1 How should we theorize and write?

As members of the socio-ecological practice research (SEPR) community, we are committed to the mission of cultivating and celebrating topnotch scholarship in Ecopracticology—the study of socio-ecological practice (Xiang 2019a, p. 4, b). We are as such committed to both developing theories of socio-ecological practice that are true and useful to the people we are privileged to serve—socio-ecological practitioners, scholar-practitioners, and fellow scholars (Xiang 2019b, pp. 7–9), and writing articles that, beside ourselves, others will also read and admire (Xiang 2019a, p. 4). But how should we theorize and write to fulfill these commitments? My response is terse: theorize from good practice for good practice; write in small words for big circles. It is inspired by two legendary scholars and examples of their topnotch scholarship.

2 An example of Aristotelian theorizing: from good practice for good practice

Two thousand four hundred years ago on the Isle of Lesbos in Greece, Greek philosopher Aristotle (384–322 B.C.) spent time observing how the local masons improvised in measuring the circumference of stone columns. This, according to American scholars Barry Schwartz and Kenneth Sharpe, is in fact part of his fieldwork on the construct of phronesis (practical wisdom).

About this instance of Aristotelian theorizing, write Barry Schwartz and Kenneth Sharpe in their 2010 book Practical Wisdom: The Right Way to Do the Right Thing (Schwartz and Sharpe 2010, pp. 28–29; italics and parentheses by the author):

Aristotle was particularly fascinated with how the masons on the Isle of Lesbos used rulers. A normal, straight-edged ruler was of little use to the masons who were carving round columns from slabs of stone and needed to measure the circumference of the columns. Unless you bent the ruler. Which is exactly what the masons did. They fashioned a flexible ruler out of lead, a forerunner of today’s tape measure. For Aristotle, knowing how to bend the rule to fit the circumstance was exactly what practical wisdom (phronesis) was all about. … [T]he masons of Lesbos didn’t bend the rule to cheat or deceive. They bent the rule to do what was right, and to do it well.

Aristotle also spent time in Athens, Greece, watching how the blacksmiths, boat pilots, carpenters, and shoemakers improvised in their work (Schwartz and Sharpe 2010, p. 28). Like the masons on the Isle of Lesbos, these craftsmen too must improvise because neither was their work “governed by systematically applying rules or following rigid procedures. The materials they worked with were too irregular, and each task posed new problems.” (Ibid.)Footnote 1

From these observations, Aristotle discerned that the ways the craftsmen improvised in their practices illuminate what phronesis is, how it differs from and relates to the other virtue sophia (theoretical wisdom).Footnote 2 And more importantly, “Aristotle thought the choices craftsmen made in acting on the material world provided clues to the kind of know-how citizens needed to make moral choices in the social world” (Schwartz and Sharpe 2010, p. 28, italic by the author). Later in Nicomachean Ethics (book V, chapter 10), he used what he observed and discerned from the stone-cutting practice of the masons, known later as Aristotle’s Lesbian rule,Footnote 3 to illuminate the social practice of fair justice (DeCoursey 2011, p. 293; James 2016, p. 19). In making the argument that to be fair, rules or standards should be adaptable to specific circumstances, he offered an eloquent simile (Aristotle 1999, p. 84; parenthesis by the author):

For the standard applied to the indefinite is itself indefinite, as the lead standard is in Lesbian building, where it is not fixed, but adapts itself to the shape of the stone; similarly, a (judicial) decree is adapted to fit its objects.

3 Inspirations we should act on

3.1 The approach of theorizing from good practice for good practice

In this example, Aristotle first induced a general descriptive theory of practice (Aristotle’s Lesbian rule) through observation and contemplation of craftsmen’s efficacious and righteous practices—theorizing from good practiceFootnote 4; he then extended the theory to the judicial field as he deduced that it would have the prescriptive power to inform and inspire judicial practitioners to be efficacious and righteous in their practice—theorizing for good practice. From such “a lively interplay … between descriptive and prescriptive theory,” as American legal scholar Roger Fisher calls it (Fisher 1983, p. 151), emerged an even more general theory of practice that remains true to the craftsmen and is useful—directly relevant, immediately actionable, and foreseeably efficacious (Xiang 2019a, p. 4, b, p. 9)—for the judicial practitioners. This effective approach to developing true and useful theories of practice has in fact been instrumental to several contemporary scholarly works on socio-ecological practice.Footnote 5 We should officially adopt it to our repertoire of socio-ecological practice research methodologies.

3.2 The underlying premises

Adopting the preceding approach requires our acceptance of its underlying premises. These premises would have served Aristotle in the above example and have been advocated by contemporary scholars on various occasions without acknowledging him as an intellectual forebear. Below is a compiled partial list of these premises with some of their advocates in parentheses. In reading it, one may benefit from the above example by using “craftsmen” in place of “practitioners” and “Aristotle” “academic theoretician.”

  1. 1.

    Practitioners are theorists of their practice (Argyris and Schön 1974, pp. 7–8; Bolan 1980, pp. 271–272; Couclelis 1991, p. 383). A practitioners’ theory of practice is a combination of beliefs, ideas, policies, procedures, and rationales about what to do and how to act in each concrete situation to achieve an intended consequence, and why (Argyris and Schön 1974, pp. 6–12; Bolan 1980, pp. 263–264; Couclelis 1991, pp. 382–383)Footnote 6;

  2. 2.

    In each concrete situation, practitioners encounter the world as an irreducible totality and must think holistically and act pragmatically (Argyris and Schön 1974, pp. 7–8; Bolan 1980, p. 272; Mao 1937, pp. 296–297; Sandberg and Tsoukas 2011, pp. 341–343; Yan 2019, pp. 2–3);

  3. 3.

    As such, their theories of practice necessarily differ from theories of practice by academic theoreticians and definitely differ from theories of science, pure or applied (Argyris and Schön 1974, pp. 7–8; Bolan 1980, p. 263; Couclelis 1991, p. 383; Sandberg and Tsoukas 2011, pp. 338–339; Schön 2001, p. 191; Van de Ven 2007, pp. 3–6; Xiang 2017, pp. 2242–2243, 2019b, p. 9, d, p. 364; Yan 2019, pp. 1, 3–4);

  4. 4.

    Practitioners’ theories of practice, when worked well in concrete situations, are inspirational and informative to those academic theoreticians who, like Aristotle, are interested in developing general theories of practice—academics’ theories of practice.Footnote 7 They are therefore study-worthy (Couclelis 1991, p. 383; Forester 2017, pp. 283–284; Innes 1995, p. 183; Mao 1937, p. 299; Xiang 2019b, pp. 8–10, c);

  5. 5.

    Academics’ theories of practice derived from practitioners’ theories of practice describe what practitioners did in concrete situations and explain why; they may also prescribe how other practitioners in comparable situations should act and justify why. They are most likely to be true and useful because they have the capability of presenting truth and the power of informing and inspiring practitioners in other concrete situations to act efficaciously and righteously (Innes 1995, p. 183; Mao 1937, p. 300; Xiang 2019b, pp. 8–10, 2019c).

Admittedly, we accept and uphold these premises not just for the “utilitarian” purpose of adopting an effective approach to theorizing. More importantly, they lay the very foundation for the pragmatic way of knowing in ecopracticology. [For the six strategies of the pragmatic way of knowing, see Xiang (2019b, pp. 10–11).]

3.3 A role model

The example renders a vivid image of the quintessential Aristotle as described by various Aristotle scholars (in parentheses): a scholar who builds theories based on direct observation of the real-world phenomena (Anagnostopoulos 2009, p. 5; Hammersley 2010, p. 396; North 2005, p. 91); a thinker who values both practical action and theoretical contemplation (Lear 2009, p. 388; North 2005, p. 93); and a writer who uses natural language to present the world of phenomena he observed and elucidates with the persuasive aspects of his observations (Keyt 2009, p. 32; North 2005, p. 93; Rapp 2009, p. 595). All these prodigious qualities remain invaluable in the twenty-first century and are highly desirable in our socio-ecological practice research. Aristotle is a role model we should follow with great reverence.

4 An example of Smithian writing: in small words for big circles

Between 1767 and 1773, Scottish philosopher and economist Adam Smith (1723–1790) settled in his hometown Kirkcaldy, Scotland, devoting much of the time to writing An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (abbreviated as the Wealth of Nations, or WN) (Phillipson 2010, pp. 201–202). His ambition was to develop a book for a broad audience in political as well as intellectual circles “to facilitate the commercial policy in his own Great Britain” and “to contribute to the progress of humankind” (Evensky 2016, p. 68). This project of writing “for big circles” (Billig 2013, p. 15), according to Jerry Phillipson, a leading scholar of the Scottish Enlightenment, turned out to be a demanding undertaking (Phillipson 2010, p. 201). Among other challenges, explains Phillipson in his 2010 biography Adam Smith: An Enlightened Life (Ibid., pp. 216–217; parentheses by the author):

In writing the Wealth of Nations Smith faced the same problem he had encountered in writing the Theory of Moral Sentiments (first published in 1759): developing lectures originally designed for university students for a different sort of readership. … The case of the Wealth of Nations was (nevertheless) more complicated(,) … (in that) his political economy (the Wealth of Nations was written about) was deeply embedded in a system of moral philosophy, jurisprudence and politics about which most of his (nonacademic) readers knew nothing. The question was, how much of it did they need to know if they were to make sense of his political economy? Smith’s answer was, not much.Footnote 8

To keep this not much promise, Smith made every effort to write “in small words” for perspicuity (Billig 2013, p. 15).Footnote 9 Perspicuity is the quality of being perspicuous—plain to the understanding because of clarity, elegance, precision, and simplicity of presentation.Footnote 10 He, among other things, reduced the long, subtle lectures he had delivered at the University of Glasgow to “a series of strategically placed aphorisms and aperçus” (Phillipson 2010, p. 217); examined “carefully, and often painstakingly chosen historical examples” from Scotland and the colonial America (Ibid., pp. 227–228); employed figures of speech, primarily metaphors plus a few similes, “to add meaning and interest in his sentences” (Kennedy 2017, p. 61); and used “well-turned phrases” (Heilbroner 1999, p. 52) and “non-technical words that he thought all educated readers would understand” (Billig 2013, p. 15).

His hard work paid off nicely. The first edition of the Wealth of Nations was sold out in 6 months (Rae 1895, p. 285) and “immediately acquired a significant readership in political and intellectual circles in Edinburgh, London and Paris” (Phillipson 2010, p. 1). The then British Prime Minister, Lord North, regarded the book as “a mine of suggestions” for “fresh, convenient and easy means of increasing the revenue” and benefitted from the book in preparing the budgets for the years 1777 and 1778 (Rae 1895, p. 320). Many members in the British governments knew and admired the book and recognized its public value (Rae 1895, p. 321; Phillipson 2010, p. 267). Various statesmen turned to Smith for advice on issues pertaining to the war with the colonial America and the trade with Ireland (McKenna 2006, p. 21). The book itself was recognized as a masterpiece of “the most profound ideas expressed in the most perspicuous language” [Gibbon 1776, cited in Rae (1895, p. 287); see also footnote 9 in this essay]. It ultimately becomes his magnum opus (Heilbroner 1986, p. 149) and, more importantly, a classic book on political economy with lasting impacts (Ross 2010, pp. 445–451).Footnote 11

5 Inspirations we should act on

5.1 The strategy of writing in small words for big circles

In this example, Adam Smith meticulously used a variety of “small words” techniques in his book writing for a broad audience in “big circles”: aphorisms, aperçus, examples, figures of speech, plain language, and non-technical words.Footnote 12 The outcome was brilliant, influence significant. We should follow this effective strategy in fulfilling our commitment to writing for a broad audience in and beyond the socio-ecological practice research community.Footnote 13

5.2 A perspicuous writing style

According to American economist and historian Robert Heilbroner, a commonplace about the Wealth of Nations is that it “is not a wholly original book, but it is unquestionably a masterpiece” (Heilbroner 1999, p. 51). “There is a long line of observers before Smith who have approached his understanding of the world: Locke, Steuart, Mandeville, Petty, Cantillon, Turgot, not to mention Quesnay and Hume…” (Ibid.)Footnote 14 No wonder many Smith’s contemporaries were so surprised with the immediate success of the book, including his best friend and mentor David Hume (McKenna 2006, p. 20; Phillipson 2010, p. 1).

But then, what had made “very popular” such an unoriginal book that “contained very little which was particularly new”? (McKenna 2006, p. 20) The perspicuous style of Smith’s writing stands out from the crowd, asserts American rhetorician Stephen McKenna in his 2006 book Adam Smith: The Rhetoric of Propriety. “[Q]uite likely a significant cause of this surprising success (of the Wealth of Nations) was the style of Smith’s writing, which was, like that of his previous book (the Theory of Moral Sentiments), widely remarked to be lucid and compelling” (McKenna 2006, p. 20; parentheses by the author).

To be sure, not only did his perspicuous writing style help boost the book’s popularity in big circles, but it contributed substantially to the making of this masterpiece. Commends Robert Heilbroner in his 1999 book The Worldly Philosophers: The Lives, Times, and Ideas of the Great Economic Thinkers, “[F]or all its weightiness, the text is shot through with insights, observations, and well-turned phrases that imbue this great lecture with life” (Heilbroner 1999, p. 52). With this perspicuous writing style, “where others had fished here and there, Smith spread his net wide; where others had clarified this and that issue, Smith illuminated the entire landscape” (Ibid., p. 51). His writing style as such “become(s) an essential part of the language of (his) political economy itself” (Phillipson 2010, p. 217; parentheses by the author). Many well-turned phrases or passages are so striking and memorable that they have become iconic and immortal ever since. The “invisible hand” of market and the famous passage “It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest” are but two most famous examples.Footnote 15

Perspicuous writing matters—it can make a huge difference. We should adopt this style of writing without question.

5.3 A careful and diligent writer

Style is the man, one’s chosen style of writing reflects one’s essential characteristics.Footnote 16 “Adam Smith was a very careful writer and not given to sloppiness in his written composition,” writes British economist Gavin Kennedy in his 2017 book An Authentic Account of Adam Smith (p. 44). “For Smith, perspicuity was the gold standard” for all his works (Ibid., p. 43). “To meet his own high standards, he took the trouble to compose and recompose whatever he wrote” (Ibid., p. 39). In a letter dated March 18, 1788, writes Smith, “I am a slow, very slow workman, who do and undo everything I write at least half a dozen times before I can be tolerably pleased with it” (cited in Kennedy 2017, p. 39; McKenna 2006, p. 23)Footnote 17 In pursuit of greater perspicuity, he kept revising his two major works diligently during his lifetime and produced substantially revised and expanded editions of the Wealth of Nations (5 editions in 12 years) and the Theory of Moral Sentiments (6 editions in 31 years) (Kennedy 2017, pp. 11, 60, 62; McKenna 2006, p. 23).Footnote 18

To become a careful and diligent writer who brings writing to life, we should follow his example.

6 Are we ready to act?

There is nothing as inspirational as a good example.Footnote 19 To fulfill our commitments to developing true and useful theories of socio-ecological practice and writing for a broad audience, I believe that we should act on the inspirations from the classic examples of Aristotelian theorizing and Smithian writing—theorize from good practice for good practice and write in small words for big circles.

But are we ready to act?

For many of us, to act on these inspirations requires not just a change in ways of knowing and writing, which admittedly is a huge undertaking in its own right; it also demands a personal reorientation in academic life. Consider the cases of Aristotle and Adam Smith. They lived in an academic world where, as British historian Paul Johnson describes in his 1992 book The Birth of the Modern: World Society 18151830, “[p]hysics and chemistry, science and engineering, literature and philosophy, art and industrial design, theory and practice–all constituted a continuum of knowledge and skill, within which men roamed freely. The notion of separate, compartmentalized ‘disciplines,’ later imposed by universities, did not yet exist” (Johnson 1992, p. 543). Like many great minds in their times, both were solitary scholars of self-directed scholarship, in that they pursued intellectual interests where the interests took them and communicated their ideas as widely as possible in both speaking and writing (Billig 2013, p. 15; Hutchison 1976, pp. 511–512; Taleb 2012, p. 227). The academic world we live in today is so much different: among other things, disciplinary divides seem insuperable, research and publications are being mass produced, we are nurtured “to write badly” or otherwise punished (Billig 2013, pp. 12–39 and 40–66; Pinker 2014; Robinson 2017, 2019), and scholarly journals are so specialized that “[t]he words (in the articles published) have become longer and the circles, in which they circulate, have become smaller” (Billig 2013, p. 15; parentheses by the author). For some of us, therefore, to follow the examples set by Aristotle and Adam Smith means to step out of our comfort zone which we have worked so hard to get into; for others, especially younger generations, it means to take an unfamiliar detour from a direct, established course. Are we still ready to act?

7 Yes, we are ready!

There are two apparent reasons.

7.1 We have good examples to follow

Of those contemporary scholars and scholar-practitioners whose works contributed to the scholarship in ecopracticology [see the partial list in footnote 5; and in Xiang (2019b, p. 9)], some have reoriented and even reinvented themselves one or multiple times on their academic journeys.Footnote 20 In doing so, they in fact followed in the footsteps of many intellectual ancestors who had done exactly the same: American pragmatist William James (1842–1910), German-American design scholar Horst Rittel (1930–1990), American planning scholar Melvin Webber (1920–2006), and systems scientist West Churchman (1913–2004), to name just a few.Footnote 21 Collectively, these scholars set powerful examples for us to act boldly yet thoughtfully on the inspirations from the classic examples of Aristotelian theorizing and Smithian writing.

7.2 We have a suitable journal to publish in

Socio-Ecological Practice Research (SEPR) is the home journal of ecopracticology (Xiang 2019b, p. 12). As a one-of-its-kind transdisciplinary journal on practice research, SEPR celebrates and cultivates the Aristotelian–Smithian type of scholarship. This is evident in the following five virtues SEPR articles are expected to possess (Xiang 2019a, p. 4)—the virtues are much in line with those showcased in the two classic examples:

  1. 1.

    attentiveness to the dual ambition of producing new knowledge and improving socio-ecological practice;

  2. 2.

    interest in the usefulness of knowledge;

  3. 3.

    commitment to scholarly rigor;

  4. 4.

    writing with style, accuracy, brevity, and clarity;

  5. 5.

    the quality of international appeal.

Since its debut in 2019, SEPR has been receiving strong support from a growing community of international authors and readers across a wide range of scholarly and practical fields. This is apparent in the articles it published to date and shown in the numbers of article downloads and citations (https://www.springer.com/journal/42532).

In conclusion, the path has been paved; to fulfill our commitments, let’s march on and act together under the banner

from good practice for good practice we theorize; in small words for big circles we write.