Keywords

These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

1 General Presentation

A wide variety of documents relating to mathematics education in the Near East and the Mediterranean basin have survived to the present day. The oldest of these sources are the southern Mesopotamian clay tablets produced in the third millennium before the Common Era. More recent sources were copied in the Byzantine Middle Ages from a long chain of texts which stem back to lost originals. Nonetheless, these late copies provide some evidence of educational activity and pedagogical orientation. As may be seen in the case studies in this chapter, these sources represent a wide chronological distribution but of texts of diverse genres. Some texts, like the tablets made of nearly indestructible clay, survive in great numbers and enable a reconstruction of the mathematical instruction of ancient Mesopotamia. Excavations in Iraq, Iran, and Syria since the late nineteenth century have produced a sufficient number of tablets to permit a detailed reconstruction of the basic mathematics curriculum in the scribal schools of the ancient Near East. Equivalent sources exist for the Greco-Roman world but in much lower numbers, and their state of preservation does not permit many conclusions. The Greco-Roman texts comprise small, disconnected fragments on papyrus, pottery, leather, and even wooden tablets covered with wax, all of which probably served in the teaching of mathematics. By contrast, relatively few texts of the copious Mesopotamian corpus report how the scribes in the ancient Near East conceived of their work, their knowledge, and its transmission, whereas the Greco-Roman texts written on parchment generally resulted from endeavors in copying or translation and only marginally constitute direct evidence of scholastic activity. Thus, these later sources shed limited light on the practicalities of transmitting mathematical knowledge from master to disciple in different contexts, and few of these texts detail elementary education. However, these sources do reveal the weighty didactic ideals of the Greco-Roman world which governed the prolific work in philosophy and rhetoric. In some cases, these ideals may be assumed to have been put into practice and corresponded to actual curricula, but this inference is speculative and probably useless. The evidence from Pharaonic Egypt represents a nadir of textual preservation and cultural reconstruction: although the series of problems found on ancient papyri probably served pedagogical purposes, the manner of instruction and the institutional setting in which these texts were used remain largely unknown.

The following synthesis is therefore based on sources that are characterized by extreme heterogeneity in their nature as well as in their geographical and chronological distribution. This fundamental fact should always be kept in mind to avoid anachronistic claims. The disparity of sources demands consideration of the varied and unevenly documented diversity of the educational settings and institutions of antiquity. In other words, the ancient sources neither relate to the same environments nor do they refer to the same cultural and institutional codes.Footnote 1 The available sources do not describe a complete or consistent picture of teaching mathematics in antiquity, but spotlights may be focused on the better documented teaching contexts of Mesopotamia, Egypt, and Greco-Roman world. Even if this disparity limits our actual knowledge of ancient mathematical teaching, these difficulties highlight the fact that both the “positive information” which we can claim to know and the kind of questions asked about ancient mathematical education depend strictly on the nature of the surviving sources.

2 Mesopotamia

During excavations conducted in Iraq, Iran, and Syria since the late nineteenth century, archaeologists and illegal diggers have unearthed hundreds of thousands of clay tablets containing texts of all kinds (including administrative records, contracts, letters, literary compositions, medical treatises, astronomical calculations, and mathematical writings). These documents provide evidence about the history of the ancient Near East over a very long period – more than 3,000 years since the beginnings of writing (c. 3300 BCE) until the abandonment of clay for writing at the beginning of the Common Era.

Numerous languages were transcribed in cuneiform writing on clay tablets (Fig. 3.1). Among mathematical texts, Sumerian and Akkadian are used. Sumerian, which was the language of the people of southern Mesopotamia during the third millennium, probably disappeared as a living language before the second millennium but remained the language of scholarship until the end of cuneiform writing. Akkadian is the Semitic language which gradually supplanted Sumerian and had long been the diplomatic language of the ancient Near East and Eastern Mediterranean.

Fig. 3.1
figure 1

Cuneiform writing (School tablet from Nippur, about 1800 BCE)

Approximately 2,000 tablets containing mathematical texts are presently known. Most of the mathematical cuneiform texts published during the early twentieth century by Neugebauer, Sachs, and Thureau-Dangin were bought from dealers by European and American museums or by private collectors, and their provenances are unknown. However, after the Second World War, archaeologists unearthed new collections of mathematical tablets with clear contexts, notably in the Diyala Valley (northern Mesopotamia) and in Susa (western Iran).

In cases where the provenances of the tablets are well documented, archaeological reports show that the tablets containing high-level mathematics shared the same findspots with elementary school tablets. Thus, the education of young scribes and activities of erudite scholars occurred in the same place, and possibly, the authors of these high-level mathematical texts were involved in teaching. But do these archaeological details indicate that all of the mathematical cuneiform texts were produced for educational purposes? A positive answer is often assumed, more or less tacitly, in recent studies of mathematics in Mesopotamia. However, the situation is probably more complex. Indeed, some of the cuneiform mathematical texts are clearly school exercises. (Some examples are examined below.) Others texts, which contain lists of solved problems, are probably (but not certainly) documents composed and used for advanced mathematical education. However, most of the higher-level mathematical texts do not clearly reveal the exact context in which they were composed or used. It is not always easy to identify the audience of such texts. As far as the cuneiform sources are concerned, more details are clearer here than in the case of Egyptian papyri. The strongest evidence derives from the physical details of the tablets themselves. The very shape, size, and layout of the tablets often reveal the nature of the context in which they were produced.

2.1 The Scribal Schools

Modern historians refer to the places where scribes were educated as “scribal schools.” Sometimes, the physical place of the school is well identified. In Nippur, Ur, Mari, and Sippar, for example, traces of teaching activities such as important collections of school exercises or bins used for recycling tablets were found in houses tentatively identified as scribal schools.Footnote 2 A particular Sumerian word designates such places as edubba, which literally means “house of tablets.” Sumerian literature portrays a highly idealized picture of the edubba, which appears as prestigious institutions for educating the social elite (Michalowski 1987, p. 63). This image may reflect reality at Nippur, the political and cultural capital of Old Babylonian Mesopotamia, whose schools merited high esteem throughout the ancient Near East. However, the organization of education appears to have varied considerably from one city to another. In some cities, the teaching activities seem to have been limited to the domestic sphere, as shown, for example, in Sippar by Tanret (2002, pp. 153–156). In other cities, priests may have participated in education, as shown in the cases of Ur (Charpin 1986, pp. 420–486) or Tell Haddad, a city of the Diyala Valley (Cavigneaux 1999, p. 257).

Most surviving Old Babylonian mathematical tablets are school tablets. They span a large geographical area (see map Fig. 3.2), but the bulk comes from Nippur. The careful analysis of thousands of tablets of Nippur has allowed historians to reconstruct in great detail the curriculum of mathematical education which took place in the schools of this city and perhaps in other edubba.Footnote 3

Fig. 3.2
figure 2

Places where mathematical tablets were found (● = OB elementary mathematical school texts; ∎ = OB advanced mathematical texts) (Map by Martin Sauvage, published in Proust 2007, p. 281)

2.2 The Elementary Level of Mathematical Education

The shapes of the tablets provide valuable evidence for the reconstruction of the curriculum. The tablets used most often at Nippur (type II in the typology of Assyriologists) are large rectangular tablets (about 10 × 15 cm), which the young apprentices used in their training to memorize and write a set of standardized texts. These texts included lists of cuneiform signs, Sumerian vocabulary, systems of measurement, and elementary numerical tables. When a long series of lexical lists or mathematical tables had been completely memorized, it was written on large multicolumn tablets known as “type I” or, sometimes, on prisms. These great compositions on prisms may be interpreted as a kind of examination (Veldhuis 1997, p. 31). In addition to these exercises, scribes would sometimes note short excerpts on small single-column rectangular tablets (type III – see Fig. 3.4). The Sumerian name of this type of tablet sometimes appears at the end of the composition, as well as in some literary texts: imgidda or “elongated tablets.” Imgidda tablets were often used to learn multiplication tables (as shown in Fig. 3.4).

Type II tablets (see Fig. 3.3) provided key evidence which allowed historians to identify the exact content of the texts studied by young scribes in the early stage of education and to reconstruct the order in which these texts were learned. Indeed, Veldhuis (1997, pp. 34–36) has shown that the reverse of type II tablets was “used as a repetition of a school text studied at a point earlier in the curriculum” (p. 36). Thus, by comparing the texts written in obverses and reverses of type II tablets, he reconstructed the elementary curriculum (pp. 41–67). Veldhuis focused on lexical texts, but the same method can be applied to mathematical texts (Robson 2001, 2002; Proust 2007). A detailed picture of elementary education in Nippur has emerged from these studies. The first level of the mathematical curriculum was devoted to learning the following lists and tables, more or less in the following order: lists enumerating measurements of capacity, weight, surface, and length; tables providing correspondence between the various measures and numbers written in sexagesimal place value notation (see Table 3.1); and numerical tables (tables of reciprocals, multiplication, squares, square roots, and cube roots). All of these elementary lists were probably learned by rote.Footnote 4

Table 3.1 Sexagesimal place value notation
Fig. 3.3
figure 3

Ni 4840+ +UM 29-13-711, type II tablet. Obverse, lexical list; reverse, measures of capacities (Proust 2007, p. 26)

Fig. 3.4
figure 4

HS 217, type III tablet. Multiplication table (Hilprecht 1906, p. 7)

Outside of Nippur, the mathematical curriculum cannot be reconstituted in such detail, partly because the number of available tablets is too small for any meaningful statistical consideration. The typology of tablets varies considerably. For example, type II tablets were rarely found outside of Nippur. In the schools of Mari and Ur, mainly small round tablets were used.

2.3 The Intermediate Level

After learning the metrological and numerical systems as well as a set of elementary arithmetical results (tables of reciprocals and multiplication tables), the scribes began an intermediate level of education. At this less formalized level, scribes learned the basics of sexagesimal calculation, namely, multiplication and calculation of the reciprocal of large numbers.

This knowledge was then applied to finding areas of squares and other figures. At schools in Nippur, this level of education is documented mainly through exercises noted on square-shaped tablets (see Fig. 3.5).

Fig. 3.5
figure 5

Ni 10241, reciprocal calculation (Proust 2007)

Table 3.2 summarizes the various aspects of the mathematical curriculum as it could have existed at Nippur and perhaps in other schools.

Table 3.2 Mathematical curriculum in OB Nippur

2.4 The Advanced Level

If the elementary and intermediate levels of mathematical education are well known, at least at Nippur, the context in which advanced mathematical texts from the Old Babylonian period were produced or used is more difficult to reconstruct. Mathematical texts have been previously interpreted as textbooks or as databases compiled for teaching. However, a pragmatic analysis of the texts suggests that the authors had at least some purposes other than teaching.Footnote 5 How is it possible to distinguish the tablets used for advanced teaching (written by students or teachers) from those that reflect investigations of pure scholarship? The first type of evidence could be the complexity of the mathematical procedures, but such a criterion can be misleading because what is complex for a modern reader may not have been complex for an ancient scribe and vice versa. Therefore, caution is advised for arguments based on the supposed “level” of a mathematical content. The second type of evidence is linked to material aspects. Very roughly, one can classify the tablets into two types: single-column tablets (type S) and multicolumn tablets (type M).Footnote 6 However, the shape of the tablets often conforms to local habits. Since most of the mathematical tablets are from unknown provenance, a general typology cannot be clearly connected with specific pedagogical practices. Thus, only case-by-case examinations are relevant to answer the question of how to distinguish teaching from scholarship. A mathematical text that seems to have been used at the beginning of the advanced level of mathematics presents a useful example.

An example of such a tablet is conserved at Yale University under the inventory number YBC 4663 (see Fig. 3.6). This tablet has an elongated shape and is written in a single column (type S). The tablet is of unknown origin but probably comes from a city in southern Mesopotamia. It contains a sequence of eight solved problems dealing with digging trenches. The parameters of the problem (data and unknowns) are the dimensions of the trench (length, width, depth), its base, the volume of extracted earth, the number of workers needed for digging, the daily labor assigned to the workers (namely, the volume of earth to be extracted each day by each worker), their daily wage, and the total wages (expressed as a weight of silver). All these parameters are linked by a simple relation that we can represent in modern fashion as follows:

Fig. 3.6
figure 6

Type S tablet – YBC 4663, Yale University (Courtesy of Benjamin Foster***)

$$ Total\; wage= daily\; wage\times \left(\frac{ length\times width\times depth}{ daily\; assigned\; task}\right) $$

Examination of the text shows how the procedures implement the computational methods taught at the elementary level of mathematical curriculum. For example, consider the first problem, translated as follows:

Translation of YBC 4663 #1

  1. 1.

    A trench. 5 ninda is the length, 1½ ninda (the width), ½ ninda its depth, 10 (gin) the volume of assignment (for each worker), 6 še (silver) [the wages of a hired man].

  2. 2.

    The area, the volume, the number of workers, and the (total expenses in) silver what? You, in your procedure,

  3. 3.

    the length and the width multiply each other. This will give you 7.30.

  4. 4.

    7.30 to its depth raise. This will give you 45.

  5. 5.

    The reciprocal of the assignment detach. This will give you 6. To 45 raise. This will give you 4.30.

  6. 6.

    4.30 to the wages raise. This will give you 9. Such is the procedure.

Note that in the statement of the problem (lines 1–2), the data are expressed in concrete numbers with units of measure, in the same way as in the metrological lists, but in the procedure (lines 3–6), the data appear only as abstract numbers expressed in sexagesimal place value notation (SPVN). Metrological tables had been used to transform measures into abstract numbers for performing calculations. This process is confirmed by the fact that the correspondences between the measures given in the statement and the abstract numbers used in the procedure fit with the correspondences provided by the metrological tables. This observation suggests that the authors of the text used the basic skills taught in the scribal schools. The sequence of problems listed on this tablet provides an opportunity to use all the metrological tables one after another, as well as multiplication tables and calculation techniques taught in the intermediate level (multiplication, inversions, calculating areas and volumes). All knowledge acquired in the early levels of mathematical education is systematically employed. In this way, we can suppose that the text was composed specifically for teaching mathematics. It could have been written by a master or an advanced student. An examination of other tablets similar to YBC 4663, which seem to come from the same city, may show that, in this city, type S tablets were used at the beginning of advanced education.Footnote 7

3 Hellenistic Period

A gap in the preservation of mathematical texts appears after the end of the Old Babylonian period. For subsequent periods, only sporadic examples of metrological and numerical tables are known. Only by the end of the first millennium BCE do coherent sets of mathematical sources reappear. Two small corpuses of mathematics texts dating from the Hellenistic period (c. 300 BC) have been discovered at Uruk and Babylon. It is difficult to know whether these corpuses from late periods reflect a kind of Renaissance after a long eclipse, or if the written mathematical tradition continued through the centuries. The transmission of elements of mathematical tradition over this long period tips the balance toward the second hypothesis. Advanced mathematical texts could have been noted on perishable materials such as leather or papyrus, which would not have resisted time.

The context of the Hellenistic period differs radically from the Old Babylonian world. The mathematical practices were developed by lineages of astrologers and astronomers who were linked to the great temples of Babylon and Uruk. In Hellenistic Mesopotamia, mathematical erudition was closely associated with the astral sciences.Footnote 8 Cuneiform mathematics was no longer taught to children or adolescents acquiring literacy and numeracy, as was the case in the Old Babylonian period, but to young scholars who were probably already literate in Aramaic and perhaps in Greek.

4 Ancient Egypt

Until the establishment of Greek as the solitary administrative language near the end of the second century of the Common Era, the situation regarding Egyptian sources on mathematical instruction inspires less confidence than that of either the cuneiform or Greek sources. First of all, the entire corpus of hieroglyphic and hieratic papyri counts roughly as many texts as the corpus of cuneiform mathematical texts. Among these papyri, only a handful of explicitly mathematical sources have survived.Footnote 9 No mathematical texts survive from the earliest periods of Egyptian history, and hieratic texts of Middle Egyptian comprise only three relatively intact papyri. One hieratic mathematical text has also survived on leather. If a wider view of mathematical texts is taken and papyri with calculations are counted, other early mathematical texts include sections of the Reisner Papyrus and a collection of hieratic fragments from Kahun. To these should be added two wooden tablets from Akhmim. After a lapse of more than a millennium, Demotic texts add one complete papyrus and six fragments and three Roman ostraca. In none of these cases have archaeologists established that the papyri survived in a pedagogical setting. The larger, more complete papyri contain collections of solved problems indicative of pedagogical use and fractional tables useful for calculation. Individual fractional tables are preserved among the smaller fragmentary papyri and ostraca, but most contain independent calculations (Table 3.3).

Table 3.3 Chronological range of Egyptian mathematical papyri

Not only do few mathematical sources survive, but the process of instruction in ancient Egypt is not well known. Because the authors of moral “instructional literature,” such as the Instructions of Ptahhotep (c. -2880), addressed their readers by familial terms, the earliest mode of Egyptian instruction has been imagined as a father instructing his children. However, this assumption ignores the possibility that the mode of address merely employs a rhetorical conceit. The first reference to “house of instruction” (˓.t n sb⫖) appeared in a Tenth Dynasty (c. -2160–2025) tomb. A composition titled The Satire of the Trades (c. -2025–1700) describes a royal school, but because the treatise seeks to esteem learning, the presence of an actual school cannot be assumed. Speculation about Egyptian pedagogy has focused on an element of the temple complexes titled “The House of Life,” but whether the curriculum of this place of instruction had a wider applicability outside the temple remains unknown.Footnote 10 The Onomasticon of Amenope (c. -1187–716) records a list of terms as important to the “scribes of The House of Life” that is similar to the lexicographical lists of Mesopotamia, but Egypt and Mesopotamia seem to have employed different organizational strategies. After he conquered Egypt, Darius endeavored to restore “The House of Life,” which may have served as a type of hospital. Again, little information about the Egyptian methods of instruction survives, and mathematics may not have even formed the curriculum of all scribes. Unlike Babylon, no large collections of school texts have survived, although some school texts (from mere onomastica and word lists to literary compositions used as models such as The Tale of Sinuhe) have been found. The larger mathematical papyri have been interpreted as pedagogical texts because they presented collections of similar exercises, but whether these writings formed the syllabus of specialists or generalists remains unstated. As shown by ostraca which repeat various phrases for different numbers and genders and others which elucidate the reading of certain hieroglyphs, education in grammar and writing seems to have formed some portion of the activity of the temple complex in the town of Medinet Madi, but these documents were mixed with administrative documents and texts useful for the composition of planetary positions. Unfortunately, some of these ostraca were reused as building materials, and the particular archaeological status of any given text may not be stated with certainty.

The date of composition for the largest of the papyri, the Rhind Mathematical Papyrus, coincides roughly with the first reference to a “place of instruction.” Whether or not it was used in such a school, the Rhind Mathematical Papyrus boasts that it contains “the model for enquiring into affairs and for knowing all that exists” but says nothing about the prerequisite knowledge, the intended audience, or the qualifications of a scribe who had mastered the material. Other than the techniques demonstrated, only the basic literacy necessary to read the papyrus may be presumed.

This translation of the title and introduction to the Rhind Mathematical Papyrus (Table 3.4) follows Couchoud’s (1993) French translation. Despite the grandiloquent promises of resolving all that is unclear and penetrating every mystery, the 87 surviving applications of Egyptian mathematics concern the doubling of fractions; the division of fractions by 10; the solution of linear polynomials; the unequal distribution of goods; the approximations of area in circles; the geometrical problems with rectangles, triangles, and pyramids; and the problems of exchange and geometrical progressions. The use of masculine, singular pronouns in the second and third person singular conforms to the impression that only males were educated in mathematics, perhaps working singly with the instructor or some other examiner.

Table 3.4 Title and introduction to the Rhind Mathematical Papyrus

The introduction to the most complete Demotic mathematical papyrus no longer survives, but some basic estimation of its pedagogical position may be derived from the fact that it shares a papyrus with a manual of legal formulae. Whether these compositions were textbooks or references remains an open question. Moreover, the juxtaposition of these two texts could be either the accidental result of reuse by a scribe whose training spanned both areas or a deliberate link forged by an instructor who connected land contracts with geometry.

In counterpoint to the pedagogical papyri, the fragmentary papyri may occasionally represent more than mere working notes for the resolution of a commonplace problem. A particular fragment of the Kahun Papyri (Kahun IV.3) could be dismissed as the pedestrian division of commodities, except for the mathematically playful requirement that the shares of the commodity increase in an arithmetic progression. Although the text may be salvaged from the corpus of “documentary evidence” by this detail, the pedagogical position of the fragment remains unclear. Taken collectively, these texts permit a rough estimation of the range of Egyptian mathematical knowledge and techniques of calculation, but specific details about what constituted basic knowledge, what represented advanced knowledge, how these topics were communicated, and how competency was assessed remain speculative.

5 Greco-Roman World

5.1 The Nature of Greco-Roman Sources on Teaching Mathematics

As evidence from Mesopotamia and Egypt shows, modern understanding of mathematical teaching and learning in antiquity depends on the nature of available sources. The Greco-Roman sources differ significantly from the Mesopotamian and Egyptian sources. For the sake of clarity, the following simplified classification may be proposed. First, texts with highly internally coherent mathematical contents sometimes (but not always) begin with prefaces which announce a pedagogical purpose, eventually oriented by a philosophical position. These texts were transmitted through a long chain of intermediaries and thus became classical texts in the long course of Greco-Roman history. This lengthy process incorporates “accompanying texts,” like marginalia or independent commentaries, which can be difficult to distinguish from the “original text.”Footnote 11 The writings of Euclid, Archimedes, and Ptolemy exhibit this process of incorporation.

Other kinds of texts also relate to mathematics and mathematical education but only in the sense that their content and nature are basically metamathematical: these texts describe philosophical or cultural projects in which mathematics plays an important role. Plato’s Republic, Vitruvius’s De Architectura, or Quintilianus’s Institutio Oratoria shares an esteem of mathematics while not being truly mathematical texts.

Somewhere between these two categories are the literary or philosophical sources which sometimes preserve excerpts of lost mathematical works by inclusion. In this case, the larger, encyclopedic project guides the choice of excerpts. For example, Simplicius preserves lost mathematical texts in his sixth-century commentaries on Aristotle. To this “intermediary” genre also belong texts like the second-century Introduction to Arithmetic by Nicomachus or the fifth-century commentary on the first book of Euclid’s Elements by Proclus, which basically attempt an explicit, philosophical project but introduce mathematical contents to achieve this purpose.

Fourth, direct archaeological evidence of mathematical teaching and learning survives in the form of fragments of papyri, ostraca, and wooden tablets, some of which can be related to a teaching context (although this attribution is often problematic). In the case of ancient mathematical knowledge, such evidence is scanty and consists of disconnected fragments with no clear context. Such sources approach the kind of material that came from Old Babylonian contexts, the richness of which enables a fairly satisfying reconstitution of mathematical curricula.

A fifth, “ghost” category nearly resembles the Egyptian material. This category contains isolated texts, like the problems of the Akhmim papyrus (Baillet 1892) or the problems in the “metrological corpus.” This category extends to the sophisticated problems contained in Diophantus’s Arithmetica, the structure of which strongly evokes pedagogical concerns, but the scholarly context of which remains unknown.

The key fact, then, about these sources is that the three first kinds of sources in the above classification have undergone a long-term process of “classicization” and are by far the best represented, while the other two categories are poorly represented. This does not suggest that nothing is known about mathematical education in praxis, but more precisely that what is “positively” known is necessarily of a different nature than what has been explained above about ancient Mesopotamia and Egypt: the divergence of approaches derives from the fact that the underlying sources differ in kind. This important acknowledgment implies a fundamental bias in our knowledge of mathematical education in this context. Only a specific part of the “ideal” picture may be revealed without access to a much richer range of sources.

For example, the technical texts in the first category, like the extant portions of Euclid, Apollonius, or Archimedes, have survived because they were transmitted, cultivated, commentated, and reused for contexts and purposes beyond the original aims of their Hellenistic authors.Footnote 12 Works like the compositions of the Pythagorean school or isolated figures like Hippocrates of Chios are known through the erudition of late scholars like Simplicius of Cilicia, whose work was in turn transmitted and copied in later times. Simplicius continued the tradition of ancient scholars like Vitruvius, Plutarch, Athenaeus, and perhaps even Euclid, who composed works that functioned as encyclopedias of ancient knowledge. This lengthy process of incorporation and citation stands as a general feature of ancient scholarship and extends much beyond the mathematical literature. This process guided the transmission and “classicization” of the ancient heritage of literature, philosophy, and more specialized issues like religious, medical, or mathematical texts. Note that this phenomenon is not proper to Greco-Roman Antiquity : already the Mesopotamian scribes had their own ‘classics’, as well as ‘dead languages’ that served as classical references. For classical culture, see Marrou (1965), Hadot (2005). For the Greco-roman heritage constituted as such for mathematics and in modern Europe, cf. Goldstein et al. (1996).

The majority of Greco-Roman sources, then, might be (rightfully) seen as “only” derived products, in contrast to the “direct” evidence of documents in the fourth category. The preserved manuscripts date to the medieval period (eighth or ninth century) for Greek literature and Late Antiquity (fifth century) for Latin technical literature.Footnote 13 These manuscripts represent a long transmission of copies, sometimes including transliterations and changes of format (Fowler 1999, pp. 204–221; Chouquet and Favory 2001, Chap. 1). As a result, they contain layers of transformations and annotations made during their history of transmission, often with no solid means to discriminate among variants, distinguish textual traditions, or establish a date for the sources. Unfortunately, for mathematical sources in particular, nearly no complementary information survives from other, older sources like scholastic papyri or even detailed accounts about mathematical practice. A larger number of documents of the fourth category would be needed to clarify how students were trained before or even during their study of more elaborate and erudite works, like Euclid’s Elements. Despite this lack, textual “transmission” should also be regarded as a fact of the utmost importance, for at least three reasons.

  • First, the process by which these sources were made classicalFootnote 14 can hardly be dissociated from the activities of teaching and learning. This is not to say that any marginal annotation in an ancient manuscript or any commentary automatically relates to a teaching activity; but, in many cases, the activities of commentary and note-taking might have plausibly been related to a scholastic activity. Such operations might have only been practiced at a high level in the curriculum of a literate person (Dorandi 2000). In some cases, then, we may guess at the possible structure or contents of a course for which directly resulting marginal notes were preserved. This relationship should be connected to the fact that in Greco-Roman contexts, advanced, literate education implied the study, oral reading, and excerpting of pieces of the classical corpus that formed “the circle of knowledge” (enkuklos paideia).Footnote 15

  • The second reason is that the activity of reading, excerpting, copying, or commentating on classical sources, be they mathematical in content or not, was valued and formed part of what Ineke Sluiter has called “the didactic tradition” (Sluiter 1999). By this is meant not the activity of teaching and its “concrete” tradition, but an idealized set of values that, in a non-negligible number of cases, were spelled out very explicitly. Such is the case in the prologues of redacted commentaries, like Theon’s commentary to Ptolemy’s Almagest (Bernard 2014) or the extremely developed exegetical prologue to Proclus’s commentary to Euclid’s Elements I (Lernoult 2010). Such documents are perhaps less valuable for what they indicate about the scholastic character of the corresponding commentaries than for what they say about the leading ideas and cultural purposes assigned to them. This aspect, in turn, is hardly separable from the existence of the second category of sources mentioned above: the Greco-Roman literature, especially in philosophy and rhetoric, contains sophisticated conceptualizations of the general notion of what teaching and learning means and even should mean. Famous early examples, as far as mathematics teaching is concerned, include Plato’s Meno, Republic, or Laws, Isocrates’s Antidosis, or for the Roman world Quintilianus’s Institutio Oratoria. All these works contain partial or extended discussion about what the role and nature of mathematical teaching should be within a general educational framework, the latter giving its full meaning and value to the former.

  • The third reason directly touches on the bias mentioned above: by their nature, these sources reflect a highly distorted picture of what the totality of “ancient mathematical cultures” might have represented, including many presently lost written sources, as well as the totality of non-written cultures. Many (if not most) ancient written sources have been lost by accident. Moreover, these sources could only be used and elaborated upon by persons who belonged to the (highly) restricted elite of “educated people” – pepaideuomenoi. Therefore, those milieus with some kind of mathematical activity and transmission of knowledge for which a bare trace remains, or which did not successfully highlight their specific skills in the standard terms of the literate culture, are almost totally absent.

The two first aspects should be carefully distinguished from the third, in order not to superimpose well-represented idealized descriptions and conceptions of teaching on the actual techniques, which are poorly documented. This precaution also eliminates deeply ingrained confusion between various periods of history or doubtful assimilations, such as the frequent claim that Euclid’s fundamental purpose for the Elements was pedagogical. The problem with this assertion is that Euclid and his exact purpose cannot be directly known because no document from the Hellenistic period relates to these questions.Footnote 16 What is known for certain is that Euclid’s purpose for his Elements may be interpreted as other than purely didacticFootnote 17 and that the first explicit mention of a didactic purpose for the Elements only appears some eight centuries later in Proclus’s commentary to its first book (Vitrac 1990, pp. 34–40; Bernard 2010b). In the case of commentators like Proclus who were also teachers,Footnote 18 this later dimension should probably be interpreted as the direct reflection of their own didactic concerns that they could easily project on the authors for whom they made commentaries (Sluiter 1999).

Another important reason for maintaining the distinction between idealized descriptions and actual techniques of teaching is that, while the actual practice and didactic devices are by nature evanescent, the prefaces, annotations, and such, along with the values they convey, are perennial in that they remain opened to reappropriation in later periods.

Bearing all this in mind, some scarce but interesting indications of the actual practice of teaching mathematics in certain contexts should now be introduced, as a way to convey a sense of the institutional setting for such teaching. This example leads to a summary of the thorny discussion of the (disputed) existence of a scholastic curriculum in Greco-Roman antiquity. Only then may a tentative and differentiated explanation about the meaning of mathematics and mathematics learning for various parts of Greco-Roman society be presented as a conclusion.

5.2 Three Possible Scenarios for Mathematics Teaching in Late Antiquity and What Can Be Concluded from Them

In the third book of the so-called Mathematical Collection,Footnote 19 the fourth-century polymath Pappus of Alexandria describes an encounter with some students of Pandrosion, a female teacher of geometry and a rival of Pappus. The students he encountered had submitted several challenges to Pappus, who was then encouraged by several of his peers to answer them. The related event is interesting in at least three respects.Footnote 20

Taken first as a straightforward account of the encounter, the anecdote shows that the agonistic and challenging character of ancient Greek culture, noted as early as the classical and first sophistic periods, survived well into Late Antique Alexandria and that geometry counted among the possible objects of controversy. Not only the fact that young people challenged Pappus but also his sophisticated answer to the challengeFootnote 21 indicates the pervasiveness of the rhetorical model of learning and teaching. This model demanded that the actual exercise of discourse be taught to students to enable them to become immersed, by imitation, in the rules of composition of discourses (Bernard 2003).

Taken now as a literary composition which describes his encounter with students in a slightly idealized manner, the philosophical tale reveals the values behind this kind of challenge: for this purpose, Pappus refers to the classical debate between Speusippus (Plato’s nephew) and Menaechmus (Eudoxus’s student) about the nature of mathematical activity. The first maintained that mathematics was all theory-making, and the other countered that it was all problem-solving. With this classical conflict in the background, Pappus identifies (and praises) the students as followers of Menaechmus (since they proposed a solution to a geometrical problem) and himself as a follower of Speusippus (since Pappus demonstrates his ability to theorize the proposed construction through relevant means). The whole “refutation” of the construction – and its mixture of blame and praise – follows the literary convention for describing such agonistic encounters, with their incumbent heavily charged ethical aspects.

A third aspect of the encounter also demands attention: the entire challenge is based on geometrical figures, handed out in written form to Pappus, which he corrected or completed in his text. This strongly suggests that the actual discussion of these figures, if it ever took place, relied on a physical prop, a figure which, for this discussion, played the same role that the images (eikones) played in ancient rhetoric: a pretext for discourse and collective discussion. More than this cannot be said: no traces of any pedagogical device have been retrieved that could help us figure out how geometry was taught or discussed in scholastic assemblies (sunousiai).

In his biography of the fifth-century philosopher Proclus of Lycia,Footnote 22 Marinus of Neapolis describes (among other stages) both Proclus’s training and his teaching methods after he succeeded Syrianus as the head of the Neoplatonist school in Athens. Like Marinus, Proclus in his own time reputedly displayed good enough knowledge of mathematics to have prepared a commentary on the first book of Euclid’s Elements and knew enough about Ptolemy’s Almagest to criticize him. As far as Proclus’s training is concerned, Marinus makes clear that Proclus’s wealthy parents, who were recognized notables, permitted him to travel from master to master, from whom he acquired skills ranging from rhetoric and declamation to mathematics and philosophy. As for mathematics, he is said to have been trained by a certain Hero, named by Marinus as an Alexandrian philosopher (Vita Procli, pp. 10–12). From Marinus’s description, Hero appears to have probably taught Proclus the neo-Pythagorean mathematics useful to understand Plato’s Timaeus and theurgic techniques in Hero’s own home. The latter aspect is not uncommon: wealthy students traveling from place to place and from one teacher to another often boarded with their teachers and became some kind of spiritual children, called gnôrimoi (relatives of the teacher). Moreover, these details show that the kind of mathematics taught probably did not constitute a specialized subject but part of a philosophically oriented teaching, hardly separable from reading Plato.Footnote 23

As an Athenian teacher of philosophy and mathematics, the intellectual activity of Proclus is represented by the two extant commentaries on mathematical authors mentioned above (namely, Euclid and Ptolemy) and also by Marinus’s description of his usual pedagogical technique. According to Marinus (Vita Procli, pp. 26–27), Proclus met with students for classes where he guided critical discussions on a traditional and varied material. In the evening, he would write down a record of his findings so that the extant commentaries probably represent the redaction of the notes taken from his courses. Again, more than this we cannot say: the archaeological remains of what might have been Proclus’s house in Athens (Karivieri 1994) have revealed no special didactic settings. Nonetheless, these details indicate that the study of classics was, as much for mathematics as for other subjects, the core of advanced teaching. The classics discussed in this context, as the extant commentaries make clear, were not “mathematical” in any restrictive sense, but incorporated a much wider circle of knowledge, including Aristotle and Plato’s writings.

The picture of a teacher surrounded by soliciting students for whom an extensive knowledge of classical works was prerequisite also seems to underlie the various prefaces written by Theon of Alexandria, a commentator from the second half of the fourth century, who elucidated Ptolemy’s Almagest (Tihon 1992; Jones 1999; Bernard 2014). Here also, the basic material of the course consists of classical works, not only Ptolemy’s treatise but also classical geometrical treatises and other commentaries on Ptolemy, which Theon encourages students to compare with his own (Bernard 2014). In this case, there are good reasons to believe that a significant portion of Theon’s audience was comprised of practicing astrologers.

The above examples, however interesting, represent only a small and biased sample of the various didactic settings that might have existed in antiquity. It must be noted that these examples all belong to Late Antiquity, for which we possess a significant number of accounts of teaching, although they are also presented in an idealized way and according to precise literary conventions.Footnote 24 Some aspects of these testimonies are nevertheless confirmed by archaeological records, especially discoveries recently made of auditoria at Kom el-Dikka in fifth-century Alexandria (Derda et al. 2007). One should also note that these reports only concern elite teaching and learning. Typically Marinus’s account of Proclus’s training makes clear that he directly began his schooling outside home with a “grammatikos”; any elementary teaching he received must in all probability have been imparted at home, thanks to his wealthy parents, and not in any “primary” school (Kaster 1983, p. 334).

For earlier periods and from other kinds of evidence (like the few surviving papyri), the intrinsically “classical” character of ancient teaching is also confirmed, but tantalizing hints appear about elementary teaching, such as exercises in simple calculations – a venue of mathematical education which is altogether very badly represented in the mathematical works or commentaries (Fowler 1999, pp. 222–262). In Theon’s commentaries or in the so-called prolegomena to the Almagest (Acerbi et al. 2010), there exists an exposition of calculation techniques, but these are hardly elementary because they relate to numbers expressed in sexagesimal numeration used only for astronomical (and therefore advanced) calculations imported from ancient Mesopotamia. Moreover, precisely because they are explained in such treatises, this style of calculation hardly appears to have been taught at an elementary level. The school exercises retrieved on papyri or ostraka are usually very difficult to situate precisely in terms of level and purpose.Footnote 25 Some of them, however, must have referred to the professional training of specialized slaves like scribes or calculators.

Finally, archaeological hints evoke very different teaching settings, like Egypt in the Roman period, where temples have existed in which astrological calculations were practiced as they were with astrologers who specialized in astral sciences and mathematics in Mesopotamia during the Hellenistic period (Jones 1994, 1999, p. 157).

All of these elements, however scarce and limited, indicate that we should certainly not generalize the picture afforded by more literary accounts, such as Pappus, Theon, or the later Neoplatonists. The existence of these accounts stems from the de facto selection of sources in proportion to their cultural value and literary sophistication (and therefore their value for the elite society alone) as well as from knowing much more about ancient education in Late Antiquity than about any other period of Greco-Roman antiquity.

In the face of this complexity, two possible approaches offer clarification. First, a widespread scholastic curriculum that would account for the various situations of Greco-Roman antiquity, and especially for the difference between elementary and advanced education, could be reconstructed. While this approach works for other cultural contexts, such as ancient Mesopotamia, this approach will be found to be highly problematic and, to some extent, sterile for Greco-Roman antiquity. Because of these difficulties, a more cautious and “localized” approach, which addresses the various elements of Greco-Roman society potentially concerned with mathematical education, may be adopted.

5.3 Disputes on the Existence and Nature of a Scholastic Curriculum in Greco-Roman Antiquity

For the past century, scholars have debated the existence of an institutionalized educational curriculum in antiquity. In the standard view that once prevailed, this curriculum could be neatly divided into three successive stages, respectively, labeled primary (or elementary), secondary, and higher or tertiary. Each stage had its own kind of teachers and school.Footnote 26 If only the contents (and not the institutional background) are considered, the first stage corresponds with the first acquisition of basic literacy (reading and writing skills) and numeracy (calculating skill with simple operations); the second stage with the study of advanced literature, especially poetry, with an emphasis on skillful reading up to the level of literary criticism and eventually including some instruction in higher mathematics; and the last stage with the learning of rhetorical skills or other advanced domains (philosophy, medicine, law).Footnote 27 The traditional view gives a straightforward interpretation of these various levels as representative of a progressive curriculum leading from elementary to higher studies, with specific teachers and locales for each level: the “teacher of letters” (grammatistês or ludus litterarii) for the first level; the “grammarian” (grammatikos, grammaticus)Footnote 28 and perhaps other professores (in geometry, arithmetic, astrology?)Footnote 29 for the second level; and rhetors, teachers of medicine or law, and philosophers for the last level.Footnote 30

But this standard view, which was already heavily nuanced by its first proponents,Footnote 31 has been increasingly challenged since Booth and others have progressively demonstrated that another model was applicable in some cases.Footnote 32 In this alternative view, elementary teaching should be considered as a basically separate track for people of the lower social level (including slaves), whereas the schools of grammatikoi were reserved for a higher elite.

The now accepted viewFootnote 33 is that no model applies uniformly to all of antiquity or throughout the entire Mediterranean world. Not surprisingly, Booth’s model of separate tracks seems better adapted for the big cities of antiquity, whereas the situation in small localities, with few teachers and very specific needs, would have been much more variegated. Thus, the main positive conclusion – perhaps the only indisputable one – of this scholarly debate is that “there were throughout the Empire schools of all shapes and kinds, depending on local needs, expectations, and resources.” Kaster rightfully adds that “in a world without centralized direction of education of any sort, that is only what we should expect.”Footnote 34

If no single model can be applied to all (known or unknown) teaching situations in antiquity, then it is worthwhile to detail the main reasons why the modern, three-stage curriculum cannot be considered valid. The first reason has already been mentioned: ample reports indicate that, in many cases, the various “stages” of education did not concern the same people, so there may be no stages at all, but only references to different teaching contents for different people.Footnote 35 The curriculum of the elite, which is naturally overrepresented in the ancient literature, concerned the same people (the rich and wellborn) and was strongly characterized by a relatively uniform and well-defined idea of literate culture that encompassed a limited set of classical authors and well-identified kinds of exercises practiced on them, from reading to critical analysis.Footnote 36 But even then, the order of studies at this stage was not completely fixed and depended on particular teachers and the length of study based on each student’s means: a significant rate of attrition existed, and the number of students decreased with the numbers of years of study. This characteristic conforms to the structure and contents of ancient teaching, which sought to deepen the understanding and study of classical texts rather than to attain a definite goal through an accumulative process. The same texts, therefore, were studied again and again but each time in a deeper way until the students, through imitation and impregnation, were able to compose or declaim on their own.Footnote 37 Moreover, the number of various elite “professions” that used this secondary curriculum shows that “secondary and tertiary” curricula were not uniform.

The second reason is that there is no clear proof of, and many counterexamples to, a fixed and unambiguous correspondence between these three “levels of teaching” and the competence of particular teachers. Thus, to take up the most discussed issue in the abovementioned studies, the same names of teachers, like “grammatistês” (teachers of letters), could actually refer to various contents or levels, from elementary to “secondary” (Kaster 1983, pp. 329–331; Szabat 2007, pp. 181–185). Likewise, grammatikoi could prepare students for higher achievements, either rhetorical or philosophical. Thus, the famous philosopher John Philoponus officially was a “grammarian” but was known to be a philosopher and commented on mathematical texts. This also means that the same person could teach at different levels, sometimes at the same time.

The third reason is that, more often than not, students of various levels learned together, all in the same space, rather than in separate classrooms organized according to the teaching. In general, the locales of teaching, if there were locales at all (some teachers worked in the street), are not easily identified; when they are, they could have belonged to various institutional buildings, from gymnasia to theaters or temples. In fact, what a “school” referred to, in the ancient context, should be understood in personal terms: as a circle of students frequenting a teacher.Footnote 38

Last but not least, the majority of inscriptions or papyri, especially those that can be found in small localities away from the great urban centers of Rome, Alexandria, or Antioch, show that the teachers’ presence, competencies, and missions depended heavily on the local context. This is actually the main reason to remain cautious about the “standard,” contemporary and (often) prescriptive accounts of ancient education, like in Quintilianus (Kaster 1983).

5.4 Various Kinds of Mathematics Teaching for Various Parts of Society and Professional Circles

Surviving sources preserve mere hints about the particular places and settings in which mathematics was taught in Greco-Roman antiquity. More than this is not really known, as shown by the difficulty of reconstructing a uniform scholastic curriculum in Greco-Roman antiquity. In fact, the various places, periods, and levels in society in which some kind of mathematics was practiced in various ways have left only fragmentary evidence or virtually no trace at all. Despite this dearth of information, some people outside of the elite might have been concerned with mathematical training.

5.4.1 The Elementary or Specialized Teaching of Arithmetical Skills: Slaves and Freedmen, Professional Scribes, and Accountants

As mentioned, little documentary evidence with mathematical content has been found on papyri or ostraka that might potentially be interpreted as school exercises. The available evidenceFootnote 39 has to be checked against the complex and “fuzzy” background of mathematical education. Apart from a few papyri that might be interpreted as stemming from the study of Euclid’s Elements and therefore as belonging to the “secondary” level, several tables of multiplication and fractions have also been retrieved. But the problem is whether these writing exercises belonged to the elementary level, or whether they should be interpreted, as Cribiore argues,Footnote 40 as belonging to a more specialized curriculum for scribes. Written exercises in calculation, especially addition, would by contrast be the exception rather than the rule: elementary operations were probably taught and practiced orally or with an abacus. More advanced exercises might have been executed by writers and calculators already in training, according to the quality of their writing. Because mastering such skills seemed alien to the spirit and contents of “secondary” teaching, this aspect of education might be plausibly interpreted as the production of advanced slaves trained to be notarii (professional scribes) or calculatores (accountants) who were completing a professional training. Not surprisingly, given the general background and nature of the so-called “elementary” level of teaching as well as uncertainties about its real nature, the mathematical documentation which might be considered “scholastic” is no less fuzzy and uncertain. Part of it, though, might correspond to a specialized curriculum concerning people (including slaves) with a low social status.

In any case, the complete classification and study of those fragments is still an open question, and the achievement of positive results through such a study remains uncertain because of the small number of such documents. Here, the interesting consequence of this general scarcity of sources on the practical dimension of the teaching of mathematics, especially at an elementary level, is the confirmation that our documentation is strongly biased. By contrast, sources for the idealized curricula are much richer and substantial for Greco-Roman antiquity. Among these sources are highly sophisticated treatises (like Plato’s Republic or, much later, the commentaries of Proclus), prefaces and introductions (which convey a sense of the didactic tradition), or pedagogically structured treatises (like for Ptolemy’s Almagest). The variety of these idealized approaches is too vast to be summarized here, and many good studies are available on the subject.

However, one revealing aspect of these works (especially within the prefaces) demands consideration here, namely, the target audience. The target audience refers to the milieu that might have been concerned with these ideals and also, to some extent, that were represented by them: defining an ideal curriculum expressed the shared cultural values that defined not only the milieu but also its raison d’être. One classical example is provided by the case of ancient astrology. For the ancients, astrology implied a demanding and complete training and the mastery of a sophisticated cannon and detailed techniques.Footnote 41 In general, then, the definition of a culture, including an idealized training system, constituted part of the social identity in antiquity. The various educated circles potentially connected with such a self-definition, and the culture of which might have included some mathematical training, merit a brief review.

5.4.2 Mathematical Training as Part of Philosophical Education

That mathematical subjects might have been considered appropriate for a philosophical curriculum, either an ideal one (as in Plato’s Republic) or a real one (as with the late Platonists like Iamblichus in the fourth century, or Syrianus and Proclus in the fifth century), is a fact so obvious that it is impossible to review exhaustively the wide range of philosophical positions and schools for which this idea was meaningful.Footnote 42 In this long story, Plato and the varied company of Platonists are well represented. Despite the breadth of the topic, the historical importance of three particular ideals merits their acknowledgment and exposition.

The first two of these ideals can probably be regarded as varieties of Platonism. The first ideal is neo-Pythagorean, represented in the second century by Nicomachus and Theon of Smyrna, whose treatises focused on so-called neo-Pythagorean arithmetic and represent a sophisticated philosophical project. Theon particularly relies on a coherent organization of mathematical knowledge, especially the four sciences (arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, and music), which later formed the scholastic quadrivium at the edge of the Middle Ages (Hadot 2005, Chaps. III and IV; Vitrac 2005).

The second ideal is that of the Ptolemaic philosophical way of life, centered on the study of mathematics, especially the kind of mathematics related to the movements of the stars and apt to bring the soul of the philosopher closer to this cosmic movement (Taub 1993, Chap. 2 and 5; Sidoli 2004; Feke and Jones 2010; Bernard 2010). While this ideal is basically Platonic in spirit, it does not subordinate the study of mathematics to higher studies (like dialectic) but, on the contrary, recommends mathematics as the highest philosophical study above all others. The Almagest, accordingly, is structured as the basis of such a philosophical study and elevation of the mind. This ideal, associated with this impressively well-organized exposition of ancient astronomy in the Almagest, proved to be highly influential throughout Late Antiquity, the Middle Ages, and up to the early modern period.

The last philosophical ideal is that of Isocrates, Socrates’ other disciple besides Plato. Isocrates proved to be influential on the founders of classical Latin rhetoric, Cicero and Quintilianus. In Isocrates’s philosophy, which is not meant as a system but as a particular way to cultivate discourses, mathematical training is essential not for its contents but for the effect it possesses as a training device, leading the student to analogous but higher studies. He therefore formed the ideal of mathematics as a preparatory stage in rhetorical education.Footnote 43

5.4.3 Mathematical Training as Part of an Astrological and Astronomical Training

If Ptolemy’s ideal can be viewed as one legacy of the literature of philosophy because of his explicit or implicit references to the “grand” philosophical literature (Plato, Aristotle, the Stoics), it might be also be understood in relation to the tradition and culture shared by ancient astrologers. Within the curriculum and ideal training of astrologers, as expressed in Vettius Valens, Firmicus Maternus, Ptolemy, or other authors, calculation of the positions of stars in order to establish an astrological chart is described by these authorsFootnote 44 as an indispensable first step in the standard training of an astrologer, which expanded to include mastering a body of knowledge that enabled him to interpret the sublunary significance of the astronomical phenomena (Bernard 2010).

Among these ancient representations of astrological training, one recorded in Ptolemy’s so-called Tetrabiblos is probably the most sophisticated. Here, the astronomical knowledge necessary for the computation is represented not only as an indispensable part of the science concerning the “physical” effects of planetary positions on sublunary events but also as a science desirable in itself (with a reference to the Almagest, which presents itself as a self-contained treatise). This simultaneously coherent and “bivalent” system is probably an extreme element within the spectrum of approaches to astrology in the same period. Papyrological evidence has clarified that Greco-Roman astrologers had recourse to calculation techniques other than the cinematic tables advocated by Ptolemy (Jones 1999). Nonetheless, Ptolemy’s astronomical text became the subject of commentaries (by Pappus of Theon) by the fourth century, thus consecrating the pedagogical ideal imbedded in the Almagest and advancing it into new directions.Footnote 45 The importance of Ptolemy’s works lies precisely in how he turned a technical treatise of astronomy into classical knowledge, liable to the activities of commentary (Jones 1999, 160ff).

The contents of the commentaries on Ptolemy’s Almagest and Handy Tables are only partly edited, as are the scholia to these texts and their commentaries (Tihon 1992). Most of these probably reflect pedagogical activities, the precise nature of which is difficult to reconstitute even if their existence is beyond doubt. The use of geometrical diagrams to explain or detail procedures, the explanation given on “elementary” operations in the sexagesimal system, or the many references to mnemonic schemas most probably reflect teaching activities oriented toward the appropriation of the complex contents of Ptolemy’s works (Tihon 1992).

5.4.4 Mathematical Training as Part of the Training of Land Surveyors, Engineers, and Architects

Our knowledge of Greco-Roman technology and its specialists, if and when such specialists existed, is complicated by the impressively diverse state of our sources, the differences in the social status of their authors, and the variety of points of view on and classifications of the related subject (Cuomo 2007). Besides highly influential and extant works like Vitruvius’s De Architectura, some of the sources on these domains, like the pseudo-Heronian and metrological corpus in Greek or the corpus of land surveyors (corpus agrimensorum = CA) in Latin, have survived in such a state of confusion that the study, attribution, and characterization of their contents remain a work in progress.Footnote 46 Even an attempt to draw sharp distinctions between architecture and the construction of machines for land surveying, for example, leads quickly to thorny problems.Footnote 47 Also, the social status of the authors or readership of the related treatises is far from clear. Thus, if there is little doubt that some authors of gromatic literatureFootnote 48 identified themselves as belonging to a well-defined profession (mensores), others, like Frontinus or Vitruvius, had a higher social status with political responsibilities and thus treated a wide range of technical subjects. Even among “professional” Roman land surveyors working during the Roman Empire, there are good reasons to think there was a significant variety of functions and social status with different types of training (Hinrichs 1989, pp. 171–174).

Thus, for the Roman land surveyors working during the imperial period (from which most of our information comes), Hinrichs proposes to distinguish between four categories of mensores, according to their function and social positions: land surveyors (a) who served in the army, (b) who were in the service of the emperor, (c) who were employed (or enslaved) by municipalities, and (d) who were private or independent. The first must have been trained within the army, according to a specific tradition about which we have no details. As for the imperial functionaries, Hinrichs speculates that their typically Greek names and the existence of a Greek “technical” tradition of land surveying indicate that they were slaves or freedmen who received their training in Alexandria; the specific “civil” curriculum of the two last categories is unknown, but there is a good chance that the contents of the CA were actually developed and/or used in this context.

Indeed, while the sources are incredibly varied and complex, there is no doubt that a significant portion related to pedagogical purposes, ideals, or realities.Footnote 49 Furthermore, part of the corresponding training included mathematical skills and knowledge of astronomy, geodesy, land surveying, measurement problems, and calculating techniques (Chouquer and Favory 2001, pp. 64–94). Finally, the contents of this corpus were influential on medieval and Renaissance mathematics teaching, and their importance cannot be underestimated.

For the sake of simplicity, some general features of these sources and their underlying teaching background may be sketched broadly. First, these sources contain idealized representations of curricula, like the sophisticated discussions of De Architectura, book I and book IX, or Pappus’s Mathematical Collection VIII, which might be partly derived from the lost introduction to Hero’s Mechanika. These texts significantly characterize mathematical skills as being basically dependent on the wider culture of the architect and useful for that culture. Such discussions about the utility of mathematical training within a larger intellectual framework are also characteristic of the introductory material contained in the Greek metrological corpus and in some prefaces in the CA. Vitruvius and Pappus/Hero also insist on the importance of developing creative skills which combine theoretical prerequisites with practical skills.

This last point relates to a second feature of the aforementioned sources: significant parts of these sources are organized as series of problems often arranged in order of growing complexity. This organization bridges from simple, practical motivations to more theoretical or didactic concerns. Problems such as measurement are typically accompanied by algorithms for calculation generally associated with pedagogical activities or purposes, even though the exact connection may not be obvious at the elementary level of teaching.

The third feature has been mentioned already: these corpuses survived in a state of deep confusion and disorder, often explained by the fact that the original texts were significantly changed and reorganized throughout the course of their history, sometimes for pedagogical purposes. Indeed, it is sometimes easier to situate and identify these reorganizations and purposes – for example, late Neoplatonists reworked the metrological corpusFootnote 50 – than it is to reconstitute the extent and purpose of the original sources. The same remark potentially holds for the question of illustrations, which are numerous in the CA. Some of these might come from original sources, but many others might have been added later, some for pedagogical purposes.

Finally, scholars often note that these corpuses are often missing significant parts. In the case of Latin agrimensores, clear allusions frequently occur to lost Greek technical treatises on related subjects. Hero’s Dioptra is often mentioned as a possible source, or at least as a treatise similar in kind to this lost material, but in all probability this is only the tip of the iceberg. This is a good example of a domain for which we might well have lost the majority of material available in antiquity.

5.4.5 Mathematical Training as Part of an Unknown Culture of Arithmetical Problem-Solving

Finally, Diophantus’s Arithmetica, one of the most mysterious mathematical treatises of antiquity, must be addressed. Although there is no certainty, the treatise may have been composed in Late Antiquity, around the third century, yet its author is unknown. The treatise contains 13 books of arithmetical problems (statements and solutions) arranged in progressive order; six books are extant in Greek and four more have been found in Arabic translation. The long preface survives in Greek and is structured around a didactic project: to enable the reader of the treatise to develop the capacity for invention in arithmetical problems (Arithm. 2.3–13). The problems and their treatments are indeed arranged in an order that enables the acquisition of a whole range of specific techniques useful for the solution of problems (Bernard and Christianidis 2011, part 4). Moreover, the reference to the rhetorical notion of invention (heurêsis) points toward the influence of higher culture and rhetorical training on the structure of the treatise. According to Diophantus’s own words, his whole treatment is organized as paving a way (hodos) to the reader, an example that he might imitate (Christianidis 2007; Bernard and Christianidis 2011, part 5; Bernard 2011).

There is little doubt that the treatise directly relates to a clearly defined didactic strategy akin to the techniques used in ancient rhetorical training. What remains almost entirely absent from the picture is the larger background constituted by the arithmetical problems studied within the “logistic tradition.” This expression usually refers to the problem-solving and calculation tradition relative to the kind of arithmetical problems practiced for millennia in ancient Mesopotamia or ancient Egypt or afterwards in the Middle Ages. But, as far as Greco-Roman antiquity is concerned, we have only hints and desperately few documents claiming that such a tradition existedFootnote 51: the bulk of it has disappeared. Diophantus’s problems might be interpreted as “abstract” problems akin to the scholastic and ad hoc rhetorical problems invented for the sake of rhetorical training.

Diophantus’s Arithmetica, therefore, might be the tip of yet another iceberg, the splendid and isolated outcome of a much larger and widespread tradition of arithmetical teaching through problem-solving, for which there is almost no trace at present.