1 Adapting philosophy of science to teaching of science students

Practice-oriented philosophers of science have emphasized the need to increase the relevance of philosophy of science for science and society (Ankeny et al., 2011; SPSP Mission statement, 2020; Soler et al., 2014). This aim is increasingly pursued through philosophical field work in scientific laboratories and collaborations with scientists (Brister & Frodeman, 2020; Laplane et al., 2019). But another important avenue for increasing scientific and societal relevance is through teaching of science students. Just as practice-orientation in research requires changes in focus and method, the didactic transposition of philosophy of science to science students requires adapting what and how we teach. We offer reflections and suggestions towards this end, based on our experience since 2005 with teaching mandatory courses in philosophy of science to undergraduate students enrolled in BSc programs at the University of Copenhagen.

Philosophy of science courses of 7,5 ECTS credits are mandatory for all university students in Denmark.Footnote 1 These courses are listed on the curriculum as “philosophy of [scientific discipline]”. This signals that the courses are not intended as generic courses for students from multiple disciplines (cf. Grüne-Yanoff, 2014), but instead have the purpose of promoting critical philosophical reflection through engagement with the subject matter of the specific program. One important reason is that the study programs in Denmark differ from university-level educational programs in many other countries, such as the US, by requiring students to specialize in a particular discipline from the outset. While national guidelines for philosophy of science courses exist, a critical task in our course design is to adapt the content and format of our teaching to increase the relevance to students in specific science programs. This involves considerations about which topics are relevant to specific groups of students, and how to best teach these.

Scholars before us have encouraged philosophers of science to critically reflect on whether their own topics of professional interest are equally well-suited for teaching scientists and science students. For example, Grüne-Yanoff (2014) argues that some philosophical topics are not equally relevant for science students. Boniolo and Campaner (2020) have similarly emphasized the need to tailor the teaching of philosophy of science to the needs of students or practitioners within the life and health sciences. This paper provides additional support for these views and pushes further towards practice-orientation by considering how we should teach in relation to science students’ modes of study and specific educational contexts. We do so by emphasizing the benefits of case-based teaching and active learning approaches (see also Prince & Felder, 2006; Terry, 2012; Bursten & Finkelstein, 2018). Case-based active teaching involves alternating between teacher-structured scaffolding and student-centered work on concrete cases within their own discipline (El-Hani et al., 2020). Our aim is not to conduct a systematic review of the case-based approach, compared to other alternatives. Rather, we provide suggestions for how this approach can be used in philosophy of science courses, by introducing abstract philosophical topics and concepts in connection to cases that already interest the students. The paper offers reflections on the background for this choice, reports on our experiences, and provides suggestions for cases that we invite readers to try in their own teaching, when relevant.

As our starting point, we take an analytical concept from science education called the “implied student” (Ulriksen, 2009). Similar to Iser’s (1984) concept of the “implied reader” in the context of literary theory, the implied student refers to the tacit assumptions about students to which both teachers and students try to align their activities. As an analytical tool, the implied student not only serves to expose presuppositions we have about students in structuring teaching, but also helps to show how “structure and mode of teaching are dependent on students being willing and able to comply with the structure” (Ulriksen, 2009). It highlights how the space for learning is mutually constrained by the implicit expectations of teachers and by the ability of students to recognize and meet those expectations. Ulriksen uses the concept to reflect on academic training in disciplinary educational structures (Kuhn, 1962/1970) and to consider the academic socialization involved in education, which involves a “hidden curriculum” of social rules (Jackson 1968/1990). We find the concept useful as a reminder that any course design reflects assumptions about the students – assumptions which may need to be reconsidered when adapting philosophy of science courses to science students. In particular, we cannot assume that science students will be interested in all the canonical themes of traditional philosophy of science courses, nor that they are familiar with the teaching format or expectations of such a course.

The science students we encounter in the specialized BSc programs are often confused about what to expect from a philosophy of science course. Since content and form typically differ greatly from other courses in their curriculum, a lack of clarity about the intended learning outcomes (ILOs) can lead to frustration and reduced motivation. Attempts to address this problem can benefit from critically examining students’ expectations, those held personally by students and through their (implicit) expression in the study program (Ulriksen, 2009). The course design should fit with students’ ideas about what it means to study and what they perceive as relevant for their current and future practice. Moreover, teachers should make the expectations and learning objectives of philosophy of science courses clear to students, e.g., by presenting concrete examples of how philosophy of science can deepen important discussions within or about their own field.

An oft-stated aim of philosophy of science courses is to make science students better scientists, i.e., to make science students more critically reflective of their own scientific research practices (Boniolo & Campaner, 2020; Grüne-Yanoff, 2014; Price, 2012). We are supportive of this claim, which also motivates our own teaching. At the same time, closer consideration of the implied student in this approach calls for further reflection on this assumed aim. First, attention to science “in practice” reveals a variety of research approaches, which broaden and blur the category of “better scientist”. Second, science students today have educational goals that differ from, and extend beyond, preparation for a research career. Assuming that all science students want to become researchers may alienate those who are instead aiming to pursue careers in industry, policy, consulting, or teaching. Thus, it is important to consider how philosophers of science can be designed in a way that is relevant for the existing diversity of study practices and anticipated career trajectories.

In the following, we explain how we adapt the teaching of philosophy of science to science students to meet their needs. Our suggestions should be understood within the context of an educational system in which philosophy of science courses are mandatory, and we therefore begin by putting our own teaching practices in context. Regardless of this special context, we hope that reflecting on our experiences are useful for others who teach philosophy of science to science students. We clarify the background for our choice of case-based teaching in Sect. 3 and provide examples of cases taught in Sect. 4. Section 5 offers concluding remarks.

2 Teaching philosophy of science in Denmark

In a European setting, the relevance of philosophy of science for science students was recognized by the European Qualifications Framework for Lifelong Learning in 2008, which included “critical understanding of theories and principles” and “critical awareness of knowledge issues in a field” as learning outcomes for bachelor’s and master’s degrees, respectively (European Commission, 2008, p. 18). However, no general overview exists of how this part of the framework has been implemented across the European Union that spans quite different systems for higher education.

In Denmark, our local setting, a 2003 parliamentary debate prompted an agreement between the national universities and the Ministry of Education to introduce a mandatory philosophy of science course into all bachelor programs. The intent was to provide students with an opportunity to “qualify their disciplinary specialization by contextualizing it in a larger perspective” and thus to “connect disciplinary questions with interesting and relevant issues of a more general character” (translated from Andersen et al., 2018, p. 24). The courses should therefore cover not only philosophy of science in a strict sense, but also elements that could give students an understanding of their field within society, including the social and ethical responsibility of scientists. Hence, despite their name, the courses were expected to also include history and sociology of science as well as ethics.

National guidelines for philosophy of science courses have been implemented locally at the University of Copenhagen through a generic set of minimal ILOs that all mandatory philosophy of science courses at the Faculty of Science need to fulfill. Importantly, these ILOs differ from traditional philosophy of science courses designed for philosophy students. To illustrate how, Table 1 lists the differences in ILOs for philosophy students (left column) and science students (right column) at the University of Copenhagen. Table 1 shows that in the course for philosophy students, the emphasis is on acquiring competences to provide a systematic analysis of philosophical positions and their historical contexts. This reflects the structuring of teaching according to the assumption that the “implied student” is already interested in, and familiar with, central positions and debates within philosophy. This cannot be assumed for science students. However, science students will be more familiar with advanced methods and concepts in their respective scientific discipline, which can provide an entry for case-based discussions that draw on these experiences (more on this in Sects. 3 and 4). In other words, it is important to keep in mind how the “implied student” may differ in the two contexts.

Table 1 Learning objectives of the mandatory BA course in philosophy of science course in the philosophy program (left) and for science students (right) at the University of Copenhagen

In alignment with these aims, we teach philosophy of science courses targeting students from actuarial science, biochemistry, biology, chemistry, computer science, geography, geology, machine learning and data science, mathematics, mathematics-economy, nanoscience, physics, and sports science at the University of Copenhagen.Footnote 2 Whereas it is an important aim in the course for philosophy students to describe the different modes of knowledge generation in the broader spectrum of the natural sciences, the social sciences, and the arts, we aim to further adapt the generic template to the respective target groups through the design of different courses for students from each discipline.Footnote 3 While all of our courses contain some generic elements (such as responsible conduct in research and practice), we make an effort to design teaching around cases that emphasize the epistemological, ethical, and social aspects of the specific discipline, as well as the institutional history relevant to that discipline.

In summary, our courses are intended to target specific scientific disciplines, and are all situated at the intersection of philosophy of science, history of science, science studies, and ethics. From this position, they aim to prompt critical, philosophical reflection on the specific discipline of study, its central questions and issues, its history, and its role in society. In the following sections, we illustrate some of the considerations we face when designing and teaching these courses and reflect upon the benefits of taking historical and contemporary cases from the specific fields as starting points for philosophical analysis.

3 Reconsidering content and teaching format

How do we ascertain which topics are engaging and relevant for science students in particular disciplines? In our experience, dialogues with students and science colleagues help make the courses more relevant and engaging. In recent years, textbooks in philosophy of science have emerged that are more accessible to science students in general (e.g., Giere et al., 2006; Potochnik et al., 2018), and to specific groups of science students (e.g., Kampourakis & Uller, 2020). Yet, we contend that the relevance of some classical philosophical topics should primarily be considered in relation to how these are taught in the context of a specific science program.

3.1 Teaching traditional topics in new ways

One example of a highly abstract topic primarily of interest to philosophers is the scientific realism/antirealism debate (Grüne-Yanoff, 2014). Yet, philosophers of scientific practice have shown that this debate can be brought to bear on research practice by considering whether and how the aim of truth-seeking is relevant in particular scientific fields and circumstances (Chang, 2012b; Currie, 2018; Potochnik, 2017). A similar approach can be adopted in teaching of philosophy of science. Rather than starting with the abstract philosophical debate on realism/antirealism, a more useful entry point would be to consider relevant discussions within science itself. An example is how scanning tunnelling microscopy (STM) gives us new ways to “see”, manipulate, and think about phenomena at the scale of atoms (Toumey, 2009). In our experience, students in physics and nanoscience can productively draw on their own experiences with advanced microscopy in a discussion of how understanding sometimes is facilitated through translation of numerical data into highly idealized visual images, such as the famous “quantum corral” featured on the cover of Science, 262, 1993 (Crommie et al., 1993).

Another example, taken from the course we teach to geography students, is to introduce students to basic philosophical questions about laws, explanation, and idealization using a contemporary example of a “unified theory of urban living” (Bettencourt & West, 2010). Developed by physicists specializing in complex systems, this theory has been strongly criticized by geographers for its broad generalizations and law-like approach to answering geographical questions (O’Sullivan & Manson, 2015). Cases like this allow students to familiarize themselves with philosophical themes without leaving their disciplinary home ground, thus providing a safe environment for engaging with novel kinds of questions.

The suggestion to reconsider the format, and not only the topic, is equally relevant when teaching ethics. Traditional ethical positions may be experienced as irrelevant to the students’ own practice, if teaching primarily consists of rehearsing “long-standing and insoluble debates among long-dead men” (Bursten & Finkelstein, 2018, p. 1). Of higher relevance to the students is the ability to identify hidden assumptions in ethical argumentation, as well as the capacity to discuss the implications of various views. Bursten and Finkelstein suggest using what they call boundary cases to confront students with examples that promote cognitive conflict. The aim is to compel students to examine unexpected ramifications and unwelcome consequences of their own viewpoints. We believe that these competences can be trained while also reestablishing the lost connection to more abstract theoretical frameworks in ethics.

To exemplify, Green has in collaboration with colleagues in sports science designed exercises inspired by previous masters’ projects. Ethical frameworks were discussed in relation to concrete imaginative research projects, including an experimental intervention study on the effects of physical activity to reduce obesity among school children. The students were asked to identify possible ways in which the imagined research projects could harm participants, and to discuss which ethical positions may support such considerations (e.g., deontological ethics or utilitarianism). We found that by drawing on such examples, it is easier for students to recognise the relevance of abstract ethical principles (such as those guiding the Helsinki declaration or data protection laws) for their own practice. The exercise also promoted critical self-reflection on their own assumptions about the research topic. The students were further asked to draft interview questions of relevance for the study of obesity. After reading and discussing text material presenting different views on the topic, the students were surprised to discover that their questions revealed implicit epistemic and normative assumptions about obesity and weight loss. This resonates with Bursten and Finkelstein’s (2018) suggestion that critical reflection can be promoted through examples that uncover and productively challenge the student’s own presuppositions.

The examples above illustrate the difference between what in science education is called deductive and inductive teaching strategies (Prince & Felder, 2006). While the traditional (deductive) approach starts with the history of the philosophical debate and primarily uses cases as illustrations, inductive teaching takes concrete cases or the students’ own practice as the starting point. Inductive strategies lend themselves naturally to active learning approaches. Active learning refers to a spectrum of student-centered approaches, ranging from very “open” approaches, where students formulate their own questions and design their own analysis, to teacher-structured activities involving a mixture of teacher instruction and group work (Hartikainen et al., 2019; Terry, 2012). Active learning involves one or more phases of adidactic teaching (Brousseau, 1997), where the teacher steps back to let the students work on cases or problems on their own.Footnote 4 It is, however, important that teachers instruct and follow up on the exercises, as students may need guidance to see relevant connections to general concepts or themes (El-Hani et al., 2020). Since studies in science education have documented the benefits of active learning approaches (Entwistle, 2009; Freeman et al., 2014; Prince, 2004), we organize our teaching around cases that we expect to already interest the students (see Sect. 4 for further examples).

3.2 Historical and contemporary cases

We view case studies as concrete and authentic problem situations or stories that illustrate the complexity of scientific practice in a manageable way (Allchin, 2013, pp. 39–40). Focusing on cases reawakens a classical debate in philosophy of science about the relation between particular cases and general lessons, as well as considerations about which cases are most fitting for this purpose. Our intention is not to use cases to make inductive inferences about science in general,Footnote 5 but to use these iteratively as mediators between concrete examples and abstract analysis (Chang, 2012a; Nersessian, 1995). Cases can put philosophy of science into context, and make abstract theories more cognitively accessible to students (Herreid et al., 2012). Conversely, abstract philosophical theories and concepts can help deepen the understanding of concrete scientific cases, e.g., by introducing conceptual tools that highlight similarities and differences between cases.

Another debated topic is whether philosophical analysis should primarily examine contemporary or past science (see, e.g., Giere, 1973; Burian, 1977). One argument raised in this debate was that historical cases have a pedagogical advantage because they tend to be less complex than contemporary cases. In contrast, historians of science have warned against “pseudohistorical” presentations of historical cases that reconstruct scientific discoveries as the result of a straightforward scientific methodology (see Allchin, 2013, chapters 4 and 5; Powers, 2020). Such debates emphasize the importance of situating cases in their historical and contemporary scientific contexts, which places new demands on the historical and scientific literacy of philosophy of science teachers. It can be challenging for philosophy teachers to acquire the competences required to discuss scientific cases with science students specialized in the same field, or to make sure that the presentation of a case acknowledges relevant historical nuances. Yet, these challenges can be addressed by training in dual competences or by collaboration on teaching. Our courses are often taught by scholars with dual training in a scientific discipline and philosophy or history, or in philosophy and history of science. Some courses are also taught in collaboration with scientists from the students’ discipline. In the latter case, it is important that both sides of the collaboration are capable of engaging in some detail with both the philosophical and the scientific literature involved, i.e., both parties should have what sometimes is referred to as “interactional expertise” (Collins & Evans, 2002; Goddiksen, 2014; Plasiance, 2020).

Both contemporary and historical cases can be used to stimulate reflections on the characteristics of “science in the making”, as opposed to teaching “ready-made science” (Allchin, 2013; Latour, 1987). Whereas textbooks used in teaching science often present what they take to be uncontroversial exemplar cases of explanations and problem solutions (Kuhn, 1962/1970), contemporary and historical cases provide insights into the tentative and exploratory aspects of knowledge generation. But historical and contemporary cases also have distinct benefits and limitations. Allchin et al. (2014) make a useful comparison of the complementary merits and deficiencies of contemporary and historical cases. Contemporary examples of scientific controversies motivate student engagement through their “here-now” relevance, but are by definition unresolved and open-ended, and therefore not ideal for illustrating how controversies can be settled. Historical cases can be harder to relate to the current practice of the students, but they can foster understanding of how various strategies have been used to manage uncertainties and errors in the past. We elaborate on these points below.

Reassessing historical episodes within their own field from an HPS perspective provides a good way to engage students and improve their understanding of their field’s historical development. First, it can help correct misconceptions created by the way history is presented within the discipline itself. In addition, some characteristics of science that rarely get discussed in science courses can be analyzed in historical case studies, e.g., the social nature of science and the establishing of scientific consensus, failed theories or experiments, or the social, political and moral implications of science. In our experience, science students are very interested in these topics, as they have a direct relevance to their own experience. Historical cases can also “humanize” science by showing the contingent and chaotic process of discovery of even the greatest heroes, who have also run into dead ends on their way. This is an eye-opener to students who often struggle themselves when presented with problems to solve or phenomena to understand (Matthews 2015/1994; Allchin, 2013; Allchin et al., 2014).Footnote 6 Learning how failure and ignorance are integral elements of scientific practice can improve their confidence going forward, and also impact their own self-understanding and future career decisions (Firestein, 2012, 2015).

In our courses, we also use existing and unresolved scientific controversies to stimulate reflection on how regulatory decisions often have to be taken in contexts of scientific uncertainty, and in situations where epistemic and ethical questions are intertwined. For instance, biology students are presented with scientific publications that have different views on whether fish and invertebrates can feel pain. They are asked to discuss the strengths and weaknesses of the methods and evidence presented for the respective claims, as well as the ethical implications of different views. This can lead to stimulating discussions on the possibility of conducting “crucial experiments” in this field and about the possibility of operationalizing seemingly irreducible and difficult concepts such as pain and (animal) sentience. Students are rarely encouraged to ponder such questions in their science courses, and philosophy of science courses can offer a welcome space for such reflections.

3.3 Considering student trajectories

Lastly, to reap the benefits of case-based teaching, an additional level of tailoring to students is required: Among, and even within, undergraduate programs, student profiles and future career plans vary enough to require reflection on how to make philosophical discussions relevant to all of them. All programs, of course, produce candidates for research — either in academic or industrial settings. But some programs also serve other markets, in particular upper secondary education, public administration, and the private sector. In the programs in mathematics at the University of Copenhagen, for instance, we know from directly asking students that some of them wish to become teachers, some to pursue research careers, and most to enter jobs in industry.Footnote 7 Some course topics, such as the reliability of mathematical knowledge, are relevant to all mathematics students, while other topics, such as the historical development of mathematics as a discipline, may be less relevant to some (e.g., students identifying with industry careers). The variety of prospective career trajectories, therefore, should be taken into account when selecting topics and cases.

The diversity of student identities presents new challenges for philosophy of science teachers but also new opportunities for making philosophy of science relevant in multiple contexts. In science education, for instance, philosophy of science has been recognized as an important part of the training of science teachers (Scheffler, 1971; Abd-El-Khalick, 2005; Matthews, 1994/2015), which connects to the widely accepted view that upper secondary school students should not only learn scientific concepts, but also about how scientific knowledge is produced (“nature of science”, or NOS). This perspective has been historically tied to scientific literacy as a broad goal in science education (Hodson, 2014), however, one of the main obstacles to effective inclusion of history and philosophy of science in secondary science classrooms is teachers’ lack of subject knowledge and understanding of how it connects to the scientific content they must teach (Höttecke & Silva, 2011). Thus, philosophy of science can help prepare teachers to convey a better-informed image of science to their students.

For example, philosophy of science courses can provide a forum for students to share and reflect upon their experiences conducting laboratory experiments or making field observations. This can provide practical guidance for how to handle anomalous results in different situations, e.g., in teaching and research contexts where the aims of experiments may differ. Discussion of realistic and tangible case examples can also help them develop the sound judgment needed when the idealized norms of good scientific practice cannot be applied in simple and straightforward ways (Johansen & Christiansen, 2020). Students are also often positively surprised to learn that their own experiences can be used to promote critical reflection on philosophy of science itself. For instance, discussion of the complexity of experimentation and observation can provide a more nuanced perspective on the ideal of reproducibility, which may differ depending on the circumstances and aims of experimentation in different fields (see also Leonelli, 2018; Guttinger, 2020).

Of course, a single course cannot be tailored to the individual interests of each student, and it is also important to build a common professional identity among the students, no matter their career path. But when planning a course, it is crucial to make informed choices to ensure the relevance of the course to the students; simply realizing that not all students wish to pursue academic careers may be eye-opening.

4 Case-based teaching: examples from our courses

In hope of stimulating further discussion and collaboration on developing teaching materials, we present four examples of cases from our courses in further detail. This selection corresponds to the four competences described in the generic template for the learning outcomes (see Table 1, right).

Case 1: Can algorithms predict student dropouts?

In 2014, a student from University of Copenhagen wrote his master’s thesis on the use of machine learning algorithms. As part of the thesis, the student developed an algorithm that could predict if a student in upper secondary school would drop out with about 93% accuracy. The algorithm was trained on performance data and data related to gender, ethnicity and socio-economic background from 72.598 upper secondary students, who had used the learning platform Lectio (Şara et al., 2015). MaCom, the company behind Lectio, had given the master student access to the performance data without consulting with the schools, and MaCom implemented the drop-out prediction algorithm as part of Lectio when it was developed. School administrators, however, protested that their students’ privacy had been violated, and the algorithm was removed from Lectio after a week (Møllerhøj, 2015).

We use the case as a starting point for several important ethical discussions relating to mathematics and computer science. These include: The rights of data subjects (was it acceptable that MaCom used students’ data without their consent?), algorithmic bias (the algorithm includes sensitive information such as gender and ethnicity, but can we know if its training has given it gender or other biases?), and the connection between epistemology and ethics (the utilitarian argument in favor of using the algorithm is confronted with uncertainties about how the algorithm works and affects the behavior of the teachers, students, and administrators interacting with it).

Case 2: Risk assessment and scientific uncertainty

To promote reflection on the societal role of science, several courses include exercises where students discuss how their field can inform risk assessment and political decision making. Biology students watch a video where different stakeholders discuss the results of a cohort study documenting a statistical association between prenatal exposure to a chemical preservative and reduced head circumference of male infants (Lassen et al., 2016). Students in the chemical sciences discuss the merits and problems of estimating toxicity of new chemical compounds from knowledge about structurally similar ones (Bschir, 2017). And physics students discuss the earthquake in L’Aquila in 2009 as a case highlighting the difficult ethical and epistemological choices physicists have to face when they advise the public on the basis of incomplete or unclear data (Hall, 2011). These cases illustrate that waiting for conclusive scientific evidence is often not an option. Students must therefore evaluate different types of evidence (and uncertainty) against the “inductive risks” of assessments that may under- or overestimate potential harm. The cases also raise discussions on whether and how to inform the general public about potential harm and scientific uncertainty, which is challenging in societal contexts where mistrust in science is a pressing concern (see also El-Hani et al., 2020).

Case 3: “Functional” in biochemistry, chemistry, nanoscience

To address the learning goal of being able to “exhibit disciplinary self-understanding and view one’s discipline in relation to bordering disciplines”, students in a course for chemistry, biochemistry, and nanoscience discuss the notion of ‘functional’ from their respective backgrounds, engaging with both commonalities and differences. The case is preceded by brief introductions to the history of the three fields, and is initiated with discussion exercises. We ask the students to reflect upon a well-known concept from their field, and to contrast it with a seemingly similar concept in a neighboring field – in this case the chemical concept of a functional group, the biochemical concept of molecular function, and function in “nanomachines”. The exercise starts out broadly, asking about the roles of these notions in research. The students are often puzzled by this question, albeit in different ways; nanoscience students may see molecular function as the workings of engineerable structures at the nanoscale, while biochemistry students are more interested in the evolution of macromolecular “active sites” than in functional groups. The question “Can the concept of ketone as a functional group be reduced to quantum chemistry or physics?” is then discussed and used to introduce the more general question of how scientific disciplines interact, not only from a positivist perspective on theory reduction, but also integrating contemporary views of disciplines as systems of practice with a variety of interactions (Chang, 2015).

Case 4: Disciplinary and professional identity in computer science

To activate student reflections on the spectrum of science within their own discipline, the tutorials in philosophy of computer science start with an introductory exercise, with 25 students divided into five groups. Each group receives one of five short primary texts by leading computer scientists presenting positions on the methods, purposes, and functions of computer science.Footnote 8 Using a matrix setup, the groups discuss their assigned text before being reshuffled into five new groups with representatives from all of the original five groups. The students share information from their original group, and then comparison and discussion begin.

One of the important topics of discussion in computer science is the relationship between basic research and technological innovation, often phrased as a tension between computer science and software engineering. Historically, this tension is inherent in their discipline and students will discuss how it revolves around different conceptions of the computer’s role: Is it a tool to study the science of data, a fundamental model of computation, or is its purpose to train programmers? Students report that after this exercise, they develop a new vocabulary to talk about their own qualifications and better understand the structure of their own curriculum. Using this as an introductory exercise stimulates student activity and discussion culture, and sets the stage for discussions about scientific methods and the spectrum of knowledge production from basic research to technological products.

We find that discussion of short texts exemplifying different views on a topic is a good way to train competences that are perceived as relevant to the students. It is in this context also relevant to consider how teaching strategies and evaluation of these competences are aligned (Biggs, 1996). Some courses have oral exams and accordingly include more emphasis on training the students to orally present case material in relation to philosophical positions taught in the course. Other courses have a written exam and include writing exercises where students get formative feedback from other students and teachers. In tutorials, we also sometimes use student presentations and role playing as teaching strategies, where students are asked to present (and sometimes defend) a specific position. We have found this particularly useful when teaching ethics, as presenting positions train the students to identify the distinctive features and strengths of specific positions, relate this to similar (more general) positions, as well as to consider weaknesses and counterarguments. We emphasize that our evaluation of their oral or written exam will value their ability to present a given topic from multiple perspectives, rather than to merely describe one position or express their own opinions. Our view here resonates with other literature in science education emphasizing a shift of focus in assessment from “declarative statements” to “interpretative analysis” and other competences higher on Bloom’s taxonomy (Allchin, 2011; Biggs & Tang, 2007).

We hope that our case examples give an impression of how cases can be selected and used in teaching of philosophy of science to science students. As a final point, our cases also illustrate the diversity of text material that can be included in the curriculum. While it is no doubt useful to keep developing good textbooks in philosophy of science, we often use textbook material in combination with papers in contemporary philosophy of science, scientific publications, policy documents, and news media. Aside from being motivating for students to read, exposing the students to a variety of materials can promote critical evaluation of sources, for which they often lack explicit training. Moreover, letting students identify and compare the arguments expressed in different texts can help them develop competences they will need in future projects, such as the ability to identify, analyze, and evaluate arguments against the strength of supporting evidence.

5 Concluding remarks

The focus on teaching philosophy of science of relevance to future scientists entails a number of considerations, not only about which philosophical dimensions to include but also about how to teach them. The internal development of and debate within the academic field of philosophy of science, which in many places structures the teaching of philosophy of science in ways relevant to philosophy students and their needs, is much less relevant to future scientists. Instead, we have highlighted the benefits of case-based teaching, which takes examples closer to students’ practices as the starting point for philosophical reflection, and which can promote active learning. It is our experience that science students find case discussions engaging and useful, which is also reflected in their oral and written course evaluations.

We have illustrated our approach through examples of cases we teach and how we use elements in exercises involving adidactic teaching situations where students discuss the cases on their own. To what extent such exercises, and active learning in general, are possible will of course depend on the context of specific courses. One should be aware that constraints on time and resources often impose a tradeoff between student-centered learning and the scope of “content-based” teaching. Moreover, the number of students is an important factor. Our group teaches more than 1000 science students per year, and we combine active student-centered tutorials (25–30 students) with larger lectures (up to 150–200 students) that naturally are more teacher-structured. Yet, we find that discussion exercises can also improve the teaching of large classes, and that there are benefits of rethinking the traditional “deductive” approach to teaching philosophy of science. Hence, we prioritize active and case-based approaches whenever possible, because we have seen that student outcomes are better if they engage deeply with selected philosophical topics rather than receiving less in-depth coverage of all major debates in philosophy of science.

We have commented on how practice-oriented teaching imposes new requirements on philosophy teachers. In addition to demands regarding interactional expertise, it can be time-consuming to find relevant cases. We hope that initiatives such as this topical collection can help facilitate a higher degree of international collaboration on the task of finding and developing suitable teaching materials and engaging student exercises.