1 Introduction

Phenomenology is a philosophical approach that seeks to provide a descriptive account of the essential structures of transcendental subjectivity, the latter being the subjectivity that experiences the world and its objects as always already there with their significance for us prior to the worldly subject’s thinking and acting in response to the pre-given world. Put another way, phenomenology describes the universal structures of the intentionality at work in the different types of possible experience, structures that make experiences the type of experience they are. In the phenomenological tradition the term “ethics”—broadly construed—encompasses every form of moral and morally relevant experience, from recognizing and evaluating goods to be pursued and bads to be avoided to choosing what to do and to characterizing the “authentic” life. Hence, phenomenologists are concerned to clarify the intentional structures at work in (1) our varied experiences of valuing, choosing, planning, trying, striving, and acting in ways that have moral or ethical significance, whether that significance be in the form of goods desired and pursued or in the form of exercises of free, self-conscious choice or in the form of felt obligations; (2) our experiences of persons, actions, situations, and events as virtuous or non-virtuous, good or bad, or right or wrong; and (3) our experiences of institutions and social structures as beneficial or harmful, as liberating or oppressive.

This methodological program has clear implications for metaethics. Questions concerning the nature of evaluation, decision or choice, the will, freedom, practical reason, and the objectivity of our moral evaluations and moral judgments are widely addressed within the phenomenological tradition. But the situation is different when we consider the implications of the various metaethical positions adopted by phenomenologists for normative ethics. They encounter problems similar to those faced by anyone concerned to account for how our interests in and desires for particular goods or values—our motivations to act—can be reconciled with the obligations characteristic of moral life.

Early phenomenological thinkers often adopted an axiological approach, although significantly different views of the nature of value coexist within the phenomenological tradition.Footnote 1 For these thinkers, subjects apprehend in an intentional feeling objective values that ground our desires and the actions that seek to satisfy them. Other thinkers claimed that values are created in the exercise of the freedom definitive of human beings. But both positions invite a criticism. Even if, the critique goes, the description of the intentional structures can identify the essential structures of valuation and choice, they do so only in relation to the subject’s feelings or freedom. The universality of these affective and volitional structures would ground only the universality of the how of evaluative and volitional intentionality. On the best-case scenario—so the argument runs—the phenomenological description can provide a norm for determining only whether a particular instance is a genuine instance of valuing or choosing. It cannot provide a norm for determining the correctness or incorrectness of the valuation or the rightness or wrongness of the choice of an action. We have no basis, the critique concludes, for judging the success or failure of the evaluation or choice with respect to its objective content. So, both phenomenological alternatives fall short of providing any normative content for a phenomenological ethics.

Moreover, each of the three italicized words in the first sentence of this paper poses a problem when approaching normative ethics from a phenomenological point of view. First, the transcendental subject must be distinguished from the psychological subject. The psychological is a region in the world, and the psychological subject is the subject in the world. The transcendental, however, insofar as it encompasses the intentional correlation between minded subjects and world, is not a region in the world, and the transcendental subject is the subject of the world, the subject that discloses the world as always already manifest and whose structure makes possible the experiences of the psychological subject in the world.Footnote 2 Transcendental subjectivity as a dimension of the psychological subject cannot simply be identified with psychological or human subjectivity. Yet ethics seems a specifically human—not transcendental—affair. Second, the universalism or essentialism of phenomenology suggests that phenomenology cannot address the particularity of ethical situations and the multiplicity of goods—and ways of pursuing those goods—that are consistent with living an ethical life. To put the matter another way, it seems that phenomenology is unable to account for the relevance of an agent’s facticity for deliberating about choiceworthy ends and right actions. Third, the descriptive characteristic of phenomenology seems inapt for capturing the normativity of ethical experience.

This paper will consider three metaethical positions adopted by phenomenologists and the implications of those positions for a normative ethics. By way of preface, I begin with a brief account of the phenomenological method.

2 A minimalist account of the phenomenological method

The phenomenological method specifies the domain for philosophical reflection by means of a reflective turn that Edmund Husserl—but not all phenomenologists—calls the “phenomenological reduction.”Footnote 3 Putting aside the debates about the possibility, extent, and significance of the reduction, I suggest that the minimal sense of the reduction shared by phenomenologists involves—to put it in Husserlian terms—suspending one’s participation in the belief in the existence of the world (and the objects therein), a belief characteristic of our straightforward, everyday experience of the world. To perform this minimal reduction is to lead one’s attention back (re-ducere) to the experience intending the object and to take the object intended in experience (whether or not it exists) simply as it is experienced, as having a particular significance for the subject. The reduction, in summary, thematizes the inseparable correlation of experiencing subject and experienced object as meant.Footnote 4 The turn to the experience with its correlate entails that the phenomenologist always takes into account the first-personal perspective of experiencing agents as an aspect of any experience with its object as experienced.

Having disclosed the intentional correlation as a field of study, the phenomenologist turns to its descriptive analysis. Description contrasts with explanation. Explanations identify causal relations and mechanisms, and applied to experience, they identify the physical and psychological causes of an experience. In this way, they look at the experience “sideways-on,” that is, from an external or third-person vantage point.Footnote 5 Phenomenological descriptions, by contrast, clarify the nature of intentional experience; they reveal the constituents, structures, and categories operative in intentional experience and its objects as experienced, just as they are meant in experience. They reveal the meaning-categories that underlie judgments and logical principles, the ontological categories that govern the relations among objects, and the transcendental categories that shape subjective life.

Finally, although adopting a first-personal perspective, phenomenologists do not employ the first-personal perspective of psychological introspection, which yields insight only into the actual and particular experiences of the introspecting subject. Phenomenologists, focusing on the correlation between experiencing agent and experienced world, seek to reveal the essential, a priori structures of subjectivity itself and of objectivity just insofar as objects are disclosed by subjectivity. Phenomenology is, even in its minimal sense, what Husserl—to employ his terminology again—calls an “eidetic” science.Footnote 6 Paradoxically, phenomenology takes a descriptive third-person stance toward the first-personal perspective essential to experiencing the world.Footnote 7

While Husserl began articulating his understanding of an eidetic methodology as early as Logical Investigations and of the phenomenological reduction as early as 1907, by the 1920s he, along with Heidegger, recognized the need for a methodological approach that could take account of the historical development of the significance objects have for us and of the handing down of this significance in tradition. In addition to revealing the structures of dependence and interdependence among aspects of experience and of the senses disclosed in those experiences, the phenomenologist explores the formation of meaning over time and how such meanings guide future experience. All these methodological features are found in the metaethical views taken by phenomenologists.

3 Non-intellectualism and strong value realism

A number of phenomenologists working roughly in the first third of the twentieth century adopted an axiological approach to ethics.Footnote 8 These phenomenologists agree on three theses: (1) values and the significance that attaches to them are dependent for their disclosure on subjects capable of intentional feelings, (2) intentional feelings are the essential moment in the disclosure of value, (3) intentional feelings grasp value-objects (either ideal values or worldly goods) independent of those feelings, at least in the sense that a thing’s being valuable is not reducible to its being felt valuable. Theses (1) and (2) suggest a non-intellectualism while a strong reading of thesis (3) asserts a strong realism with respect to values.Footnote 9 Nicolai Hartmann, Alexius Meinong, Max Scheler, and Dietrich von Hildebrand offer variants of this view. The intentional feeling involved in experiencing value is indispensable to the experience of value, and the ideal value-properties apprehended are monadic properties that do not depend on the feeling-experience for their being, although they do depend on experience for the lived significance of these values in the lives of agents.Footnote 10

Scheler is perhaps the starkest proponent of this position. He speaks of an order of intentional feelings through which a priori, monadic, mind-independent value-properties are directly apprehended.Footnote 11 These a priori values, rather than the valuable things (goods), are the primordial phenomenon. Value precedes its bearer, and our apprehension of something as valuable depends on a prior apprehension of the value, an apprehension that in no way depends upon any inductive or causal inferences from the experience of the bearers of that value. Values, in other words, are pure, essential qualities ontologically distinct from, ontologically prior to, and presented independently of both the goods that serve as their bearers—that is, of possible objects of desire—and of any willing or positing activity of the subject.Footnote 12 The prior apprehension of the value underlies the grasp of the object as a good, and the instantiated value is the good-making characteristic of the object valued as good.Footnote 13

Non-intellectualist realism faces a challenge: Can the apprehension of ideal values provide sufficient guidance in making decisions about what one ought to do in particular situations? Scheler, for example, identifies an a priori hierarchy of values. From the lowest to the highest they are: (1) values of the pleasant and unpleasant; (2) the vital values (e.g., the fine and the vulgar); (3) the spiritual values (e.g., the beautiful and the ugly, correctness and incorrectness); and (4) the values of the holy and unholy. Noteworthy, however, is that the list does not include any moral values. Scheler views moral values as attaching to the actions that realize the values listed in the hierarchy. This view is rooted in Scheler’s distinction between the purely ideal ought-to-be (the value) and the moral ought-to-do.Footnote 14 Scheler claims that insight into the ideal ought-to-be serves as the basis for willing and for realizing a universally binding moral ought-to-do. However, since a feeling must grasp the value as desirable or lovable prior to the grasp of a moral ought-to-do, the ought-to-do appears as an imperative only to those who recognize the value as desirable or lovable. Scheler’s imperatives are in the end only hypothetical imperatives.

This is the basis of von Hildebrand’s criticism of Scheler. Von Hildebrand insists that moral obligation has categorical force. He speaks of the significance or “importance” (Bedeutsamkeit) of an object, where importance is understood as that “property of a being which gives it the character of a bonum or a malum.”Footnote 15 There are three “categories” of importance: the “subjectively satisfying” to or for a person; the “objective good for the person”; and the “important-in-itself.”Footnote 16 Since the second category presupposes the third, the three categories in practice collapse into two, and von Hildebrand concludes, “Only that which is important-in-itself is a value in the true sense.”Footnote 17 Von Hildebrand argues that any attempt to ground an imperative in the experience of the subjectively satisfying determines the will only contingently and heteronomously. Intrinsic values, by contrast, “challenge” (rather than “invite”) the agent apart from any relation to subjective interests, emotions, desires, needs, and wants.Footnote 18 While this view gains a ground for moral obligation, it is unclear that intrinsic value by itself can motivate moral action—can count as a moral norm for the agent—apart from the value having importance for the agent.

Hartmann seems to recognize the difficulty most clearly. He recognizes that the appeal to ideal values as normative cannot account for the role facticity—our experiential history, our interests, the situation, and the context in which we act—plays in moral action. Although he stresses to a greater degree even than Scheler the universality of values, he recognizes that values can be of varying importance to different persons, that universal and personal values might not always align. In Hartmann’s view, ideal values are experienced as universal demands. However, as he himself notes, to do what everyone should do in the same circumstances is, in effect, to say an agent is replaceable by anyone, and this is to deny the agent’s individuality as a person.Footnote 19 Appeals to universal principles depend upon a typicality among the situations in which we are called upon to act, but any maxim of action must be tied to a particular situation and to a particular agent in that situation. Hence, the universality of a principle undercuts its own applicability to the particular situation that, owing to the uniqueness of persons and their interests and commitments, is itself unique.Footnote 20 In a paradoxical way, universal principles, on Hartmann’s view, just insofar as they fail to heed the individual personalities and situations of agents, do not—and cannot—offer moral guidance.

In summary, since different individuals have different affective responses to things and different desires, it appears that values can be binding only on agents having the relevant feelings and desires. For Scheler, von Hildebrand, and Hartmann, the phenomenologically disclosed metaethical principle that objective and universal values are directly apprehended in an intentional feeling fails to underwrite a normative ethical theory of the sort that could justify the categorical character that moral imperatives grounded in ideal values should have.

There is a more general phenomenological issue involving the relation between grasping a value and acting that is relevant to this discussion. We cannot assume, as I believe the strong realists do, that experiencing a value will directly incline us to act so as to realize that value.Footnote 21 The relation between valuation and action is mediated by desire. Not every grasp of something as valuable motivates desire. There are, for example, feelings and emotions whose “performance dimension” terminates in the expression of the emotion. But this is different from motivating action for an end, much less moral action.Footnote 22

Nor does desire seem a component of emotion when we are “struck” by value, when, in fact, action seems arrested.Footnote 23 Such experiences are often expressed by an exclamation or interjection, such as “How sad that is” upon hearing of a colleague’s serious illness, or “How vulgar” upon witnessing someone’s behavior, or “Such generosity” upon hearing that someone has made a magnificent gift to an institution. These clearly involve emotions such as sadness, disgust, and admiration, but they do not arouse desire and motivate actions that arise from the emotion itself and its recognition of the value or disvalue of its object.

Moreover, even when an emotion does motivate a desire as, say, in fear, it is the desire that, in turn, motivates the action. The desire is grounded in the evaluation of something as good, and in situations where I lack what is evaluated as good, that good can become the object of desire. The emotion discloses the good, and desire takes realizing or obtaining that good (or avoiding a bad) as the end of possible actions. But the different possibilities of action must also themselves be evaluated. It is not enough that the actions conduce to the end; the action too must be evaluated positively. Insofar as the emotion motivates a desire, it motivates a range of possible actions, and further evaluation must determine the particular action undertaken. There is no easy, direct road from emotion to action from emotion, although there might be a direct road from emotion to “acting” (to a physical performance) in the grip of an emotion. In brief, the phenomenology of the transition from valuing a good to acting from the value-norm is more complex than suggested by the strong value-realists.

4 Non-intellectualism and anti-realism

A later generation of “existential” phenomenologists appeal instead to freedom as the ground of value, providing a constructivist or “decisionist” account of the experience of value.Footnote 24 Examples include the early Jean-Paul Sartre, Simone de Beauvoir, and Merleau-Ponty, all of whom claim that choice—the exercise of the freedom that is constitutive of human beings—creates value.Footnote 25 Values come into being when agents freely transcend their own situation and grasp a non-existent possibility as the object of their desires and choices, of their projects.

Human autonomy, in this view, is the sole source of value, including the value of human existence itself, and values have no existence apart from the free choices of agents. Although there are factical obstacles to the agent’s exercise of freedom—obstacles that are to be overcome—freedom itself is unconstrained by objective values or principles. Indeed, this tension between the freedom of an agent and the factical obstacles faced in realizing one’s freely chosen projects is, as Beauvoir notes, the fundamental ambiguity of human existence. A human being, identical with its freedom and unconstrained by objective principle, chooses its own ends, including freedom itself, but the goal at which freedom aims “is not fixed once and for all” and “is defined all along the road which leads to it.”Footnote 26 Whereas Sartre thinks that both meaning and value are constituted in the free, even if unconscious and non-deliberated, choices of agents, Merleau-Ponty believes that persons are born into a world already permeated with meaning. Freedom, in Merleau-Ponty’s view, is exercised in this context of meaning, creating and recreating values and thereby accomplishing the task of completing the world through the institution of values.Footnote 27

Can this non-intellectualist anti-realism ground universal moral norms? There is no problem here in connecting the value and action, since the claim is that moral norms are established in the choice itself, in choosing to act in a particular way. As Sartre puts it, one chooses for all.Footnote 28 However, this normativity is not morally normative in any significant sense, since no other agent is bound by such norms.Footnote 29 My choices are “binding” on you only from my perspective. If I adopt a bourgeois lifestyle, then your spitting on the sidewalk, lying, and thievery justify my condemnation of you.Footnote 30 But you, having made different choices, do not see the demands of my lifestyle as binding on you, and you instead judge me in relation to the values your exercise of freedom has established. Since we are always (at least somewhat) free to choose otherwise, it appears that values can bind us only insofar as we choose that value.

One response to this objection is to claim that these phenomenologists are more interested in giving a normative account of what it is to be a self rather than developing a normative ethics. In describing the exercise of freedom, the phenomenological anti-realist identifies the universal structures of freedom. The existential account sees the human agent as one who makes of herself who and what she is through her choices; she defines herself through self-conscious choice and is thereby responsible for herself. The self-conscious exercise of freedom is “authentic” existence. An authentic autonomous agent recognizes and values her existence as it is: free, gratuitous, and lacking transcendent values to justify it.Footnote 31 Authenticity thus appears in the guise of a “virtue,” the disposition to take control over one’s life in self-conscious choices. The agent thus frees herself from the social and historical forces that threaten to make her a pawn of contingent circumstances. Non-intellectualist anti-realism norms only how the choice is made—in a full, self-conscious exercise of personal freedom—and not the content of the choice. While this does not undergird a normative moral theory, it does provide an account of what a “flourishing” or authentic human life would be, an account of the fullness of human existence.

The problem of making the transition from the experience of value as involving either feelings or choice to the experience of categorical moral norms—that is, of obligations—prompts some phenomenologists to ground the notion of obligation independently from value. Emmanuel Levinas, for example, claims that the experience of obligation is prior to all acts of evaluation, all choices, all projects, and all dictates of reason. Obligation arises for Levinas, as it does for Kant, from beyond all “inclinations.” Unlike Kant, however, Levinas turns his attention to intersubjectivity to find the ground of obligation. He adopts a “second-person perspective” in which moral demands are experienced in encountering the “face” of the Other.Footnote 32

Levinas’s ethics begins from the fact that intersubjective life commences when the other addresses me, summons me, and commands me. The “face” of the other, “exceeding the idea of the other in me” is pure expression and carries the summons and the command.Footnote 33 The other and I are in an asymmetrical relation wherein the other’s ethical superiority outweighs my egoism.Footnote 34 The other approaches, as Levinas puts it, from on high, disconcerting my conscious intentionality and contesting my freedom, calling both into question in such a way that I have no choice but to respond. The other’s command awakens in me a sense of responsibility such that my concerns must transcend the merely egoistic in the direction of the other.Footnote 35 Only insofar as I acknowledge this command do I live in a world with the other and become a person myself. Morality and responsibility begin, then, with neither my feelings nor my freedom but with the other’s challenge to my identity, a challenge that obligates me to give more of myself than I can expect from the other. The experience of the other is from the beginning an experience of obligation.

The question raised by this account is similar to the one raised by von Hildebrand’s account. I can encounter moral obligation as my obligation only insofar as what I encounter is referred back to my moral concerns. As Hartmann recognizes, obedience to the moral imperative apart from any reference to inclinations depersonalizes the action—whether in Kant, von Hildebrand, or Levinas—insofar as the action is divorced even from the agent’s will to flourish precisely as a moral agent through obedience to the moral imperative and in fulfilling her own moral commitments. The will to flourish is entirely displaced in Kant by obedience to law, in von Hildebrand by obedience to the call of the important-in-itself (value), and in Levinas by the presence of the Other. The question arises whether this is satisfactory as an account of moral motivation and, by extension, of moral normativity for individual agents.

5 Weak intellectualism and weak value realism

A third metaethical alternative, best exemplified by Husserl, is found in the phenomenological tradition. It agrees with the three theses previously laid out in §2, but it understands thesis (3) differently from the thinkers mentioned there. I characterize this as a weak intellectualism because, although feelings remain indispensable to the disclosure of value, the basic experience of value—that is, of a valued object, of a good—is a value-perception (Wertnehmung) that encompasses the cognition of a set of underlying non-axiological properties that serve to motivate the feeling (or emotion) apprehending the object as valued, as good or bad.Footnote 36 These non-axiological properties, relative to the physiological constitution, experiential history, interests, concerns, and commitments of the subject, motivate an intentional feeling that takes the object as valuable in the current experiential context.Footnote 37 The object, in other words, presents itself as having an axiological or affective sense over and above its purely cognitive sense, but that axiological sense is intertwined with, motivated by, and (presumably) justified by the non-axiological sense of the object.Footnote 38 This value-perception underlies both value-judgments and the identification of the a priori “values as objects themselves” (Wertgegenstände or Wertobjektitäten).Footnote 39 This is a “weak” value realism insofar as the value attribute is understood not as a monadic property (as for Hartmann, Meinong, Scheler, and von Hildebrand) but as a dyadic attribute dependent upon both features of the object and the subjective structures at work in the subject’s evaluatively intending the object.Footnote 40

The reference to the experiencing agent preserves the first-personal perspective characteristic of phenomenology, for it ensures that the value-attributes of experienced things do not have their sense and being entirely independent of any reference to (a possible) mind. This entails that values are disclosed only in relation to minds that are characterized by certain interests in things, by certain desires, cares, and commitments and to agents acting in particular situations and historical contexts. Values are subject-related, dyadic attributes of things; nevertheless, the objectivity of values is preserved insofar as any possible subject having or entertaining similar interests, desires, cares, or commitments would recognize the thing as having the value-attribute.

Can this combination of weak intellectualism and weak value-realism allow for the development of a normative ethics? I believe so. Establishing this, however, requires a consideration of a different aspect of intentional relatedness, namely, the teleological directedness of an empty intention to a full intention. An empty intention is one that makes present (as in imagination or language) an object that is absent to consciousness. Full intentions, by contrast, present an object intuitively by virtue of their involving either (1) a sensuous dimension or (2) a phantasm (that is, with the aid of the retention of a previous experience involving a sensuous dimension, as in a distinct memory). A full intention is called “fulfilling” when, in the dynamic interplay of intentions, it sensuously or phantasmally presents the object as it has been emptily intended and thereby “satisfies” or “fulfills” the empty intention. In a broader context, reason is then understood as the striving for evidence, that is, the experience of the agreement between what is meant in an empty intention and what is sensuously or phantasmally given in a fulfilling intention.Footnote 41

An agent is rational in the full sense when in an evidential experience she determines for herself what is true, adopts the appropriate evaluative attitudes, or decides what is rightly done.Footnote 42 The fully rational agent takes responsibility for her convictions and for disclosing the evidence that warrants those convictions. This self-responsible pursuit of what is truthful in all the spheres of reason makes up the eudaimonistic character of a phenomenological axiology. The agent who is rational in the full sense—the agent who lives the flourishing life for rational agents—is “authentic” or self-responsible.Footnote 43 This notion of authenticity differs from that of the “existential” phenomenologists in three significant ways: (1) it connects authenticity to truthfulness rather than freedom; (2) it connects authenticity to self-realization as a truthful and responsible agent rather than to self-determination through self-conscious choice; and (3) it is the end of rational agency rather than the manner of self-conscious choice. This view by no means precludes freedom in matters of cognition, feeling, or acting. Our judgments are not caused by the things we experience, but they are normed—at least to some degree—by what the things truly are even as our interests, cares, and commitments necessarily contribute to our sense of the world and of the goods found, or to be realized, in it. Because this notion of authenticity is connected to truthfulness, it cannot have the same content-neutrality that authenticity on the existential view does.

This notion of authenticity entails a bifurcated sense of the good.Footnote 44 There are the first-order goods that are the objects of our everyday evaluations and choices, and there are the second-order goods of evidential fulfillment and self-responsibility, the goods proper to intentional life itself. Our being as rational agents is inherently ordered toward what we can consider the transcendental good of self-responsibility in all the spheres of reason, the goods of truthfully disclosing what is the case, what is genuinely valuable, and what is right to do. But this good is realized only in the truthful pursuit of first-order goods. Conversely, the flourishing agent, acting truthfully in the pursuit of genuine first-order and contingent goods for herself and others, superveniently and necessarily realizes the goods of thinking well, feeling well, and acting well—what we might call the goods of rational agency.

The goods of thinking truly, feeling appropriately, and choosing and acting rightly are goods properly realized only in interpersonal contexts when others also realize them. The apprehension of what is the case, the evaluation of goods (including moral goods), the decision about how best to realize those goods, and evaluative judgments about our own actions, the actions of others, and social practices and institutions all arise against the background of a common knowledge embodied in our collective determinations of empirical, evaluative, and moral concepts, of choiceworthy goods, and of praiseworthy actions. This common knowledge—our notions, for example, of politeness, kindness, or generosity—is passed from one generation to the next, and it continues to be examined, criticized, reappropriated, and modified within successive generations in our encounters with those whose opinions or reasoning might differ from our own. Only in coming to grips with differing opinions and beliefs and only if our own opinions and beliefs have been self-responsibly formed and asserted can we truly be said to be a person holding convictions that have withstood a thoroughgoing critique. In order to be self-responsible and to realize the goods of agency, in other words, one must think for oneself but not by oneself. For this reason, these goods of agency must be effectively—even if only implicitly—sought for others as well as for oneself.Footnote 45

Securing the goods of agency for ourselves and others does not foreclose the pursuit of different first-order, contingent goods. The universality and necessity of the second-order goods of agency is, in other words, consistent with the pluralism of first-order goods pursuable in free societies. However, insofar as the self-responsible pursuit of first-order goods requires that one secure the goods of agency as such, the pursuit of some first-order goods is morally wrong on universalist grounds if that pursuit blocks the realization of the goods of agency for oneself or others.Footnote 46 Hence, first-order goods are now apprehended both as necessarily transformed by and as yielding to the second-order goods of agency. This is the framework in which a phenomenological normative ethics is to be developed.

6 Conclusion

Four elements of the phenomenological method were identified at the outset. Phenomenology is a transcendental, descriptive, and eidetic science that explores the intentional correlation with its irreducible first-person perspective and its inescapable (essential) facticity, the details of which are, of course, contingent and non-essential. This methodology is consistent with different metaethical views, but the question about the possibility of a phenomenological normative ethics remained. I have claimed that only the combination of a weak intellectualism and weak value realism can establish a normative ethics consistent with these four features of the phenomenological method.

The position outlined is transcendental, descriptive, and eidetic. It describes how the experiences involved in our moral and ethical lives disclose the importance and significance of the things, situations, events, actions, and persons we encounter. It identifies the universal and necessary intentional structures of evaluation, choice, and fulfillment.Footnote 47 Its transcendental character is visible in its identification of the second-order goods of rational agency. These goods are formal goods; they are neutral among competing first-order goods. The first-person perspective with its facticity is evident in the subject-relatedness of our experience of value as informed and shaped by our physiological constitution, our experiential history, our interests, concerns, and commitments. Actions in pursuit of first-order goods will be moral just insofar as our valuations are appropriate and our actions are right. Both appropriateness and rightness are determined against the background of the common concepts and traditions that characterize the communities in which we live and act. But both our individual experience and those shared concepts are morally circumscribed by the second-order goods whose realization requires that we respect the autonomy of others and sympathetically seek their flourishing as well as our own.