1 Introduction

In the same year that Harry Markowitz revolutionized portfolio theory (Markowitz, 1952a), he also planted the seed of what decades later would become behavioral economics (Markowitz, 1952b). He also played a key role in the debate over stocks for the long-run and the geometric-mean criterion (Markowitz, 1976, 2006). This paper hopes to shed new light on this long-standing debate.

The investment with the maximal geometric mean yields a terminal wealth which is higher than that obtained by any other investment, with a probability that approaches 1 as the investment horizon increases. This leads to a strong intuition favoring the maximization of the geometric mean by the long-run investors (Kelly, 1956, Latane, 1959, Breiman, 1960, Elton & Gruber, 1974, Thorp, 1975, Markowitz, 1976, Bernstein, 1976, 2006, Vander Weide et al., 1977, Vander Weide, 2010, Levy, 2016, and Lo et al., 2018). As stocks have higher geometric means than bonds, this result leads to the popular prescription of “stocks for the long run” (Siegel, 2021). Maximizing the geometric-mean conforms with expected utility maximization for investors with log preferences, i.e. Constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) with a relative risk aversion coefficient of 1. On the other hand, Merton and Samuelson (1974) and Samuelson (1994) object to the geometric-mean criterion and argue that a CRRA investor with relative risk aversion different than 1 will generally choose an investment other than the one with the maximal geometric mean, and this choice holds regardless of the horizon. While this statement is no-doubt mathematically correct, many find its implications hard to swallow. In this paper we show that CRRA preferences imply paradoxical behavior unless the relative risk aversion coefficient is close to 1. Thus, while Merton and Samuelson’s argument is correct, it may be economically irrelevant, reinforcing Markowitz’s intuition about geometric-mean maximization.

CRRA preferences play a central role in the economic theory of decision-making. These preferences seem to provide the best existing model for decisions involving a substantial part of the individual’s wealth. Evidence supporting CRRA preferences has been found both empirically (for example, see Friend & Blume, 1975; Szpiro, 1986a, 1986b; Szpiro & Outreville, 1988; Meyer & Meyer, 2005; Brunnermeier & Nagel, 2008; Chiappori & Paiella, 2011) and experimentally (Agnew et al., 2008; Andreoni & Sprenger, 2012; Heinemann, 2008; Levy, 1994; Levy & Levy, 2021; Levy & Nir, 2012). Accordingly, most economic models of individual decision-making assume CRRA preferences.Footnote 1

When smaller stakes are involved, such as in incentivized laboratory experiments, many studies find that Prospect Theory, or alternative behavioral models provide a better description of choice (Kahneman & Tversky, 1979; Machina, 1987; Thaler, 2016; Tversky & Kahneman, 1992). Thus, it has been suggested that different models apply to decisions “in the large” and to decisions “in the small” (Rabin, 2000; Levy & Levy, 2021). In this study we focus on decision “in the large”, i.e. decisions with substantial implications for the individual’s total wealth, such as decisions about portfolio allocations and lifelong savings.

This paper scrutinizes CRRA preferences, and shows that unless the relative risk aversion coefficient is in a rather narrow range around 1, they imply paradoxical choices that very few, if any, individuals would ever make. It is well-known that any utility function that is either unbounded from above, or converges to \(-\infty \) at some wealth level, leads to paradoxical choices (see, for example, Menger, 1934; Arrow, 1974; Aumann, 1977). If the utility function is unbounded from above, then for any arbitrarily large value M and any arbitrarily small probability p, there exists a value N (N > M) such that a gamble yielding N with probability p is preferred over M for sure. This implies paradoxical choices: very few individuals would be willing to forgo $100 million (M) for sure for a 1-in-a-million (p) chance of getting a blank check (in which they can fill in the value N). This paradox has not stopped economists from taking unbounded utility functions seriously, as evident by the popularity of CRRA preferences as a modelling choice. A possible reason for this is that the value N required to ensure the preference of the risky gamble over M may be so large as to make the gamble meaningless. According to recent estimates,Footnote 2 the total wealth in the world is in the order of $1,000 trillion, i.e. $\({10}^{15}\). If the N required for the individual to paradoxically prefer the lottery is, say, $\({10}^{100}\), then the lottery is meaningless—it involves an outcome which is billions of times larger than the total wealth in the world. This may explain why most economists are not too troubled by this kind of paradox.

Similarly, utility functions that converge to \(-\infty \) at some wealth level also imply paradoxical behavior. For example, consider utility functions converging to \(-\infty \) at wealth zero, such as any CRRA utility function with relative risk aversion exceeding (or equal to) 1. For any arbitrarily large value M, there exists a value m close to 0, such that the decision-maker prefers having 1¢ for sure over a 50–50 chance gamble yielding either M or m. Clearly, very few individuals would prefer 1¢ for sure over a 50–50 chance gamble yielding either $100 million (M) or, say, $\({1}^{-10}\). Again, this sort of gamble may be considered as meaningless, and hence the paradox mute, because there is a minimal quantum of wealth, e.g. 1¢, and there is no real-world meaning to a wealth of $\({1}^{-10}\).

This paper imposes realistic constraints on the maximal possible wealth and the minimal unit of wealth, and derives the values of relative risk aversion that yield paradoxical behavior under these conditions. We find that CRRA preferences with relative risk aversion outside of the range (0.75–1.15) lead to paradoxical choices that very few, if any, individuals would ever make. Thus, the relative risk aversion coefficient must be in a rather narrow range around 1, the value corresponding to the Bernoulli log preferences.

2 A lower bound on relative risk aversion

CRRA preferences are given by the utility function \(U\left(W\right)=\frac{1}{1-\alpha }{W}^{1-\alpha }\), where \(W\) denotes wealth and \(\alpha \ge 0\) is the relative risk aversion coefficient. The logarithmic utility function is obtained as a special case of the CRRA family, with a relative risk aversion of 1.

Consider a gamble yielding a terminal wealth of $\({10}^{15}\) (roughly the entire wealth in the world) with a probability of 1%, or a wealth of $1 with probability 99%. What is the certain amount of wealth X that would make you indifferent between it and the gamble? It seems reasonable to expect that the vast majority of individuals would prefer having $10 million for sure over the above gamble. Yet, CRRA individuals with \(\alpha <0.75\) prefer the gamble over a sure $10 million, as shown below.

For a given value of \(\alpha \), the indifference value X is given as the solution to:

$$ X^{1 - \alpha } = 0.01 \cdot 10^{{15\left( {1 - \alpha } \right)}} + 0.99 \cdot 1^{1 - \alpha } $$
(1)

Figure 1 depicts the value of X as a function of the relative risk aversion, \(\alpha \). We can gain insight to the solution of Eq. (1) by noticing that the second term, 0.99, is typically negligible relative to the first term involving \({10}^{15}\). If we neglect the 0.99 term, we have:

$$ \left( {1 - \alpha } \right)\log \left( X \right) = - 2 + 15\left( {1 - \alpha } \right) $$
(2)

(where log denotes base-10 logarithm), or:

$$ X = 10^{{\left( {15 - \frac{2}{1 - \alpha }} \right)}} $$
(3)
Fig. 1
figure 1

The Certainty equivalent of a gamble yielding a 1% chance of having all the wealth in the world (\({\$10}^{15}\))and a 99% probability of having $1 (the exact solution to Eq. 1). The vertical axis depicts X, in $, on a logarithmic scale. CRRA individuals with relative risk aversion \(\alpha <0.75\) prefer this gamble over having $10 million with certainty

Thus, for a CRRA investor with \(\alpha =0.5\), for example, the indifference sure value X is $\({10}^{11}\). A person with this relative risk aversion coefficient is willing to forgo $100 billion for sure for a 1% chance of having all the wealth in the world and a 99% chance of having only $1. This seems as a paradoxical choice. For \(\alpha =0.75\) Eq. (3) implies an indifference value of \(X=\${10}^{7}\) or $10 million. Again, it seems that very few individuals would make such choices. As Fig. 1 shows, for values of \(\alpha \) in excess of 0.75, X sharply decreases to more reasonable values. For example, for \(\alpha =0.8\) the value of X drops to $100,000, which seems to be a much more reasonable value (for even higher values of \(\alpha \) the approximation in (3) breaks down, and one should employ the exact Eq. (1); Fig. 1 depicts this exact solution).

Running an experiment with real payoffs to elicit individuals’ indifference values X is obviously impossible. However, introspection leads to the conclusion that some values can be considered as “unreasonable” or “paradoxical”. It is hard to imagine anyone preferring a gamble with a 99% chance of ending up with only $1 and a 1% chance of having all the wealth in world over a sure wealth of $10 million. Thus, we conclude that the real-world upper bound on wealth of \({\$10}^{15}\) implies that relative risk aversion should be higher than 0.75.

3 An upper bound on relative risk aversion

Consider the choice between two wealth gambles, as shown in Table 1. Gamble A yields a wealth of $1 with certainty. Gamble B yields a 50–50 chance of either 1¢ or X. 1¢ is taken as the real-world minimal unit of wealth. What is the value of X that would make you indifferent between the two gambles?

Table 1 xxx

It seems that most people would determine the indifference value X somewhere in the range between $2 and $100. Yet, CRRA investors with \(\alpha >1.15\) prefer the sure $1 of Prospect A even if X is the entire wealth in the world. To see this, note that X satisfies:

$$ 1^{1 - \alpha } = \frac{1}{2}\left( {0.01^{1 - \alpha } + X^{1 - \alpha } } \right) $$
(4)

Rearranging yields:

$$ X^{1 - \alpha } = 2 - 0.01^{1 - \alpha } $$
(5)

Figure 2 shows the solution to Eq. (5). For \(\alpha =0\) (risk-neutrality) we have \(X=1.99\). X increases with \(\alpha \), as expected. The interesting point is that at \(\alpha =1.15\) the expression on the right hand side converges to 0, and X “explodes” to infinity.Footnote 3 In other words, investors with \(\alpha >1.15\) prefer the sure $1 even if the risky gamble offers a 50% chance for all the wealth in the world. As very few, if any, individuals would make such choices, we conclude that relative risk aversion must be less than 1.15.

Fig. 2
figure 2

The value X yielding indifference between gambles A and B in Table 1 (i.e. the solution to Eq. 5). The vertical axis depicts X, in $, on a logarithmic scale. CRRA individuals with relative risk aversion \(\alpha >1.15\) prefer $1 for sure over a 50–50 gamble yielding either 1¢ or all the wealth in the world

Of course, gambles with real-world payoffs other than those considered here may imply even tighter bounds on \(\alpha \). But even the simple gambles analyzed here suffice to lead to the conclusion that relative risk aversion must be close to 1.

4 Generalization to power utility with a minimum subsistence level

Some researchers have suggested a generalization of CRRA preferences reflecting a minimum subsistence level that should be attained before any other considerations (see, for example, Roy, 1952, Samuelson, 1989, Merton, 1971, and Brocas et al., 2019). This is typically captured by a utility function of the form \(U\left(W\right)=\frac{1}{1-\alpha }{\left(W-S\right)}^{1-\alpha }\), where S is the minimum subsistence level. In this case relative risk aversion is no longer constant, but the same bounds on the power \(\alpha \) apply. Namely, in the prospects discussed in Sect. 2, which place a lower bound on \(\alpha \), replace the outcome of $1 by $S + 1, and define the certainty equivalent value by S + X, rather than X. In this case the solution to X is exactly the same as in Eq. (1) (note that S is negligible compared to \({\$10}^{15}\)). Thus, the same lower bound of 0.75 applies to \(\alpha \).

Similarly, the same upper bound of 1.15 on \(\alpha \) also applies. To see this, replace the outcome of $1 in Prospect A of Table 1 by $S + 1, and replace the outcomes in Prospect B by $S + 0.01 and $S + X, respectively. X is again the solution to Eq. (5), which is depicted in Fig. 2. Thus, the same lower and upper bounds on the value of the power \(\alpha \) hold is the case of a generalized power utility function with a minimum subsistence level.

5 Discussion

Many economists consider CRRA preferences as the best existing model of behavior when major decisions involving individuals’ total wealth are involved. Evidence supporting this preference class has been found in many empirical and experimental studies. Accordingly, CRRA preferences are a very common assumption in economic modelling. This study shows that unless the relative risk aversion coefficient is close to 1, the value corresponding to log preferences, CRRA preferences imply paradoxical choices, that very few, if any, real-world decision-makers would ever make. This result imposes structure on modelling choice: if one considers CRRA as a reasonable model of choice, this should be limited only to the case relative risk aversion close to 1.Footnote 4 Most of the estimates of the relative risk aversion coefficient are indeed in the range 0–2.Footnote 5 It is interesting to observe that the very first utility function ever suggested, almost three centuries ago (Bernoulli, 1738), is probably still the best model of choice for decisions “in the large”.

CRRA preferences are central to the longstanding debate about investment for the long-run. It is well-known that Relative risk aversion of 1 corresponds to log utility, and thus conforms with the maximization of the geometric mean.Footnote 6 Hence, the goal of maximizing the geometric mean for the long-run seems to be well-grounded: the CRRA preferences employed to justify behavior to the contrary (Merton & Samuelson, 1974) lead to behavior that not only Professor Markowitz, but even Professors Merton and Samuelson, I presume, would consider to be paradoxical.