Preamble

In the classic “The Mathematical Experience”, Reuben Hersh and Philip Davis gave a fresh look at mathematics and mathematicians, and showed us that notwithstanding Plato and Hilbert, mathematics is a human activity and culture, and its pretensions to absolute truth are unfounded. Mathematics is what mathematicians do!. This leitmotif was further expanded in the wonderful ‘sequel’ “Descartes’ Dream: The World According to Mathematics”, also with Davis, and the more philosophical “What Is Mathematics, Really?”, written by Reuben all by himself. The fact that mathematics is what (human) mathematicians do is further expounded, beautifully, in “Loving and Hating Mathematics”, written in collaboration with Vera John-Steiner, that, inter alia, debunks G.H. Hardy’s stupid quip that ‘Mathematics is a young men’s game’, by describing many excellent women mathematicians, and many excellent ‘old’ mathematicians.

What Hersh and Davis preached back in 1980 is still true today, but it has to be tweaked quite a bit, since very soon (in ≤ 50 years), mathematics would be ‘what (machine) mathematicians do’, and machines have different ‘emotional life’ than humans. Hence mathematics would finally, hopefully, become a true science.

What Is Mathematics (as Practiced Today)?

  • A religion with its doctrines and dogmas

  • A game with its (often arbitrary) rules

  • An (intellectual) athletic competitive sport, akin to chess and go

  • An art form with rigid rules

One thing, it is not is a science. Scientists, by definition, are trying to discover the truth about the outside world. Mathematicians do not care about discovering the truth about the mathematical world. All they care about is playing their artificial game, called [rigorous] proving, and observing their strict dogmas.

Beware of Greeks Carrying Mathematical Gifts

Once upon a time, a long time ago, mathematics was indeed a true science, and its practitioners devised methods for solving practical mathematical problems. The ancient Chinese, Indian, and Babylonian mathematicians were dedicated good scientists. Then came a major setback, the Greeks!

The dirty (open) secret of the enlightened Athenian “democracy” was that it was a slave society. Since slaves did all the manual labor, the rich folks had plenty of time to contemplate their navels and to ponder about the meaning of life. Hence, Western philosophy, with its many pseudo-questions, was developed in the hands of Plato, Aristotle, and their buddies, and “modern” pure mathematics was inaugurated in the hands of the gang of Euclid et al.

Not all Greek mathematics was like that, and Archimedes, Heron, and many others also did excellent applied mathematics, but even Archimedes was bound by the Euclidean “party line.”

Let’s digress and summarize the pernicious Greek influence.

A Brief History of Mathematics as a Sequence of (Unsuccessfully!) Trying to Answer Stupid Questions

  • Stupid Question 1: Prove the parallel postulate, i.e., make it a theorem.

    Many very smart people tried, in vain, to solve this problem, until it turned out, as we all know, to be impossible.

    This was really an artificial puzzle. Play the game of “logical deduction,” starting with the (other) axioms, and step-by-step construct an artificial structure called “rigorous mathematical proof,” whose bottom line is the statement that given a (geometrical) line and a point outside it, there is exactly one line through the point that does not meet the line.

  • Stupid Question 2: Trisect an arbitrary angle only using straight edge and compass.

    Many very smart people tried, in vain, to solve this problem, until it turned out, in the 19th century, to be impossible (trisecting an angle involves constructing a cubic-algebraic number, while it is not too hard to show that a necessary condition for a ruler-and-compass constructible number is that its minimal equation is a power of 2).

  • Stupid Question 3: Double the cube.

    Ditto, 21∕3 is a cubic-algebraic number.

  • Stupid Question 4: Square the circle.

    Many very smart people tried (and some still do!), in vain, to solve this problem, until it turned out, in the late 19th century, thanks to Lindemann (inspired by Hermite), to be impossible. Indeed, π (and hence \(\sqrt{\pi }\)) is transcendental, all the more reason why it is not constructible.

    Note that these three classical Delfian problems were really artificial puzzles, in an artificial game, whose artificial rules “only use straight edge and compass.”

  • Stupid Question 5: Find a general, closed-form formula, as an expression in p, q, r, s, only using addition, multiplication, division, and root extraction for a solution of the quintic equation:

    $$\displaystyle{x^{5} + px^{3} + qx^{2} + rx + s = 0\,.}$$

    Recall that the analogous question for a quadratic equation was answered, essentially, by the Babylonians. The questions for the cubic and quartic were answered by Tartaglia and Ferrari (and published by Cardano, ca. 1530), but after that, many smart people, for about three hundred years, tried, in vain, to “solve” the quintic equation.

    Let’s digress to examine how the Renaissance mathematicians “solved” the cubic equation:

    $$\displaystyle{x^{3} + px + q = 0\,.}$$

    (Recall that we can always transform x 3 + a 2 x 2 + a 1 x + a 0 = 0 to the above form by writing \(x = y -\frac{a_{2}} {3}\).)

    We first do an ad hoc trick, writing x = u + v, where u and v are to be determined.

    Then

    $$\displaystyle{(u + v)^{3} + p(u + v) + q = 0\,.}$$

    Expanding

    $$\displaystyle{u^{3} + 3u^{2}v + 3uv^{2} + v^{3} + p(u + v) + q = 0\,.}$$

    Rearranging

    $$\displaystyle{u^{3} + v^{3} + 3u^{2}v + 3uv^{2} + p(u + v) + q = 0\,.}$$

    Replacing 3u 2 v + 3uv 2 by 3uv(u + v) we get

    $$\displaystyle{u^{3} + v^{3} + 3uv(u + v) + p(u + v) + q = 0\,.}$$

    Factoring out (u + v) from the third and fourth terms

    $$\displaystyle{u^{3} + v^{3} + (3uv + p)(u + v) + q = 0\,.}$$

    We now do wishful thinking, demanding that

    $$\displaystyle{3uv + p = 0\,.}$$

    In other words

    $$\displaystyle{uv = -\frac{p} {3}\,.}$$

    Going back to the above equation we have

    $$\displaystyle{u^{3} + v^{3} + 0 + q = 0\,.}$$

    So

    $$\displaystyle{u^{3} + v^{3} = -q\,.}$$

    Cubing the equation \(uv = -\frac{p} {3}\), we get

    $$\displaystyle{u^{3}v^{3} = -\frac{p^{3}} {27}\,.}$$

    Hence the sum of u 3 and v 3 is − q and their product is \(-\frac{p^{3}} {27}\); hence both are solutions of the quadratic equation

    $$\displaystyle{z^{2} + qz -\frac{p^{3}} {27} = 0\,.}$$

    By the quadratic formula, the two roots u 3, v 3 are

    $$\displaystyle{\frac{-q \pm \sqrt{q^{2 } + \frac{4} {27}p^{3}}} {2} }$$

    So one root of the cubic is

    $$\displaystyle{\left (\frac{-q + \sqrt{q^{2 } + \frac{4} {27}p^{3}}} {2} \right )^{\frac{1} {3} } + \left (\frac{-q -\sqrt{q^{2 } + \frac{4} {27}p^{3}}} {2} \right )^{\frac{1} {3} }\,.}$$

    The other two roots are ωu + ω 2 v and ω 2 u + ωv, where ω is a root of ω 2ω + 1 = 0.

    So by an ad hoc trick, and a lot of luck, we reduced solving a cubic to that of solving a quadratic.

    Similar ad hoc tricks work for the quartic, but mathematicians were stumped for three hundred years, until, famously, Ruffini, Abel, and most notably Galois proved that it is impossible.

    In hindsight, “solvability by radicals” is an artificial game with an artificial set of “legal moves,” and Galois et al. proved that it is impossible to get from position A, the quintic equation, to position B, an algebraic formula, only using addition, multiplication, division, and root extraction.

    I admit that while the question itself “solve a quintic by radicals,” which turned out (at least in hindsight) to be very stupid, it led to something not quite as stupid, Group theory and Galois theory.

  • Stupid Question 6: Find a “rigorous” foundation to the non-rigorous differential and integral calculus of Newton and Leibnitz, thereby “resolving” the paradoxes of Zeno and “addressing” Bishop Berkeley’s critique.

    This was allegedly “solved” by Cauchy and Weierstrass, but their “solution” was unnecessarily complicated and pedantic, creating the so-called real analysis as one of the most unattractive courses in the math major curriculum, where one does scholastic mental gymnastics to “prove” intuitively obvious facts.

    As I pointed out in my essay ‘Real’ Analysis Is a Degenerate Case of Discrete Analysis,

    [‘‘New Progress in Difference Equations’’, edited by Bernd Aulbach, Saber Elaydi, and Gerry Ladas (Proc. ICDEA 2001), Taylor and Francis, London] available online from my website,

    http://www.math.rutgers.edu/~zeilberg/mamarim/mamarimPDF/real.pdf,

    a much better, conceptually simpler, and more honest foundation is to chuck infinity and limits altogether and replace the derivative of a function f(x) that is defined as the limit of (f(x + h) − f(x))∕h as h goes to zero, by the difference operator \(\Delta _{h}f(x):= (f(x + h) - f(x))/h\), where h is a very small, but not “infinitesimal.” Since h is so tiny (and unknowable), it is more convenient to leave it symbolic (analogously to the way physicists write h for Planck’s constant). It is true that technically things get a bit messier; for example, the product rule is a little more complicated, but this is a small price to pay, and at the end of the day, when you replace the symbolic h by 0, you get the familiar rules.

    We live in a finite and discrete world, and the infinite and the continuous are mere optical illusions.

    Ironically, the way that “continuous” differential equations are (numerically) solved today, by computers, is by approximating them with finite-difference equations, and numerical analysts make a living by proving a priori error estimates. The true equations are finite-difference equations to begin with, but the mesh size is too small (and unknowable, the above mentioned h) that it would be impractical to solve numerically and one has to replace it by a far coarser grid.

  • Stupid Question 7: Is there a set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and that of the real numbers?

    This is Hilbert’s first problem, the so-called continuum hypothesis or CH for short. It is really a pseudo-question, since it pertains to two “infinite,” and hence fictional, sets. It is really an artificial puzzle. Can you reach, by finitely many legal moves (in the game called “logical deduction”) starting with the axioms of ZFC, either the statement that there exists such a set or the statement that there does not exist such a set. Paul Cohen famously proved that neither! The conventional way of saying it is that CH is independent of ZFC, but what Cohen really (brilliantly!) meta-proved was that the question was stupid! Neither CH nor its negation is reachable in the logical deduction game starting from the axioms of ZFC; hence both CH and ZFC are devoid of content, and what Cohen (and Gödel) meta-proved was that the so-called infinity does not exist [taken at face value].

  • Stupid Question 8: Are the axioms of arithmetic consistent?

    This, Hilbert’s second problem, was famously shown to be a stupid question by Kurt Gödel. The conventional, polite interpretation is that there exist undecidable statements, but a more honest interpretation is that every statement that involves quantities over “infinite” sets is a priori meaningless. Some such statements, e.g., that n + 1 = 1 + n for every natural number, can be made a posteriori meaningful, by thinking of n as a symbol, but what Gödel proved was that many such statements may not be resurrected like that.

  • Stupid Question 9: “Given a diophantine equation with any number of unknown quantities and with rational integral numerical coefficients, devise a process according to which it can be determined by a finite number of operations whether the question is solvable in rational integers.”

    This was famously (brilliantly) meta-proved to be a stupid question by Yuri Matiyasevich, standing on the shoulders of Martin Davis, Hillary Putnam, and Julia Robinson. What he really proved was that while for some specific diophantine equations, it is possible to prove that there are no solutions, (e.g., x 2 − 2y 2 = 0 and the equation x n + y n = z n , n > 2 , xyz ≠ 0), for other ones, it is possible to find many (in fact, potentially infinitely many) solutions (e.g., x 2 − 2y 2 = 1), and many such (seemingly sensible, but in fact meaningless) questions can’t be resolved in the artificial game called proving number theoretic statements. In other words, they are not only a priori meaningless (as all statements involving “infinite” sets are), they are also a posteriori meaningless.

Many Games Have Unreachable Positions

Time and time again, mathematicians realized that in their human-made, artificial game that they naively believed to be the real thing, many things are impossible. Sometimes, it is easy to prove the impossibility, for example, tiling, by domino pieces, an n × n checkerboard where two opposite corners have been removed, when n is odd. Since n 2 − 2 is odd, any covering by domino pieces must cover an even number of unit squares. Other times, the impossibility is more subtle; this is the case when n is even (e.g., n = 8, the usual chessboard). Coloring the unit squares (as in a chessboard) white and black alternatively, any putative domino covering must cover an equal number of black and white unit squares, but if you remove two opposite corners (from an n × n board with n even), they must be of the same color; hence, the remainder has an excess of two of the other color.

A less obvious example of proven impossibility is in the solitaire game called the fifteen puzzle that Sam Loyd was safe in offering a large prize for its solution (transposing the 14 and 15 and leaving the rest the same), since, as proved in one of the first volumes of James Joseph Sylvester’s periodical, American Journal of Mathematics, it is impossible.

Today’s Mathematics Is a Religion

Its central dogma is thou should prove everything rigorously. Let me describe two examples of the religious fanaticism of two of my good friends, George Andrews and Christian Krattenthaler. I admire their mathematics, and I like them as people, but I was disappointed (but also impressed) at their fanaticism (and [misguided] integrity).

Drew Sillls and I disproved (in the everyday sense of the word), conclusively, a long-standing conjecture by Hans Rademacher (one of the greatest number theorists of the 20th century and George Andrews’ thesis advisor). Since the disproof was not “rigorous,” George Andrews refused to consider it for the Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (PNAS), and when we submitted it, it was rejected, because he was consulted. Then we went to the less prestigious journal Mathematics of Computation, and once again it was rejected, since it was “too computational.” Then we went “down” to the Journal “Experimental Mathematics,” and once again it was rejected, by its editor, Yuri Tschinkel, since it was “too experimental.” Luckily (for Drew Sills, I already was fully promoted and would have left it in arxiv.org), it was finally accepted in another journal.

Another amusing example of the religious dogmatism of current, otherwise reasonable, mathematicians is when my collaborators, Manuel Kauers and Christian Koutschan, and I submitted to the not-exactly-prestigious journal Séminaire Lotharingien de Combinatoire an article

A Proof of George Andrews’ and Dave Robbins’ q-TSPP Conjecture (modulo a finite amount of routine calculations).

It contained a proof plan that, given enough computer resources, would give a fully rigorous proof, and we had plenty of evidence that the plan should work. But Christian Krattenthaler objected to the title! He would have been happy to accept it if we changed the title to:

A Proposal for a Possible Computer Proof of George Andrews’ and Dave Robbins’ q-TSPP Conjecture,

but we refused, so it remained in our websites (and the arxiv). Luckily, a year later, we found a way to prove it with today’s computers, and this fully rigorous version was gladly accepted by George Andrews for the PNAS. But all the main ideas were already contained in the previous, semi-rigorous version, with clear evidence that given enough computing power, it should work.

Today’s Mathematics Is a Competitive Sport

Number theory is full of conjectures that are obviously true, but humans are unable to prove them [in their outdated, narrow-minded sense of the word, meaning “rigorous proof”]. For example, Yitang Zhang got instantly famous by getting ever so close to the twin-prime conjecture. But even the still-open twin-prime conjecture is so far from what is definitely true, by very plausible heuristics. The twin-prime conjecture asserts that there are infinitely primes p such that also p + 2 is prime. The true fact is that there are lots and lots of them, not just “infinitely many”! In fact, there are O(n∕log(n)2) such twin-prime pairs less than n. But mathematicians do not care about truth; they only care about playing their (artificial!) game.

Today’s Mathematics Is an Artificial Game

As I demonstrated at length above.

Today’s Mathematics is an Art Form

Paul Erdős famously talked about proofs from the book, and, indeed, elegance and beauty are great values cherished by human mathematicians.

Humans, starting with Plato, via Dirac, Hardy, and almost everyone else, waxed eloquently about beauty. G. H. Hardy went as far as saying:

There is no place for ugly mathematics.

Excuse me, my dear Hardy, this is even stupider than your “young man’s game’ unfortunate quip [debunked by Hersh; btw, note the word game]. Beauty is only skin-deep and is also in the eyes of the beholder, and who are you to exclude “ugly” mathematics! Ironically, personally, I find most of your hard-analysis mathematics much uglier than the average mathematics, but this is beside the point.

In a cute New York Times [April 16, 2017] Opinion piece, entitled Beautiful Equations, math groupie and distinguished Cornell psychiatry professor, Richard A. Friedman, describes a psychological experiment conducted by Semir Zeki (in collaboration with three other coauthors: John Paul Romaya, Dionigi M. T. Benincasa, and, guess who?, Abel Prize Laureate and Fields Medalist Sir Michael Atiyah).

[The experience of mathematical beauty and its neural correlates, Front. Hum. Neurosci., 13 February 2014 https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2014.00068].

In that experiment, fifteen mathematicians were asked to rank a list of sixty famous equations according to beauty, and then electrodes were connected to their brains (using fMRI scanners), and there turned out to be a high correlation between the subject’s beauty rank of the formula before the scan and the activation of the area of the brain responsible for aesthetic pleasure.

This is a very interesting psychology experiment that tells a lot about humans but does not say anything about what mathematics should be.

It is instructive to see what rankded first and what ranked last. The number-one-hit formula was Euler’s

$$\displaystyle{e^{i\pi } + 1\, = 0\,,}$$

and the bottom one, the ugliest (in the eyes of the mathematicians’ guinea pigs), was Ramanujan’s formula for \(\frac{1} {\pi }\)

$$\displaystyle{{1 \over \pi } \, =\, 2\sqrt{2}\,\sum _{k=0}^{\infty }\,\frac{(1103 + 26390k)\,(1/4)_{k}(1/2)_{k}(3/4)_{k}} {k!^{3}} \cdot \frac{1} {99^{4k+2}}\,,}$$

where (a) k = a(a + 1)(a + k − 1).

This shows that human mathematicians are superficial. In the “eyes of God,” Ramanujan’s formula is much prettier than Euler’s. It is a deep relationship enabling a very fast computation of π to billions of decimals. In contrast, Euler’s beauty queen is an utter triviality, only a bit less trivial than

$$\displaystyle{1 + 1 = 2\,.}$$

In fact, these two equations have something in common; they may be viewed as definitions. 2, by definition, is 1 + 1, and π, by definition, is the smallest real number larger than 0 for which e ix happens to be equal to − 1. In other words, the smallest x for which sinx equals 0 (and hence cosx equals − 1 and hence e ix = cosx + isinx = −1 + i ⋅ 0 = −1).

While there is no harm in enjoying mathematics for its (subjective!) beauty, it is wrong to make it a defining property and to exclude what one (subjectively!) finds ugly. Every statement that has a proof from the book, is ipso facto, trivial, and, at least, a posteriori, since all deep statements have long proofs. In my eyes, the most beautiful theorems are those with succinct statements for which the shortest known (and hopefully any) proof is very long. So in my eyes, both the Appel-Haken’s four color theorem and Tom Hales’ Kepler’s ex-conjecture should be in the book.

Today’s Mathematics Is an Elitist and Exclusive Club

It has a very intricate social structure, with a fairly rigid pecking order, and hierarchy, and “peer-reviewed journals,” with pompous, often sadistic editors, who must enjoy rejecting submissions (or else they would refuse to take the job).

Some areas are considered very respectable, while other ones are slums. This is a dynamic process, and areas come and go out of fashion, but there are always, like in a high school, the “cool kids lunch table,” and there are always the outcasts and the pariahs. Humans will be humans!

Today’s Mathematics Is Not a Science

As we saw above, mathematics today is many things, but one thing that it is not is a science. It is amazing that, nevertheless, mathematics was so effective in science, so convincingly told by Eugene Wigner. One reason it was so effective was that the kind of mathematics that scientists needed was either discovered or rediscovered by themselves (e.g., Heisenberg rediscovered matrix algebra, ab initio), and they develop their own brand of mathematics, without the mathematicians’ misplaced obsession with rigor (e.g., quantum field theory and the renormalization group), and the great success of mathematics in science is in spite of the mathematicians’ superstitious dogmas. Imagine how more effective it would have been if they threw away their artificial shackles.

The Computer Revolution

The reason mathematics today is the way it is is due to the contingent fact that it was developed without computers. Most of the questions (and pseudo-questions) that occupied mathematicians through the ages are now moot and irrelevant. It may be a good idea to start all over and develop mathematics ab initio, not peeking at the human-generated mathematics done so far and taking full advantage of computers.

Let’s Make Mathematics a Science Again!

Mathematics should become a science, and its main raison-d’être should be the discovery of mathematical truth (broadly defined!). In particular, one should abandon the dichotomy between conjecture and theorem.

If a mathematical question is in doubt (and it looks that it can go either way: true, false (or meaningless (i.e., “undecidable”)), then it is a mathematical question. If there is overwhelming empirical and/or heuristic evidence, then it is a theorem. What was formerly called a theorem should be renamed “rigorously proved statement” [using the artificial game of logical deduction].

Final Words

Don’t get me wrong, while you may call me a self-hating mathematician, I do love elegant proofs and still enjoy traditional standards. So like Reuben Hersh’s wonderful book mentioned above, I love and hate (traditional) mathematics. But I do believe that it is time to make it a true science.