. Now, Roxanne can also observe what the state of the gauge itself is, if she chooses to. Roxanne notes that the needle reads “F” at the time when she believes, by reading the gauge, that the tank is full. Roxanne conjoins her belief that the gauge reads “F” with her belief that the tank is full, and deduces that the gauge reads accurately on this occasion. We can suppose that Roxanne repeats this strange procedure a good number of times, accumulating beliefs that the gauge reads accurately at various times. Roxanne then concludes by induction that the gauge is accurate in general, that is, that the gauge is reliable.

In the example, Roxanne forms beliefs by reliable methods (the gauge, deduction and induction). The gauge is reliable ex hypothesi, so her beliefs in the tank level are justified, per reliabilism. Moreover, given the background assumptions of the story, it is a logical consequence of the statements that “the gauge reads ‘F”’ and “the tank is full,” that “the gauge is reading accurately.” Thus, Roxanne’s belief at each time in the accuracy of the gauge is gained by competent deduction. Furthermore, if Roxanne repeats this procedure with the same results, she can make an inductive inference that on many occasions her fuel gauge has been accurate, and therefore this gauge is a reliable one. Thus, all Roxanne’s methods in this procedure are reliable: the gas gauge is reliable by stipulation, and deduction and induction are commonly accepted as reliable. According to the reliabilist, Vogel thinks, Roxanne must now have a justified belief that the gauge is reliable, without having done anything to check whether it is reliable beyond having blind faith. But this is clearly problematic; this “bootstrapping” procedure is reliable but seems illegitimate. The only way to deny Roxanne justification is to deny that she knows that the tank is full in the first place. The reliabilist cannot do this, however, without giving up the central tenet of reliabilism: that a belief is justified iff it is formed by a reliable method.

Direct circularity and bootstrapping are not often distinguished.Footnote 9 They are clearly related: each involves the use of a method to determine it’s own reliability. However, the two problems are distinct. Direct circularity involves undue trust of a method, based entirely and directly on that method itself. Bootstrapping, on the other hand, requires more than just the method in question in order for the problem to arise: Roxanne appeals to deduction, induction, and memory, in addition to her gas gauge, in order to bootstrap to the reliability of the gauge. The bootstrapping problem is also easily generalized to any epistemological theory which admits of basic beliefs (Cohen 2002). It is less clear how many theories besides reliabilism are subject to the direct circularity worry.

There is a significant literature regarding epistemic circularity, primarily focused on finding a solution to the bootstrapping problem. Many of the proposed solutions will not work as a response to the direct circularity problem.Footnote 10 Moreover, each proposed solution has been met with objections and difficulties even in attempting to solve the bootstrapping problem.Footnote 11 In light of these difficulties, some have even argued that the reliabilist should accept circularity as unproblematic, on pain of skepticism (e.g., Van Cleve 2003; Bergmann 2004). I find this an unwelcome result.

In what follows, I argue that reliabilist views incorporating a method coherence condition can deal with both epistemic circularity objections. Method coherence blocks bootstrapping of all kinds, and provides the reliabilist with a well-motivated response to direct circularity.

3 Method Coherence

One attractive avenue for a rescue of reliabilism from circularity and insufficiency objections is by appeal to coherence. After all, coherentism about justification is an attempt to redeem a certain kind of circularity in response to the epistemic regress problem (BonJour 1985). Coherence is generally understood as a property of sets of beliefs, a property a set has when it is self-supporting in some sense. It has seemed plausible to many that certain sets of beliefs can be justified simply by appeal to the support the members offer each other, even if this is in some sense circular.

However, coherence is a disputed concept. Some theorists treat it as a kind of robust connection between consistent sets of beliefs (cf. BonJour 1985; Thagard 2000), while others have understood it as a relation of explanation (cf. Elgin 2005; Poston 2014), while still others understand it in terms of mutual probabilistic support (cf. Lewis 1946; Olsson 2005; Fitelson 2003). It is difficult to define, and when definitions are given, it becomes unclear what the relationship is between coherence and other epistemic values (Olsson 2014). In particular, whether coherence is truth-conducive has proved controversial (Klein and Warfield 1994; Olsson 2014; Olsson and Schubert 2007). Nonetheless, I think that appeal to coherence can save reliabilism from many of the difficulties raised above. However, the kind of coherence I will appeal to is distinct from that of traditional coherentist views: it is a coherence of belief-forming methods, rather than of beliefs.Footnote 12

Why are we so certain that crystal gazing is not a reliable belief forming method? Why is it effective as an example of an absurd method? I would like to suggest that we could come to a more satisfying reliabilist theory of justification by attending to the “common sense” answers to these questions.

Why are we certain that crystal ball gazing is unreliable? Because gazing does not work. The crystal ball does not give us true predictions about the future in a reliable manner. How do we know it does not work? When we attempt to test the predictions offered us by the gazer, we find that they do not correspond to what we experience. Since we form beliefs about our experiences using our other methods, what this means is that the predictions offered by the crystal gazer do not cohere with beliefs we form using other methods like vision or hearing. Thus, the primary reason we are certain that crystal gazing is not a reliable belief-forming method is that its predictions are incoherent with the deliverances of our other methods.

When I am told by the crystal gazer that I will meet a beautiful stranger this week, and no such stranger appears, then the crystal gazer is “proven wrong.” To put it in the terms of the current discussion: the belief formed using crystal gazing, “I will meet a beautiful stranger this week,” is not coherent with the beliefs I form (after the allotted time has passed) with my other methods, such as hearing, vision, and memory, that “I did not meet a beautiful stranger this week.” In this sense, the crystal gazing is incoherent with my other methods. This specific sense of coherence is the one relevant to justification and knowledge. Utilizing this common sense intuition about how we actually identify reliable methods, I would like to suggest an additional condition necessary for a reliabilist theory of justification.

I will argue that adding a requirement of “method coherence” to a reliabilist theory of justification provides a better response to the circularity objections. Below, I will give a more rigorous explanation of the notion of method coherence. To see how it fits into a theory of justification, however, I am first going to provide the schema I promised above, an ecumenical version of a method coherence reliabilism:

MCR :

A belief held by a subject is justified iff it meets the following two conditions:

1.:

Reliability Condition It is formed by a reliable belief-forming method.

2.:

Method Coherence Condition (MCC) This method is sufficiently coherent with the other methods used by that subject.

Thus, to obtain a new theory of justification, simply plug your favored version of reliabilism into the reliability condition, and your favored characterization of belief-forming methods into both conditions. Any reliabilist can appeal to this strategy to build a new theory of justification which solves the difficulties raised above.Footnote 13

Before elaborating on this account, it is worth noting that one way that MCR is schematic is regarding considerations of defeat. Most reliabilists think that reliabilism needs some additional condition about how to handle defeaters in order to deal with troublesome counter-examples, like BonJour’s clairvoyance cases (BonJour80,Goldman15). Goldman initially appealed to a requirement that the subject be sensitive to other belief-forming processes available to her. The MCR schema is compatible with a variety of ways to exclude cases of defeated justification. For our purposes, we can treat the simple version of MCR as giving an account of prima facie justification. We can then leave open what other conditions need to obtain for ultima facie justification.Footnote 14 In what follows, I will largely set considerations of defeat aside.

There are several concepts here that must be explained. The most important are the very idea of methods being coherent, and what is required in order to be “sufficiently coherent.”

One thought behind the MCC is that testing methods against each other is our only real indicator of reliability: how else are we to tell whether some method is reliably giving us true beliefs than by checking at least some of those beliefs against those formed by our other methods? We have no other option in testing our methods than by appeal to other methods. Luckily, at least in the actual world, this is a good way to tell whether a method is reliable.Footnote 15

A first stab at a definition of Method Coherence is as follows:

Method Coherence (MC) :

A belief forming method P is coherent with another method Q insofar as P and Q tend to produce identical or sufficiently mutually supportive beliefs concerning the same times.

The motivation here is to account for the claim argued for above: that the reason crystal gazing is not considered a reliable method is that it does not generate beliefs that cohere with those generated by our other belief-forming methods. Underlying this definition is the notion that we can test the coherence of two methods based on the beliefs they generate regarding some particular time. Here there are three important concepts that need to be explained: “identical”, “sufficiently mutually supportive” and “concerning the same times.”

3.1 Mutual Support

The definition of method coherence utilizes the idea that beliefs can be “identical” and “sufficiently mutually supportive” because appeal to the “coherence” of the beliefs, in the traditional sense (as typified by BonJour), will make the MC condition too strong. Traditional coherence theories apply to a set of beliefs of significant size in order to establish coherence among them. This is because mere consistency of beliefs is not enough; for this kind of broad coherence, there must be a sufficient number of appropriate relationships between beliefs. The kind of test I am proposing involves a set of beliefs too small to establish that kind of coherence.

I take it that it is possible for us to form type-identical beliefs using two different belief-forming methods. The relevant type-identity is identity of content. For example, there are at least two ways I can discover that there is an end table in front of me: I can see the end table, or I can stub my toe on it in the dark. I can form the belief that there is a dog nearby by seeing it or hearing it bark. I can form the belief that there is something rotten in my apartment by smelling it, or by remembering that I forgot to bring the pears with me when I went for a week’s vacation.

Even when the content is not identical, we can sensibly talk about beliefs being mutually supportive. For example, I can form a belief with vision that there is a brick wall in front of me. However, if it is dark, I may only be able to form the belief with my haptic (touch) sense that there is something hard and rough in front of me. These two beliefs are mutually supporting: each is more probable in light of the other. This mutual support is relevant to judging how well the methods that formed them are functioning together.

This understanding of mutual support (and similarity) seems reasonably straightforward and unproblematic to me. However, some readers might still be concerned that this notion of support is too imprecise. In order to assuage such doubts, I will provide one way of making it more precise. One obvious way to elucidate the relevant notion of similarity is by appeal to probabilistic notions of dependence, evidential support, and coherence. This provides a more precise, formalized definition of method coherence, for those skeptical of the more intuitive notion.

The idea of mutual support can be cashed out probabilistically, in terms of evidential support. Two beliefs A and B are similar enough just when they each support each the other to a high enough degree.Footnote 16 The two example beliefs are mutually supporting in this sense: the probability of a brick wall in front of me is higher, given that there is something hard and rough in front of me. And that “there is something hard and rough” is entailed by “there is a brick wall.” Each belief supports the other, and it is plausible in this case that they do so to a high enough degree. Thus the two beliefs are mutually supportive enough, in this sense. This can be generalized: for instance, if we have a set of three beliefs, \(\{A, B, C\} \), sufficient mutual support requires that each one is supported enough by each of the others individually, and by the conjunction of the other two. So, A would need to be supported by B, C, and \(B\wedge C\). And mutatis mutandis for sets with four members, and so on and so forth.

Helpfully, this way of precisifying mutual support turns out to be a simplified version of a probabilistic measure of coherence developed by Branden Fitelson (2003). Fitelson uses a probabilistic definition of evidential support [borrowed from Kemeny and Oppenheim (1952)] to define a measure of coherence over a set of propositions E, C(E). It works by looking at each proposition e which is a member of E and determining how much e is supported by every subset of E. Basically, it looks to see how well supported e is by every combination of the other propositions in E. If each member e is supported by every such combination (subset), E gets a high degree of coherence. Thus, the measure is a helpful way of determining how mutually supporting a set of propositions is.Footnote 17

Fitelson’s measure has a number of nice features. For instance, it turns out that sets of logically equivalent statements get a maximal measure of coherence, \(C(E) = 1\), no matter how small the set (so my independent appeal to identical beliefs above is unnecessary on this precisification). Moreover, whenever a set is composed of sentences all of which are positively probabilistically dependent on each other (and all the conjunctions of the others), it receives a positive value of coherence.

So we can just appeal to Fitelson’s measure in giving a precisified version of our notion of mutual support: a set of beliefs E is sufficiently mutually supportive just when \(C(E)>t\), where t is a contextually determined threshold.Footnote 18

Thus, a more precise account of mutual support is provided by appeal to evidential support, and a probabilistically defined notion of “coherence” for sets of beliefs. However, we need not be committed to this particular precisification. I offer it simply as an illustration of how we might make the notion precise. There are other measures of coherence that we might appeal to, or other formal tools we could employ. Moreover, I think the intuitive, informal characterization is probably enough to support the view. But I am attracted to the precisified view presented.

Method coherence is a matter of degree. This explains my earlier appeal in MCR to methods being “sufficiently coherent.” We considered one way in which method coherence could be degreed: regarding how mutually supportive the produced beliefs are to one another. But we might also ask how many of our methods are producing mutually supportive beliefs. How often does this method produce beliefs that cohere well with our other methods? Although it may be difficult to specify a procedure for determining the exact degree of coherence, the fact that method coherence is graded fits well with the idea that methods will have varying degrees of reliability. Induction has a great deal less conditional reliability than deduction, in the sense of percentage of true beliefs generated from true premises.

The method coherence condition captures our intuitive sense that testing our methods against each other is our only access to their reliability. Since this kind of coherence is proposed (in part) as an indicator of reliability, it only makes sense that the coherence would admit of degree just as reliability does. It may be difficult to nail down marginal cases (Vegas odds in sports predictions, divining rods, etc...), but it is clear that we are often quite easily able to distinguish between methods with a low degree of coherence (crystal gazing), and those with a high degree of coherence with our other methods (vision).

3.2 Method Coherence as a Test

The idea that the beliefs formed should “concern the same time” is also crucial to this conception of method coherence and to the MC condition. We want to compare beliefs about how things stand in the world at a given time, where that time might be the current time, or some future time. This allows for determining how well methods cohere both by making predictions and by more simultaneous belief formation.Footnote 19

The crystal gazing case provides an example of prediction. In that case, the belief formed is a prediction about the future, i.e., a belief concerning a future time. In this case, the beliefs formed will fail to be identical, or sufficiently mutually supportive of, the beliefs formed by vision, hearing, introspection, or reasoning. Other methods that we use, however, form predictive beliefs that are sufficiently mutually supportive to the beliefs that we form when the time comes. For instance, we make predictions using deductive and inductive inferences. Using induction, I predict that the sun will rise tomorrow morning. If I see the sunlight tomorrow, and feel its warmth, then the beliefs formed by these methods will be identical with, or will mutually support, the prediction. Then, my simple enumerative induction method is, in this instance, coherent with my other methods.

Whether methods are coherent depends only on beliefs which are formed concerning the same time. This requirement is helpful in two ways. First, it allows us to treat method coherence as a kind of test, and second, it makes the requirement of method coherence less stringent and more realistically attainable.

Method coherence is not a global coherence, as BonJour would require, or the kind of broad coherence Sosa suggests for reflective knowledge. It is a narrow kind of coherence. Instead of testing the coherence of a belief against an enormous web of beliefs, a subject is instead testing the coherence of her methods by comparing the beliefs delivered by them in specific situations. This corresponds to our common sense procedure of testing a method, as in the crystal gazing case. We are certain that crystal gazing is not a reliable method, because when we test the beliefs it generates by comparing them to beliefs generated by our other methods, it fails the test. The beliefs crystal gazing generates are not coherent with those generated by our other methods. Induction, on the other hand, coheres well with our other methods, because it produces predictions that, when tested in this way, are often enough identical or sufficiently mutually supportive to our other methods’ deliverances.

Method coherence, then, requires being able to pass a certain kind of test. A method is coherent when it can pass such a test, and more coherent the more it tends to pass. Passing the test requires that the method delivers a belief that is identical to or sufficiently mutually supportive with the beliefs delivered at the same time by the subject’s other methods.

Of course, this kind of test is precisely what we use whenever we consider the reliability of some new instrument, exam, or procedure. Anytime we have some new way of collecting data or evidence, we test it by appeal to our existing belief-forming methods. When the first radar speed gun was developed, it was tested for reliability using existing methods, probably using a car on a road with a measured length and a stop watch, as well as using a car’s internal speedometer. Only after a method has shown itself capable of repeatedly passing such tests do we come to trust it. What my account does is extend this notion so that it applies not just to new methods, but to all of our methods. After all, pace Descartes, we do not have some perfectly reliable method we can use to calibrate each of our new methods against as we begin using them. Instead, we “calibrate” our methods by appeal to our other methods.

Method coherence is thus similar to a kind of calibration of our methods, but without any external standard to calibrate with. It is similar to the way a group might calibrate their watches before engaging in some highly time-sensitive activity. Each must be appropriately calibrated with the others, but not necessarily with some standard timepiece (such as the U.S. Atomic Clock). It also echoes the notion of “robustness” appealed to by Wimsatt (2007), in which we are more confident in a theory when there are multiple kinds of tests confirming it. Moreover, the motivations for method coherence are similar to our motivation for thinking that independent sources of evidence are superior, a fact which Bayesian confirmation theory helps explain (Fitelson 2001; Earman 1992).

Method coherence requires passing of a test, where passing means producing sufficiently mutually supportive beliefs. One might wonder, however, which beliefs need to be mutually supportive in order to pass the test. Presumably, during any particular episode of belief formation, an agent may form an enormous number of beliefs. Which beliefs count toward determining method coherence? The notion of a method coherence test, coupled with our idea of mutual support, provides an answer. Specifically, any belief formed during a relevant testing episode which concerns the relevant time will appropriately count toward determining coherence. Whether or not the set of beliefs thus formed do count as coherent then just depends on whether they are adequately mutually supportive. If the relevant beliefs formed for the test (E) are adequately mutually supportive (\(C(E)>t\)), then the test is successful and the methods being tested are adequately coherent. This set of beliefs might be quite large, but this poses no obstacle to evaluating them for mutual supportiveness.Footnote 20

I have been clarifying the central notions employed in the definition of method coherence. We have established that MC requires that a method pass a test, whereby it produces mutually supportive beliefs with other methods, and that it tends to do so sufficiently often. The question now is about how to understand “tends to.” I think the best understanding of “tends” is the following: the method in question tends to pass method coherence testing when it has actually done so frequently enough in the subject’s history. MC thus requires that the subject has actually had her methods pass such tests in the past, and done so frequently enough.Footnote 21 These past tests need not be anything the subject is aware of, nor do they need to be something the subject remembers having done. It is simply required that the subject has done so, and the method has passed frequently enough.

One might worry that this understanding of “tends” makes method coherence too strong a requirement. One might even worry that it seems quite internalist, contra the spirit of reliabilism. However, it is not nearly so strong a requirement as that of accessibilism or mentalism, the two standard forms of internalism (cf. Conee and Feldman 2001). A method coherence test does not have to be done deliberately or consciously: the subject need not have access to the fact that the test has been passed. So accessibilism is not required. Nor does the subject need to remember, or have any current evidence (that supervenes on her current mental state) that their methods have passed coherence tests. Thus mentalism is not required either. Instead, MC only requires that the agent have actually tested her methods.Footnote 22

MC is also not as strong a requirement as traditional coherentism (BonJour 1985), as I pointed out above (Sect. 2.1). It does not require that all of a subject’s beliefs are consistent, interconnected by inference and explanation, are mutually probabilifying, and avoid anomalies. Rather, it merely requires a small subset of beliefs concerning a particular time to be the same or to support one another. As I will argue below, the strength of the requirement is necessary for solving both kinds of epistemic circularity worries.Footnote 23

So although method coherence is clearly a stronger requirement than mere reliability, it is not so strong as internalism or coherentism. It thus avoids raising the bar implausibly high for what kinds of creatures are able to have justified beliefs. Although it is unlikely that most children will be able to articulate anything as sophisticated as “method coherence testing,” children are still capable of passing method coherence tests.

Method coherence is thus an externalist requirement. Satisfying the MCC merely requires that the subject have actually successfully tested her method for coherence in the past. It need not be the case that she knows this, or has any kind of access to or awareness of this fact. As I will argue below, adding this requirement provides an answer for the reliabilist to both kinds of circularity worries, without the move to a genuinely internalist theory that would present a more stringent requirement.Footnote 24

3.3 Method Coherence: Precise Version

The preceding discussion provides for a more precise version of method coherence:

Method Coherence (Precise) :

A belief forming method P is coherent with another method Q insofar as P has (frequently enough) passed method coherence testing with Q, where passing such a test means the two methods produced beliefs concerning the same time which have identical content or have content which is adequately mutually supporting (i.e., “Fitelson-coherent”).

This more precise version is optional, given the way the terms in the initial version have been subsequently defined and explained.

4 Method Coherence: Solutions for Reliabilism

Before moving on to detail how MCR provides solutions for reliabilism, it is worth noting the tight connection between method coherence and reliability. Given an overlap in the content of beliefs produced, the more reliable a set of methods is, the more method coherent it will be. This is most clear at the extreme end: if a set of methods is perfectly reliable, and overlaps completely in the relevant content area, then the method is guaranteed to be perfectly method coherent. This illustrates the connection between the notions. Moreover, I suspect that there will be interesting connections between the three factors (reliability, content, and method coherence). As you vary the degree of reliability of the methods in question, for instance, I expect you will also see a variation in coherence. Exploring these connections in greater detail is an avenue for future research. What is important at this juncture is that, far from being a radical departure from reliabilism, MCR is a natural extension of it. Method coherence is connected with reliability. Moreover, the view continues the emphasis that reliabilism has regarding the importance of how we form beliefs.

The addition of method coherence to reliabilist views provides solutions to both kinds of epistemic circularity. I will address each in turn.

4.1 Direct Epistemic Circularity

A reliabilism incorporating the method coherence condition does not allow a method to be justified merely by appeal to itself, and therefore avoids vicious direct circularity. The MCC requires that a belief about the reliability of a method be formed by a method which has been tested against other methods. So, even if one were to engage in the type of reasoning Fumerton is concerned with, it would not be merely the reliability of the method in question doing the justificatory work. Consider the toy case where a subject is forming a belief about the reliability of visual perception by using the method of visual perception. The visual doxastic method, if it is to satisfy the requirements of MCR, must have previously been tested against other doxastic methods. But then its power to confer justification on beliefs is partially due to its method coherence.

On this account, then, a belief is justified in virtue of the fact that the method by which it was formed has been method coherence tested by the subject using their other methods. So the belief is justified partially in virtue of these other methods, rather than merely by appeal to the method in question. Thus, it is not true that a subject may justify her belief in the reliability of a method merely by appeal to that very method.

Relying on method coherence means that there is still some sense of circularity present. After all, there is no assumption of a Cartesian-style perfectly reliable method by which we can calibrate our other methods. So the methods are merely coherent with one another.

Fumerton objects to the use of a method in justifying itself. Perhaps, one might think, the use of one method to justify another, which would justify another, etc..., would be just as objectionable. Method Coherence, however, involves holistic, non-linear justification: the coherence of the set of methods justifies the use of a particular method. Instead of allowing the direct, linear, and two-step circularity that Fumerton finds objectionable, the MC condition instead widens our scope: the subject is justified in the use of some method by appeal to its coherence with other methods. In other words, beliefs are justified partially in virtue of their method of formation being justified (i.e., successfully tested) by other methods. This seems to be a significant improvement over a standard reliabilist account, which Fumerton rightly points out, must resort to linear epistemic circularity.

Still, Fumerton (or someone with similar commitments) may have a lingering worry about direct circularity. Method coherent reliabilism states that a belief is justified just when it is formed by a method that is both reliable and method coherent. On this account, if some method M meets both conditions, then a belief formed using M about the reliability of M will count as justified. That is, there still appears to be some direct circularity: it seems that a belief in the reliability of a method is justified in virtue of that very same method.

I think this lingering appearance is mistaken. MCR does not allow a belief in the reliability of a method M to be justified merely in virtue of being formed by M. While it is true that the belief will receive justification through being formed by M, the fact that M is capable of conferring justification is due to its coherence with other methods. That is, the belief in method M’s reliability is justified partially in virtue of the subject’s other methods. In order for M to get in the game of conferring justification, it must first pass the MC test. In some sense, then, M itself must first be justified, must first receive support from other methods. M’s ability to justify thus depends on the subject’s other methods. Any justification conferred by M must then depend, at least in part, on those other methods.

Still, a subject employing a method need not be aware of its reliability or of its method coherence. According to MCR, if I appeal to a method of visual perception in judging the reliability of that very method, I need not have any evidence, memory, or awareness of the fact that this method meets the MC condition. I need not remember having tested the method for coherence. From the inside (that is, from the subject’s first-person perspective), it will seem just like the original case of direct circularity.

At this point, however, it seems that the objector is simply demanding some form of accessibilist internalism. That is, the objector wants the subject to always be able to tell that there is no direct circularity. But MCR is an explicitly externalist view. I do not expect that the arguments I have provided here will convince someone to give up internalism. I take it that there are strong reasons to give up internalism, though this is not the place to rehearse them. Instead, I am providing a solution for a purported problem for reliabilism: that the reliabilist allows direct circularity. MCR forbids vicious direct circularity. This means the reliabilist is not forced to give up reliabilism in the face of the objection (though obviously the solution involves a modification of the view).Footnote 25

To be clear, I suspect that this line of reasoning will not persuade the committed internalist, such as Fumerton, to give up their theory in favor of method-coherent reliabilism. Instead, I offer this as a solution for the reliabilist who still feels the pull of Fumerton’s objection. Once we adopt MCR, the objection is defused, for the reliabilist. After we adopt MCR, what remains of the objection just is the internalists’ commitment to accessibilism. It is not my project here to dissuade them from that commitment.Footnote 26

The method coherence condition also has the advantage of denying justification to subjects like the crystal gazer, who are obviously unjustified. As Sosa (2009) points out, the crystal gazer can have an extremely coherent (in the traditional sense) belief system that nevertheless seems wholly divorced from reality. This results from the ability of the gazer to consider only certain inputs, or to entertain only beliefs that fit with his chosen world-view, and thus avoid any possibility of contradiction. In the case of the gazer, this is cashed out as speaking in riddles, or making unspecific predictions, in order to maintain the illusion that the method is reliable and coherent. A view incorporating the MCC as part of the definition of justification will avoid this problem because it requires the testing of predictions in a very specific, concrete way. It requires testing of particular beliefs concerning particular times, by appeal to other belief-forming methods used by the subject. So, it precludes the gazer’s method of avoiding incoherence: when the gazer makes an unspecific prediction, this will be tested by appeal to actual beliefs formed using perception, induction, and other methods. In order for the predictions to be coherent with later beliefs, they would need to be adequately mutually supporting. And the less specific a prediction, the less support it will gain or receive from these other, specific beliefs.Footnote 27

This accounts for what it is about the gazer’s reasoning that is illegitimate in a way that appeals to broad coherence cannot. Thus, we now have a way of faulting the direct circularity illustrated in the crystal gazer case.

4.2 Bootstrapping and Easy Knowledge

A reliabilism that includes the MCC rules out the bootstrapping procedure in the gas gauge case. Roxanne will not be able to “bootstrap” to knowledge about her gauge’s reliability. She will not have knowledge (or be justified in believing) that her tank is full in the first place because her belief fails the MC condition. By stipulations necessary for the case, she has not (consciously or otherwise) tested the gas gauge against her other methods to establish its coherence. While the gas gauge is reliable, and would thus satisfy the reliabilist condition of MCR, Roxanne’s use of it does not satisfy the MC condition.

MCR blocks Roxanne’s illicit bootstrapping procedure from the first step: she does not know that the tank is full, when her gauge reads “full,” because this method has not been tested for coherence with her other methods. Therefore, Roxanne would not have knowledge that “the tank is full” to use as a basis by which to deduce the fact that the gauge reads accurately at any particular time, let alone enough times to underwrite an inductive inference that the gauge is reliable.

Notice that the MC condition does not deny the average motorist knowledge about whether her gauge is reliable. Roxanne has been described as a bad epistemic agent: she makes no attempt to check the gauge’s reliability. I think it is reasonable to suspect that most motorists will check their gauges for reliability, simply through the common everyday activities of driving and filling the car with gas. If the gauge is not reliable, this will become quickly apparent to the driver (e.g., when the car runs out of gas). An attentive driver also notices the number of gallons that she puts into the gas tank when the gauge reads “half,” “quarter,” or “empty,” and checks the owner’s manual of the car for the tank size. These procedures allow a driver to test the coherence of the gas-gauge-based doxastic method with her other relevant methods, and thus establish the necessary level of coherence for the use of the gauge to meet the MCC.

Thus, a reliabilist theory patterned on MCR, incorporating both a reliability requirement and a method coherence requirement, accounts for why bootstrapping is an illegitimate procedure, without denying knowledge to those subjects who intuitively have it. MCR explains the illegitimacy of the first stage of the bootstrapping procedure. However, as we will see in a moment, the method coherence will also block the inductive stage of the bootstrapping procedure, since Roxanne also seems to be using an illicit inductive procedure.

4.3 Slight Bootstrapping

Weisberg (2010) raises an additional problem for solutions to the bootstrapping problem: these solutions fail to block cases of “slight bootstrapping.” This problem illustrates something seemingly illegitimate about subjects who use an inductive procedure like Roxanne’s. These are cases where, for instance, the subject moves from knowledge about reliability to “super-reliability” in a seemingly suspect, bootstrapping way. “Super-reliability” denotes extremely high reliability.

Super-Reliable Gas Gauge Charlie knows that the gauge in his car is reliable, and it is in fact super-reliable. On one occasion the gauge reads F, leading him to believe that the tank is full, which it is. He notes that on this occasion the tank reads F and is full. He then repeats this procedure many times on other occasions, coming to believe that the gauge is not only reliable, but super-reliable (Weisberg (2010), p. 532).

Weisberg’s Super-Reliable case shows that other solutions, including a retreat to internalism, fail to block these cases of bootstrapping. Requiring antecedent knowledge of reliability is not enough to avoid bootstrapping problems.

Weisberg offers a solution to bootstrapping which blocks bootstrapping at the inductive step, including in such slight bootstrapping cases. His solution involves a new condition on inductive methods, which he calls “No Feedback” (533).

In a nutshell, Weisberg’s No Feedback condition outlaws inductive methods with illicit lemmas, that is, lemmas which provide greater support to the conclusion than the base evidence already does.Footnote 28 So any conclusions reached by inductive inference cannot be simply added to the inductive base in order to make a further inference, because this seems to be illicitly adding evidence to one’s inductive base. As a classic example, suppose I have come across 100 ravens and each one has been black. I now have a strong inductive argument for the conclusion that the next raven I see will be black. Suppose I form a belief that the 101st raven is black, on that basis. If I then go on to add this belief to my evidence (my inductive base), I have an even stronger argument that the 102nd raven I encounter will be black, and so come to believe this, and so I will come to believe this and add this premise to my base as well. I can repeat this procedure as many times as I want. This seems clearly illicit; only the ravens I have encountered should count as part of my evidence.

This kind of feedback procedure can lead to absurd results, and this is precisely what we see in the slight bootstrapping case. What No Feedback rules out is taking the belief “The tank is full and the gauge is reliable” as a lemma, and adding it to the inductive base for the final inference to “the gauge is super-reliable.”

One limitation of No Feedback, from the perspective of the reliabilist looking to employ it, is that it does nothing to block Roxanne from having knowledge of the first step of the bootstrapping. That is, Roxanne counts as justified in believing that her tank is full when it reads full. But she is a bad epistemic agent, ex hypothesi. Method coherence, on the other hand, blocks Roxanne from being justified in her belief about the fullness of the tank.Footnote 29

I think that Weisberg is right that No Feedback is a rule that good inductive methods respect. However, MCR will ensure that one is only justified in using methods which respect No Feedback. This is because adding lemmas to one’s evidence before making a further induction will lead to weak, and thereby unreliable, inductive methods. When such feedback-allowing inductive methods are given a method coherence test they will (at least usually) fail, because the methods being used to test them will be reliable. A reliable method and an unreliable one will tend to fail to produce sufficiently mutually supportive beliefs when applied in the same situation regarding the same topic. And so a feedback-allowing method will be method incoherent with reliable methods, at least in the actual world. So, any inductive method that fails to respect No Feedback will fail to be method coherent, because it will allow one to produce beliefs which tend to fail method coherence testing.

Thus, feedback-inclusive inductive methods will qualify for neither the reliability condition, nor the method coherence condition in my justification schema. While I think that Weisberg’s No Feedback principle is correct, it does not provide a full solution to bootstrapping. But in the actual world (and worlds like it), it will be captured by a method coherent reliabilist view.

In virtue of requiring No Feedback, MCR theories will block slight bootstrapping, while also ruling out problematic inductive methods. This, without having to postulate an additional requirement on a theory of justification: methods that are method coherent and reliable will respect No Feedback. MCR will thus deny justification to bad epistemic agents like Roxanne and Charlie.

5 Objections

There are several possible objections to MCR, and to the solutions it provides for the circularity problems, that are worth addressing immediately.

First, the characterization of belief-forming methods here is quite vague, and this may affect whether the type of testing procedure necessary for the MCC is plausible. However, I have allowed the description of methods in this account to be non-specific because I think the MC condition is widely applicable to reliabilist theories regardless of their generality or specificity in characterizing methods. Whether a method is characterized broadly (e.g. “vision” and “induction”) or very narrowly (e.g. “the faculty of recognizing blueness in objects under twilight conditions”), the MCC could be used effectively to block the epistemic circularity objections and garner the other advantages I have suggested.

This worry might be strengthened by pointing to the fact that often beliefs are formed by appeal to multiple perceptual modalities, and in fact people are more reliable and successful at tasks when utilizing multi-sensory integration (Nagel 2014). Thus, it may be difficult to pull apart independent belief-forming methods in order to engage in the relevant testing. However, I think it is plausible that a subject will often be able to individuate between different methods, where we have cases of multiple methods operating together. Moreover, in many of these multi-modal cases, it is very plausible that there is really only one belief-forming method, even when multiple perceptual modalities are involved. So there are some difficult technical issues that arise if we attempt to individuate doxastic methods by appeal to psychology. Ultimately, my view requires a solution to the generality problem, and it is far from being alone in this requirement. But there is no special reason from multimodal perceptual processing to think that we can’t distinguish different belief-forming methods that can be tested against one another.Footnote 30

These considerations lead to a second potential objection: that my reliance on using different methods to test each other requires that there is a solution to the generality problem, since we must be able to distinguish these methods from one another. This seems correct. However, reliabilists are already on the hook for providing a solution to this problem, and I do not have space here to solve this thorny problem. Perhaps it is worth pointing out, however, that recently it has been argued that the generality problem applies to any view of doxastic justification (Comesaña, 2005; Bishop 2010). Thus, I do not think the objection is particularly worrisome for my view, compared to other reliabilist views, and perhaps compared to any current theory of doxastic justification. Everyone needs a solution to the problem. I am optimistic that a solution will eventually be found, but I suspect that this solution will require significant empirical research into the actual psychological and neurological processes that underly belief-forming methods. How to type human belief-forming methods seems like a question that depends on the way the human psychology works.Footnote 31

Another objection involves the possibility of untestable methods: beliefs formed by one method that are not amenable to testing by other methods. For instance, we could imagine that there is a particular belief about a smell or about a color that is not testable by comparison to our other beliefs. These would be beliefs such as “I smell pie” or “this shade of blue looks like the ocean,” or perhaps most worrisome of all “this is blue.” These kinds of beliefs may seem to be in principle untestable, and thus to be something that could not count as justified under MCR. There are several possible responses to this objection.

First, I suspect there are few belief-forming methods that would qualify as untestable. When confronted with a belief about a particular shade of a color, for example, generally I would compare my perception of the color with the reports of other people’s perceptions to determine if I was correct in comparing it with other instances of color. This would qualify as testing the belief, since testimonyFootnote 32 is generally a reliable belief-forming method. Episodic memory and induction are both methods as well, so in fact there would be several methods that could be used to test this color perception, even though beliefs about color are characteristically formed by vision. Note that this is similar to how some people might actually come to find out that they are color-blind. One might consistently judge that two lights are the same color, until they are told otherwise. This would then show that the belief-forming method in question is incoherent and thus suspect.

Moreover, if we have a belief formed by one method that cannot be validated by other methods, we often take this as evidence that there is something wrong with that method, whether that is a temporary unsuitability to the situation, or something more drastic. Just as in the case of the carefully vague beliefs formed by crystal gazing, the fact that the beliefs are untestable is a reason to think that something may be wrong with the method. This seems akin to problems we have with scientific theories which are untestable, or unfalsifiable.

If one is not yet convinced by these considerations, I wonder how problematic the cases left over will really be for the view. The most worrisome kind of case will involve judgments about phenomenal character or our mental life, such as “this appears blue,” or “blue is like this,” or something like “I think, I exist.” But such judgments are those of which we can (perhaps) be most certain. However, reliabilism, and MCR, are theories about how we can come to know things, even though we are fallible. It doesn’t seem like much of a concession to admit that MCR doesn’t apply to those (very few) cases in which we are most certain. The project of trying to understand all of knowledge and justification in terms of the way we come to know this small set of things is impossible. So we need some other account of our less certain knowledge and justification, and that is what MCR provides.Footnote 33

Another worry one might have about the MCC is that it is too stringent for very simple creatures to satisfy it. If a creature had only one belief-forming method, for instance, then it would be unable to achieve method coherence. This does not seem like a problem to me, however. I doubt that creatures with only a single method for forming “beliefs” would actually be cognitively sophisticated enough to count as believers at all. This is because having beliefs seems to require having mental states with a sophisticated functional profile. Beliefs are mental states of creatures capable of cognition. It is unclear that a system without significant interaction between states would count as cognitive. If a creature only has one kind of “belief”-forming method, it doesn’t seem like it will have enough variety in its belief-like states in order to count as being cognitive, and thereby even count as having genuine beliefs.

For instance, consider a magnetotactic bacterium, which orients itself based on earth’s magentic field. It seems incapable of having beliefs, and of having epistemic justification. This is despite the fact that it has a reliable way of determining the direction of oxygen, and acts so as to satisfy its survival requirements on the basis of this determination. It is not sophisticated enough to count as a believer, because it is does not seem that any cognition is occurring. Rather, it just reacts to external stimuli. Moreover, even if such a creature did count as having beliefs, it seems intuitive to me that they would not count as being epistemically justified in their beliefs. Epistemic justification is another feature that seems restricted to relatively sophisticated creatures. After all, even committed reliabilists recognize the epistemic importance of a subject having sensitivity to defeat (e.g., Goldman 1979). Simple creatures relying on a single method will not have such sensitivity.

Conversely, one might worry that the method coherence condition is too easy to achieve. Specifically, if it were possible for a method to count as “sufficiently coherent” when it has only been tested by a single other method, then the MCC would be worrisomely permissive. However, I intend sufficient coherence to be more stringent than this, as my appeal to the notion of “holistic” coherence above is meant to indicate. A subject’s methods must be tested against a number of others in order to achieve this holistic coherence. Precisely how many will depend on a number of factors: the kind of reliability requirement one prefers (i.e., process, or competence), the answer to the generality problem, and perhaps the situation and context of the subject. Since I want to remain ecumenical about these topics, I will not endorse a particular answer here. Nonetheless, I do not think this objection poses a serious problem for the view.

Another objection concerns the Roxanne case. Above, I claim that it is a benefit of MCR that it avoids granting Roxanne justification even at the first step of her bootstrapping process: it denies that she is justified in believing that the tank is full. One might worry that this goes against the intuitions and commitments of reliabilists. Isn’t this just the kind of basic belief reliabilists want to justify?

I want to grant that there are many cases which are similar to Roxanne’s where the subject is justified (as I point out at the end of Sect. 3.2). However, Roxanne has been described as a particularly bad epistemic agent. She does not have the sensitivity to her other available methods which we expect an agent to have. That there is an expectation of heeding one’s available reliable methods has been recognized by reliabilists as a way of responding to certain purported counter-examples (Goldman 1979; Goldman and Beddor 2015). MCR provides an account of one aspect of that expectation: Roxanne is using a method which she has not successfully tested for coherence with her other methods. Thus, I don’t think reliabilists should be happy to treat Roxanne as justified in this case. The MCR appropriately allows us to avoid this result.

Another worry one might have is related to the last objection. This objection is that we do not really need a solution to the direct circularity problem, and that MC is thus less necessary than I suggest. Some reliabilists, including Van Cleve (2003), Sosa (2009), have argued that the similarity the circular reasoning between the perceiver and the crystal gazer should not perturb the reliabilist. After all, the difference between the perceiver and the gazer is that perception really is reliable, whereas crystal gazing is not. Moreover, in light of the bootstrapping/easy knowledge problem, we might be stuck with skepticism if we don’t allow this kind of circular reasoning (Van Cleve 2003). We should simply be happy to point to the fact that Al in the Crystal Ball Gazer case (from pg. 4) employs false premises in his reasoning: crystal gazing is not in fact reliable. This distinguishes Al and the perceiver adequately so that reliabilists should not be perturbed by the similar form of the arguments.

Nonetheless, I remain perturbed. I’m perturbed because, generally, we are able to distinguish good reasoning from bad, quite apart from the actual truth value of our premises. This is true even in cases where the quality of the reasoning does not depend merely on formal structure; i.e., we are generally good at distinguishing strong inductive inferences from weak ones. Al does not just have false premises, he seems to engage in bad reasoning. If reliabilism really does permit the same kind of reasoning for Al and for the perceiver, then it seems to permit bad reasoning. A solution to epistemic circularity that simply appeals to the truth of the premises fails account for the fact that Al’s reasoning is bad, not just his beliefs.

The method coherence condition provides an explanation of how Al’s belief-formation went wrong, without appeal simply to the falsity of premises in his reasoning. His reasoning is unacceptable, over and above the falsity of his premises, because the method he is using to evaluate itself is not method coherent. Suppose Al has a twin in another possible world, Al*. Al* lives in a world where crystal gazing is reliable. If Al* forms his beliefs just like Al does (and fails to adequately method coherence test the crystal ball by, e.g., only making vague predictions), he will still be doing something wrong.

Recall that the kind of reasoning in question is an inference we can express thusly: method x says that method x is reliable, therefore method x is reliable. What is wrong with this kind of inference? One clear problem is that it is prone to false positives. It can be employed with respect to an unreliable method, and unreliable methods (like Al’s crystal gazing) can provide the result that they are reliable, a false conclusion. The MCC provides a principled way of limiting which methods should be trusted, and so helps avoid these false positives.

Importantly, the MCC limits such inferences in a way which does not require us to presuppose the truth or falsity of the conclusion of the reasoning in question. A restriction of the inference that instead appealed to the reliability of the methods would require us to presuppose the truth or falsity of the conclusion in question. Furthermore, the method coherence restriction seems more easily action-guiding for the subject. Method coherence does not require the subject have access, but it does seem more directly accessible than reliability.

Thus, I take it that we do need a solution for the direct circularity problem, and method coherence provides one that is acceptably non-circular and action-guiding.

Finally, one might worry about that a reliabilist who adds the MCC to her account of justification may no longer be able to provide a Moorean response to the skeptic (such as the one in Sosa 2009). The Moorean argument requires that the account allows for a subject to be justified in believing (e.g.,) “here is a hand” without presupposing the conclusion “I am not a hand-less brain in a vat.” Since the MCC requires more than mere reliability, one might worry that we cannot obtain this result. However, MCR can still deliver this result. Satisfying the method coherence condition does not require presupposing that one is not brain in a vat (in fact, a brain in a vat can satisfy the MCC). All that is required is that one successfully test one’s relevant perceptual belief-forming method before deploying it to form the belief “here is a hand.” This requires no presupposition that one is not a brain in a vat.

6 Conclusion

A reliabilism incorporating a method coherence condition will be better able to meet the direct circularity objections raised by Fumerton. Method coherence also accounts for the illegitimacy of bootstrapping. Furthermore, method coherence respects our intuitions about the importance of the way we form beliefs, and it fits with our everyday and scientific practices of justification. The addition of the method coherence condition offers us a way to capture the key advantages of reliabilism, while avoiding objections, in a manner that coheres well with our intuitive notion of appropriate epistemic behavior. Arguing that this solution to epistemic circularity problems is superior to all others on offer must await future work.