In this article, I address divergent Buddhist positions on conceptual and non-conceptual understanding of reality and the process of transition from the former to the latter. My discussion is anchored in the context of a well-known problematic issue in the field of religious studies, namely, the question of (un)mediated mystical experience. Connecting uniquely Buddhist philosophical and contemplative perspectives with the questions debated in contemporary studies of mysticism, I argue that Buddhism can make significant contributions to that field. Not only does it provide refined models of mind, contemplative processes, and other elements that help us understand certain mystical experiences, but it also encourages us to rethink the very meaning of “mediation,” “ineffability,” “experience,” and other categories used in discussions of mysticism. The application of the category of mystical experience to Buddhist traditions thereby problematizes that category itself, simultaneously suggesting new meanings and perspectives. Far from being passive objects of contemporary scholarly Euro-American discourse on this issue, Buddhist traditions can actively engage, challenge, and modify that discourse.

Research into specificities of experiences, insights, and realizations articulated by Buddhists themselves and interpreted from within the context of Buddhist worldviews and practices has much more to offer to the study of mysticism and mystical experiences than the one that starts with generalizations about mysticism across diverse religions grouped under such categories as “theistic,” “non-theistic,” and so forth. For example, most Buddhists would disagree that such key Buddhist experiences as realization of ultimate reality and awakening or “enlightenment”Footnote 1 are accessible to those who have not undergone specific types of Buddhist training and conditioning. At the same time, they also agree on similarities or sameness of certain experiences across Buddhist traditions. That consensus in its turn is often interwoven with fierce polemics against seeming flaws of Buddhist traditions disagreeing with one’s own in the areas of contemplation, identification of reality, results of meditative practice, and so forth. Studying these elements across Buddhist traditions and analyzing how Buddhists themselves approach such differences, similarities, uniqueness, and diversity will greatly contribute to a more nuanced overall understanding of mysticism and mystical experiences.

In particular, I argue that if the category of “mystical experience” is applicable to Buddhism at all, the direct realization of ultimate reality (Skt. paramārthasatya)Footnote 2 or emptiness (Skt. śūnyatā) should be treated as one of the highest expressions of that experience in the Buddhist context because of its supreme soteriological value as the only direct antidote to impediments to awakening. Likewise, because that realization both transcends and destroys conceptuality, mundane mentality, and dualistic thinking, it best approximates the category of “unmediated mystical experience,” if such a category has any relevant use in the Buddhist context. Correspondingly, because the process of direct realization of ultimate reality is one of the most challenging and important topics of Buddhist philosophical and contemplative theory and practice, the study of different approaches to accessing that realization directly bears upon and promises to contribute to the question of (un)mediated mystical experience. Therefore, although many elements involved in this polemical issue are uniquely Buddhist, their analysis can help us to achieve a better and more nuanced understanding of the issue of (un)mediated mystical experience. While only briefly addressing other forms of mystical experience in Buddhism, I will be targeting the issue of the process of realization of ultimate reality throughout this article.

In what follows below, I first address the broader question of mystical experience in its connection to Buddhism, focusing primarily on two dimensions of the Buddhist worldview: nature of mind and Buddhist paths. This discussion forms a general background for the analysis of Buddhist approaches to the realization of ultimate reality. My analysis specifically targets the ecumenical approach developed by the seminal 15th century Tibetan thinker Serdok Penchen Shakya Chokden (Tib. gser mdog \( pa {\mathop n\limits_ \cdot } \) chen shākya mchog ldan, 1428–1507)Footnote 3 with respect to the two major rival systems of Mahāyāna Buddhism—Madhyamaka (Middle Way) and Yogācāra (Yogic Practice).Footnote 4 I elaborate on his main argument that despite contradictory worldviews, different types of contemplative conditioning leading to direct realization of ultimate reality, and conflicting descriptions of that realization, followers of both Madhyamaka and Yogācāra can access the same direct meditative experience of emptiness that is not mediated by any words and concepts at the time when it actually occurs. This approach is especially intriguing and heuristically useful, providing new perspectives on the nature of non-conceptual experience of ultimate reality and the role conceptual processes play in initially triggering and subsequently articulating that experience. I connect my analysis of Shakya Chokden’s position to the broader issue of how mediation might be involved in mystical experiences and the possibility of achieving the same mystical experience despite different conditioning processes leading to it.

My overall objective is to demonstrate that Buddhism offers highly advanced and sophisticated tools for addressing mystical experiences that have no exact parallels in the non-Buddhist discourse. Analysis and application of those tools will help better understand what issues related to mystical experience trouble Buddhist thinkers themselves and how they handle those issues. That in turn will result in a more nuanced and up-to-date understanding of the question of (un)mediated mystical experience addressed in contemporary scholarship on mysticism.

Locating Buddhist mystical experiences

Multiplicity, contextuality, and the need for fine-tuning

The question regarding whether there can be (un)mediated mystical experience has long been troubling scholars of religious studies.Footnote 5 This question is especially important to those who contest the possibility that followers of different religious traditions who have diverse backgrounds, follow different practices, and hold contradictory worldviews might achieve similar mystical experience(s). Claiming the possibility of unmediated mystical experience is important to those who believe in the existence of “religion” and “mysticism” as generic phenomena with definable characteristics, whose essence lies in personal experience, and whose manifestations are found in Buddhism, Christianity, and so forth. Denying this possibility is crucial to those who question the applicability of such categories, as well as narratives and theories designed for their explanation.

Over the past 30 years, polemics about mediated and unmediated mystical experience became heated, boiled, welled up, and spilled into the area of Buddhist thought and practice. Both the attribution of “mystical” to “experience” and the emphasis on experience itself are problematic within the Buddhist context. Firstly, Buddhism lacks an equivalent of the term “mysticism.”Footnote 6 Secondly, even in such allegedly “mystical” Buddhist cultures as Tibetan, the role of experience is less important than theories of mystical experience suggest.Footnote 7 Overall, Buddhism emphasizes realizations/insights into reality and abandonments of obscurationsFootnote 8 achieved through contemplation, ethical behavior, and ritual practice, while experience is assigned only secondary importance, usually as a by-product and indicator of the progress on the path. This is not to ignore the fact that Buddhists deal with multiple types of experiences that can be or already have been termed “mystical” by scholars of mysticism. Careful analysis of those experiences can greatly contribute to the broader field of religious studies. Nevertheless, if we do not want to turn mysticism into mystification, those experiences have to be handled with care and appreciated in their own right in terms of specific contextual meanings, emphases, and objectives. Only if these conditions are fulfilled can “mysticism” and “mystical experience” be released from the confines of quotation marks and addressed as if they were active and actual categories in Buddhism itself.

The terms “mysticism” and “mystical experience” are vague, and are used differently in different contexts. Their applicability to Buddhism is particularly questionable: neither have they been meaningfully used for translating or clarifying any Buddhist terms or ideas, nor can they easily fit into any Buddhist categories or concepts. Because they do not match the Buddhist worldview, I do not attempt to define them or even to sketch out their general characteristics. Nevertheless, I also believe we can use the vagueness of the terms “mysticism” and “mystical experience” to our advantage if our objective is to clarify the variety of phenomena these terms address rather than select only some phenomena as illustrations of limited definitions of the terms themselves.Footnote 9

Furthermore, the category of “experience” in Buddhism is very complex. Buddhists use several terms that can be translated as “experience” but have different meanings when discussed together or addressed in specific contexts. Only some of these terms have meanings that overlap with the meaning of “realization,” and it is realization that is emphasized even in such “experience-oriented” systems as Mahāmudrā (Tib. phyag chen, Great Seal) and Dzokchen (Tib. rdzogs chen, Great Perfection). When one is encouraged to personally taste, experience, and realize different elements of Buddhist teachings, it is not the experience per se that is being emphasized, but the fact that one has to “interiorize” those elements or discover them “within” oneself instead of treating them merely as external objects of intellectual study. Therefore, we should not confuse these referents of “experience” with any of the specific experiences of bliss, non-conceptuality, etc., that Buddhists often warn against forming attachment to and do not treat as unique objectives of their practice. The Mahāmudrā system, for example, addresses different types of direct insights or realizations (Tib. rtogs pa) into the nature of mind that can be preceded or accompanied by experiences of bliss, clarity, and non-conceptuality (Tib. bde gsal mi rtog pa’i nyams), but are separate from and superior to them.Footnote 10 (Throughout the paper I am using the terms “realization of ultimate reality” and “experience of ultimate reality” interchangeably, because in that particular case Buddhist thinkers themselves can understand the term “experience” (Tib. nyams su myong ba) as “realization”.Footnote 11)

Besides that, Buddhist thinkers and contemporary scholars of mysticism clearly pursue different objectives, have different interests, and operate within different conceptual frameworks. This is especially clear when we compare Buddhist approaches with those of the two prominent adversaries on the issue of (un)mediated mystical experience, Steven Katz and Robert Forman. Katz’s position is best described in his own words: “There are NO pure (i.e., unmediated) experiences. Neither mystical experience nor more ordinary forms of experience give any indication, or any grounds for believing, that they are unmediated.”Footnote 12 Importantly, Katz adds that this process of mediation occurs during the experience itself, not only before or after.Footnote 13 Forman, on the other hand, using Roland Fischer’s “cartography” of conscious states, splits them into ergotropic and trophotropic, and tends to reserve the term “mysticism” only for trophotropic states that are marked by low levels of cognitive and psychological activity.Footnote 14 He specifically focuses on the “pure consciousness event” (PCE), defining it as a “wakeful though contentless (nonintentional) consciousness,” and further identifying it with what Walter Stace called “introvertive mysticism,” distinguished from “extrovertive mysticism.”Footnote 15

Both Katz and Forman tend to address mystical experience in general, although they do limit it to examples that suit their respective agendas. As Victor Hori rightly observes, to support his claim that all cases of mystical experience are contextually constructed, Katz systematically chooses only those reported cases of mystical experience that have intellectual content, while Forman never discusses reported cases of mystical experience that have much content. Footnote 16 Larry Short also points out that arguing for the existence of the pure consciousness event, Forman, and those scholars who have joined him, attempt to “demonstrate that mystical experience is epistemologically extraordinary (that is, an exception to the general rule that consciousness is mediated), as a way of establishing the possibility of a common core to mystical experience.”Footnote 17 Nevertheless, contemporary scholarship demonstrates that this divide itself is questionable.Footnote 18 As soon will become apparent, Katz’s and Forman’s positions also cannot be easily applied to the Buddhist context. This is despite the fact that Buddhists do face similar problems in their approaches to what can be called “mystical experience.”

Study of the tools and strategies used in Buddhist approaches to those problems and issues can significantly refine, expand, and modify contemporary debates about mystical experience. Similar to followers of other religious traditions, Buddhists emphasize the uniqueness of their practices and realizations, as well as their results, such as \( {\text{nirv}}\overline {\text{a}} \mathop{\text{n}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{a}} \). This being said, they also accommodate varieties of meditative states under the category of “mundane paths” (Skt. laukikamārga),Footnote 19 thinking that those states are shared in common by Buddhist and non-Buddhist contemplatives. Arguing that one does not have to be a Buddhist to experience “infinite consciousness” (Skt. vijñānānatya), “nothingness” (Skt. \( aki\mathop{m}\limits_{ \cdot } canya \)), and other states subsumed under that category, Buddhist thinkers show their insufficiency for attaining uniquely Buddhist objectives, and warn against confusing such states and uniquely Buddhist meditative states.Footnote 20 Most importantly, Buddhist thinkers approach the question of mediation differently than either Katz or Forman: while the two scholars debate about the very possibility of unmediated mystical experience, the majority of Buddhist thinkers take for granted that certain states―such as the direct realization of ultimate reality and the omniscience of buddhahood―are not mediated by any conceptual images or verbal constructs at the time of their occurrence.Footnote 21 This is despite the fact that they are necessarily mediated through specific Buddhist practices that precede them, and in cases other than buddhahood are also limited to realizing only some “parts” of reality. Buddhist thinkers also disagree on the question of whether the direct realization of ultimate reality has “content” and images, and involves mental processes. Therefore, Buddhists themselves hold divergent views on the meaning and process of mediation involved in mystical experiences.

These and other elements addressed below call for a more nuanced understanding of what Buddhists themselves believe to be common and uncommon experiences that can be termed “mystical,” and how they understand the nature of those experiences. If we want the Buddhist approach to mystical experiences to be relevant to our discussion, it is important to make our discussion of mystical experiences relevant to Buddhism. In particular, we can greatly clarify the question of (un)mediated mystical experience in connection to Buddhism if we let Buddhist thinkers speak for themselves. They believe that Buddhist mystical experiences are conditioned by specifically Buddhist types of training. If we take those claims seriously, we have to shift our emphasis from the question of unmediated mystical experience per se to conditioning processes that precede and trigger it. Our question in that context will be to ask whether different conditionings necessarily lead to the same or different mystical experiences.

Similar to other religious traditions, in the Buddhist world, mystical experiences comprise a part of interwoven combinations of different elements or dimensions, such as epistemological models of conceptual and non-conceptual states of mind, models of the path to awakening, diverse cosmological models, distinctions between “esoteric” and “exoteric” elements, bodily transformations, and so forth. To fully appreciate Buddhist mystical experiences, therefore, it is crucial to consider all such related elements instead of just picking and choosing. Some dimensions necessarily play a more important role in particular mystical experiences than others. Due to limitations of this paper, I will focus on two such dimensions that are virtually ubiquitous throughout the Buddhist world and are particularly important in the present context: the dimension of mindFootnote 22 structure and processes, and the dimension of the Buddhist paths (Skt. mārga). The former is indispensable for understanding how Buddhists themselves view mental processes involved in mystical experiences, while the latter is crucial for understanding what those experiences are embedded in, shaped by, limited to, and what role they play within the broader framework of Buddhist views and practices.Footnote 23 The two dimensions are also interrelated, overlap, and cannot be treated in separation from each other: Buddhist paths are understood primarily as progressive mental states, while the majority of mental transformations related to mystical experiences, visions, and realizations in Buddhism can be understood only in the context of Buddhist paths.

The following short surveys of the Buddhist mind and path models are intended to introduce unfamiliar readers to the complexity of those models and demonstrate their close relationship with Buddhist experiences and realizations. This in turn will put into question the applicability to Buddhism of such foreign ideas and categories as Forman’s category of contentless consciousness or Katz’s assumption that all our experiences are necessarily constructed and mediated. Discussion of those models will also provide a necessary background and context for analyzing the interpretive approach of Shakya Chokden that will be given below. My overall objective is not to defend one particular model over another but to demonstrate their multiplicity and the indispensability of paying close attention to and utilizing specific Buddhist models when analyzing specific Buddhist mystical experiences, especially when those models are designed for not only explaining but in fact also leading to those experiences.

Mind models

Buddhists developed highly sophisticated models of the mind’s structure and functioning, and use them in discussions of realizations of reality, meditative states, progress on the path, exalted visions, and awakening.

Mind in Buddhism is treated not as a reservoir containing thoughts and feelings, but rather as a framework of interrelated processes and mental states. The most common model is the twofold division of mind into cognitive states (Skt. citta) and mental factors (Skt. caitta). Cognitive states are usually subdivided into six―five sensory (Skt. indriyajñāna) and one mental consciousness (Skt. manojñāna)―or eight, adding the afflicted mentality (Skt. \( kli\mathop{s}\limits_{\cdot} \mathop{t}\limits_{\cdot} amanas \)) and storehouse consciousness (Skt. ālayavijñāna), as is usually done by Yogācāra thinkers. Mental factors are divided into 49, 51, etc., and further grouped into clusters, such as the 5 omnipresent mental factors (Skt. sarvatraga), 11 virtuous mental factors (Skt. kuśala), and so forth.Footnote 24 Similar to the other seven types of consciousness, storehouse consciousness is always accompanied by the five omnipresent mental factors: mental contact (Skt. sparśa), attention (Skt. manaskāra), feeling (Skt. vedanā), discrimination (Skt. \( sa\mathop{m}\limits_{ \cdot } j\widetilde{n}\overline a \)), and intention (Skt. cetanā).Footnote 25 Also, similar to other cognitive acts and mental factors, even the storehouse consciousness has objects of perception (Skt. ālambana), such as the external world.Footnote 26

These models are used to describe all unenlightened and enlightened states of mind, or limited to unenlightened states only. In the latter case, new elements can be added, such as the stainless consciousness (Skt. amalavijñāna), primordial mind (Skt. jñāna), primordial mind of luminosity (Skt. prabhāsvarajñāna), and buddha-essence (Skt. buddhagarbha). Those elements then can be treated as becoming active/manifest during direct realizations of reality, buddhahood, and other circumstances when obscurations subside either temporarily or forever. In that context, some thinkers might take the primordial mind as self-cognizing and perceiving nothing else but the primordial mind itself.Footnote 27 When no extra mental categories are added, or when they are subsumed under one of the six-fold or eight-fold categories, it might either be argued that realization of ultimate reality and awakening are performed by those cognitive states and mental factors, or are devoid of any mental states whatsoever and utterly inexpressible.

According to some thinkers, certain mental states last throughout lifetimes and can even continue into the state of buddhahood, while others are more short lived and disappear at a certain point either temporarily or forever. For example, according to Yogācāra, the storehouse consciousness persists continuously and perishes in the state of \( {\text{nirv}}\overline {\text{a}} \mathop{\text{n}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{a}} \) Footnote 28; the afflicted mentality temporarily ceases in a particular state of cessation (Skt. nirodhasamāpatti) and during direct realization of ultimate reality prior to \( {\text{nirv}}\overline {\text{a}} \mathop{\text{n}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{a}} \), and is completely eradicated in the state of an arhat.Footnote 29

Buddhist thinkers also provide dynamic models of mental states as unfolding processes. According to some Buddhist tantric systems, for example, worldly deluded states of consciousness develop on the basis of the primordially pure state of luminosity (Skt. prabhāsvara), fundamental innate luminous mind (Tib. gnyug ma lhan cig skyes pa’i ’od gsal gyi sems), and in the process of dying the order is reversed: all types of consciousness, including the storehouse consciousness, undergo successive stages of dissolution and vanish back into the basic luminosity at the moment of death just to reemerge again in the postmortem state. Tantric teachings provide elaborate descriptions of these processes with accompanying visions, and creatively incorporate them into contemplative practices.Footnote 30 Likewise, some systems―such as the Chinese Hua-yen advocated by the Ch’an/Hua-yen thinker Kuei-feng Tsung-mi (780–841) and the “Quintessential Instructions” division (Tib. man ngag sde) of Tibetan Dzokchen advocated by Longchen Rapjam (Tib. klong chen rab ’byams, 1308–1364) and later elaborated upon by Jikmé Lingpa (Tib. ’jigs med gling pa, 1730–1798)―describe the basic reality as awareness (Ch. chih, Tib. rig pa), emphasize the dynamic nature of reality, and embrace the teaching of the nature-origination (Ch. hsing-ch’i) or nature-manifestation (Tib. gzhi snang) that bridges the gap between ultimate reality and phenomenal appearances, treating the latter as manifestations of the primordial nature due to its functioning (Ch. yung, Tib. rtsal). According to Dzokchen, awareness―also called “fundamental mind” (Tib. gnyug sems)―forms the basis for all the eight types of consciousness mentioned above, and its realization cannot be performed by any other consciousness than that awareness itself. This fundamental awareness is also called “ground” (Tib. gzhi), because all impure and pure, enlightened states of consciousness arise from it due to its dynamic functioning.Footnote 31

I should note that although the ground, awareness, and luminosity provide for and serve as the basis of the arising of phenomenal appearances, they do not contain them. Otherwise, we would have to accept an absurd possibility of the non-dualistic non-conceptual state of mind containing dualistic concepts, non-afflicted state having afflictions, etc. Because, as has been mentioned above, Buddhist thinkers do not treat mind as a thought container, the idea of emptying mind of its contents is hardly acceptable in the Buddhist context.Footnote 32 It is more fruitful, therefore, to pay attention to what state ceases, what state persists, and at what level specific realizations and experiences occur. This adds an additional weight to distinctions between different types and levels of consciousness.

Certain models of mind can add new significance to philosophical and contemplative systems when these models are combined with each other. Yogācāra terminology of the eight types of consciousness, for example, can be carried into highly elaborate tantric systems and used as an aid in making subtle distinctions between different levels of consciousness utilized in tantric contemplative practice.Footnote 33 Alternatively, it can be argued that because of divergent interpretations of mind in different systems, their practices and results of those practices are also vastly different. For example, it is often argued that tantric practice is highly efficient and swift because it teaches and utilizes subtle and powerful levels of consciousness that are even unheard of in non-tantric systems.Footnote 34 Dzokchen meditation is built on making a sharp distinction between the fundamental mind of awareness and other types of consciousness, and then utilizing the former in contemplative practice.Footnote 35 Kuei-feng Tsung-mi’s argument for the superiority of the Ho-tse school of Ch’an’s practice is based on his claim that in contrast to Northern and Hung-chou Ch’an lineages, it teaches awakening to both static and dynamic aspects of mind followed by their cultivation in contemplative practice.Footnote 36

One distinction that is particularly helpful for understanding Buddhist approaches to mystical experiences―and specifically to the direct realization of ultimate reality―is the distinction between conceptual and non-conceptual types of mind. Although concepts and the lack thereof are understood by Buddhist thinkers differently, interpretive approaches inspired by the ideas of the famous Indian Buddhist logician Dharmakīrti (ca. 600–670 C.E.) assumed a place of paramount importance in the Indian and Tibetan Buddhist world. According to Tibetan interpreters of his system, conceptuality (Skt. kalpanā) is understood as a state of mind that cognizes its objects via their generic images or meaning-universals (Skt. arthasāmānya),Footnote 37 while non-conceptual direct perception (Skt. \( pratyak\mathop{s}\limits_{ \cdot } a \)) perceives its objects directly, without the media of those meaning-universals. Nevertheless, both conceptual and non-conceptual states of mind cognize their objects via “representations” (Skt. ākāra), i.e., images of perceived things, which can be likened to reflections (representations) on the surface of a mirror (mind). The ontological status of those representations is understood differently even within the same Dharmakīrtean system,Footnote 38 not to mention their different interpretations by subsequent thinkers.Footnote 39

Dharmakīrti describes the transition from conceptual to non-conceptual understanding as follows: “…that to which one meditatively conditions oneself, whether it be real or unreal, will result in a clear, non-conceptual cognition when the meditation is perfected.”Footnote 40 This very model is applied by Indian and Tibetan thinkers to conceptual and non-conceptual realization of reality and the process of transition from the former to the latter.Footnote 41 This process, nevertheless, is understood by Buddhist thinkers differently. Recently, John Dunne argued that Dharmakīrti himself did not view the transition from conceptual to non-conceptual realization of reality as some sort of a break through the veil of concepts to a mystical gnosis that experiences reality lying beyond concepts, but rather as a transition from conceptual understanding to a non-conceptual experience of the four noble truths.Footnote 42 In Dharmakīrti’s system, this process involves the sequence of cognitions induced initially by learning, then by contemplating, and finally by meditating (Skt. śrutamaya-, cintāmaya-, and bhāvanāmayajñāna).”Footnote 43 In contrast to that position, later Tibetan interpreters of Dharmakīrti’s thought and other systems to which that thought was adopted often saw the transition from conceptual to non-conceptual realization of reality precisely as a break through conceptuality to the inconceivable and ineffable ultimate reality underlying and hidden beyond concepts.Footnote 44

It is also true that virtually all Mahāyāna thinkers treat the highest ultimate reality and its direct realization as ineffable and transcending words and concepts. Nevertheless, the ineffability of the ultimate implies neither its similarity across different systems nor its accessibility. As some critics rightly observed, interpreters of mysticism can be misled by similar-sounding descriptions of mystical experience as ineffable, inexpressible, transcendent, sublime, and so forth.Footnote 45 As I have recently argued, even within one and the same Buddhist culture, such as Tibetan, in the context of discussion of the same system, such as Madhyamaka, Buddhist thinkers offer multiple and contradictory interpretations of ineffable ultimate reality.Footnote 46 As I will demonstrate below, Buddhist thinkers also conceive different ways of accessing the ultimate. Likewise, the direct realization of ultimate reality can be described as perceiving “something” or having no object at all.Footnote 47 Because the direct realization of ultimate reality occupies the place of paramount importance in Buddhism, it comes as no surprise that Buddhist thinkers tend to argue that such interpretations do not just describe the same reality in different ways, but actually shape mental processes in such a way that some of them can grant access to direct realization of that reality while others, being wrong and misleading, only obscure it.

Buddhist paths

The above discussion makes it clear that distinctions between different types and levels of mind are indispensable for understanding diverse approaches to meditation, progress in Buddhist practice, and by extension mystical experiences, because these distinctions directly bear upon such questions as what state of consciousness is used in what type of practice, how different mental states condition each other, and what experiences they trigger. Nevertheless, because mystical experiences in Buddhism for the most part are treated as results and stages of Buddhist practices, their discussion will remain overly vague and general unless placed within the framework of those practices. Buddhist practices in turn are often understood in terms of models of the path to awakening, such as the “five paths” (Skt. pañcamārga) model. Mahāyāna thinkers further add to it the “ten grounds” (Skt. daśabhūmi), thereby issuing the model of “ten grounds-five paths” and presenting all of them as progressive stages of the path to buddhahood.

According to this model, one starts from the path of accumulation (Skt. \( sa\mathop{m}\limits_{ \cdot } bh\overline a ram\overline a rga \)), moves on to the path of preparation (Skt. prayogamārga), and when for the first time one directly realizes the ultimate reality of all phenomena, one enters the path of seeing (Skt. darśanamārga) and the first bodhisattva ground, and becomes a Mahāyāna ārya or a “noble”/“exalted” being. One keeps practicing on the path of meditation (Skt. bhāvanāmārga) that covers bodhisattva grounds 2–10 and finally achieves the path of no more learning (Skt. \( a\mathop{s}\limits^{\prime } aik\mathop{s}\limits_{ \cdot } am\overline a rga \)), i.e., the state of buddhahood. Each of the ten grounds consists of a state of absorption in meditative equipoise (Skt. samāhita), when one directly realizes ultimate reality, and a state not in absorption, known as subsequent attainment (Skt. \( p\mathop{r}\limits_{\cdot } \mathop{s}\limits_{\cdot } \mathop{t}\limits_{\cdot } halabdha \)), when one engages in other bodhisattva practices.Footnote 48 Every transition from one ground to the next is necessarily conditioned by specific practices of the preceding ground known as “trainings” or “applications” (Skt. parikarman).Footnote 49 According to the non-tantric Mahāyāna teachings, it takes at least three countless eons to cover all the five paths, requiring one countless eon to cover paths 1–2, one countless eon to cover grounds 1–7, and one more countless eon to cover grounds 8–10.

This model explains when and why certain mystical experiences are believed to happen. The direct realization of ultimate reality can happen only during meditative equipoise on the path of seeing, meditation, and no more learning, and has to be preceded by a long process of conceptual contemplation of emptiness and other practices. At the very beginning of subsequent attainment that immediately follows most meditative equipoises, one experiences the illusion-like meditative stabilization (Skt. māyopamāsamadhi) when conventional phenomena appear just as illusions, this experience being colored by the immediately preceding realization of emptiness. Besides this experience, subsequent attainments also contain multiple visions and experiences that can be termed “mystical” in the ecstatic sense: on each ground one sees an increasing number of buddhas, travels to an increasing number of pure lands, enters an increasing number of meditative absorptions, and so forth.

Buddhist path models also make it clear that despite similar terminology of “ultimate reality,” “selflessness,” and “emptiness,” those terms have different referents in the context of specific paths, and can be applied to objects of yogic direct perception on the paths of śrāvakas, pratyekabuddhas, and bodhisattvas (the latter being the Mahāyāna path described above, the former two being non-Mahāyāna paths to arhatship). Buddhist thinkers often emphasize the hierarchy of direct realizations of emptiness and claim that only Mahāyāna āryas can realize ultimate reality fully, while śrāvakas and pratyekabuddhas are able to realize it only partially.Footnote 50 Furthermore, during each of the ten grounds on the same Mahāyāna path, one acquires increasingly extensive visions of reality, similar to seeing the waxing moon.Footnote 51

This is not to say that the mind and path models addressed above can be universally applied to all kinds of Buddhist mystical experiences. On the contrary, those models and their combinations themselves require tuning and reconsideration when applied to specific contexts. For example, when it is claimed that one can directly realize ultimate reality only starting from the level of ārya bodhisattvas that begins from the path of seeing, it follows that virtually no living Mahāyāna practitioners can claim to have realized ultimate reality directly. Otherwise, they would also have to claim that they have been practicing the Mahāyāna path in previous lives for at least one countless eon, can see at least a hundred buddhas, shake at least a hundred world realms, and so forth. On the other hand, followers of Dzokchen and Mahāmudrā systems repeatedly emphasize that from the very beginning of practice one has to be introduced and exposed to the ultimate nature of mind directly, and that even this initial realization is non-conceptual.Footnote 52 But in the context of the ten grounds-five paths model this position raises the problems just mentioned above. In attempts to resolve such problems while retaining the ten grounds-five paths model, some Dzokchen and Mahāmudrā thinkers resorted to ideas of acquiring the not-yet-manifest potential to meet a hundred buddhas, shake a hundred realms, etc., that can be achieved in this very life but manifest after death when the “shell” of the body is finally broken, similar to a mighty mythical bird garuda whose powers are complete within the egg even before it hatches.Footnote 53 But such interpretations are far from being universally accepted even within the Tibetan Buddhist world.

Furthermore, in spite of the popularity of the ten grounds-five paths model and the fact that many Buddhist writers feel obliged to refer to it in order to contextualize and authenticate views and practices they address, this is not the only model of the path. Kuei-feng Tsung-mi, for example, does not make reference to this model but uses his own model. He locates his approach to the path in the context of the three types of awakening―intrinsic awakening (Ch. pen-chüeh), awakening of initial insight (Ch. chieh-wu) characterized as sudden awakening (Ch. tun-wu), and awakening of complete realization (Ch. cheng-wu)―and argues that genuine practice of the path starts with the awakening of initial insight only. Because he sees that awakening as sudden, he clearly does not feel that preparatory practices, such as those of the paths preceding the path of seeing in the ten grounds-five paths model, are necessary.Footnote 54

Understanding which path models are implied in case of particular mystical experiences helps clear away a lot of confusion created by drawing overly generalized parallels not only between Buddhist and non-Buddhist mystical experiences, but also between mystical experiences addressed within different Buddhist traditions. Footnote 55 For example, despite the fact that some Ch’an/Zen and Theravāda thinkers describe awakening as the goal of practice and as sudden, Footnote 56 what is signified by “awakening” and “suddenness” can be vastly different depending on context. The awakening or “enlightenment” (Pali/Skt. bodhi) Footnote 57 most Theravāda followers are striving for is understood as \( {\text{nirv}}\overline {\text{a}} \mathop{\text{n}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{a}} \) of an arhat other than a buddha,Footnote 58 while buddhahood is reserved only for outstanding individuals, such as the Buddha Śākyamuni. Such an arhatship is the fifth within the five paths that are not linked with bodhisattva practices as those are understood in Mahāyāna. Descriptions of Ch’an/Zen awakening, depending on context, might bypass the five path model or be embedded in it, but being a part of the Mahāyāna tradition, Ch’an/Zen is necessarily linked with bodhisattva practices. Suddenness of an arhat’s awakening mentioned in Theravāda texts means that sometimes such awakening happens unexpectedly, although it necessarily has to be preceded by years and sometimes lives dedicated to contemplative practice. In contrast, in the Ch’an/Zen―as in the case of the above-mentioned Tsung-mi’s model―suddenness implies that no artificial conditioning can trigger initial awakening (although it does not imply that awakening just happens out of the blue).

What emerges from this discussion is that the issues of mediation, objects, and processes involved in mystical experiences are treated differently by Buddhist thinkers and assume various meanings in diverse contexts. According to the model of the six or eight types of consciousness and accompanying mental factors, mind always has certain objects of perception, and therefore no state of consciousness can be completely free from any objects and processes. Notice that even the above-mentioned states of “limitless consciousness” or “nothingness” are otherwise accompanied by more than a dozen mental factors, including volition or intention, and have objects. Some models that involve more than eight types of consciousness allow the possibility of actualizing the subliminal mind devoid of everything but ultimate reality and/or that mind itself. Nevertheless, Buddhist thinkers diverge on the issue of whether this ultimate reality is an object or not and what kind of object it is.

If we analyze the context in which Buddhist mystical experiences occur, it also becomes clear that they are triggered only by specific Buddhist training and conditioning. Even in the context of some Zen models that advocate initial awakening as sudden, this event is clearly mediated by certain conditioning processes that precede it, such as the contemplation of kōans in Rinzai training, for example. (Mediation, of course, does not necessarily have to precede mystical experiences immediately, but can occur at some time earlier.) In terms of the aforementioned Buddhist path models in particular, even the direct realization of reality never stays the same and constantly evolves until one is fully enlightened; realizations of emptiness and types of emptiness realized will differ depending on what path and stage of the path one is on. This implies that even this highest type of mystical experience in Buddhism is mediated―if not at the time of its occurrence then at least prior to it. It goes without saying that all pure visions of the subsequent attainment are both mediated and have objects.

The above discussion makes it clear that unless contextualized, analysis of (un)mediated mystical experience makes little sense in Buddhism; it is greatly assisted by the mind and path models, especially those of conceptuality/non-conceptuality and the ten stages-five paths. Within the Buddhist context, the direct realization of ultimate reality is one of the highest expressions of mystical experience, and it also best approximates the category of unmediated mystical experience. Direct realization of ultimate reality and other Buddhist mystical experiences are mediated in terms of being preceded by conditioning processes that bear upon and trigger those experiences. Whether such experiences are seen as mediated or not, objectless or not, etc., at the time of their occurrence, depends on particular forms of Buddhism we deal with, on contextual meanings, and on descriptive strategies used to address those experiences.

Shakya Chokden’s approach to Yogācāra and Madhyamaka

The previous section demonstrated that direct realization of ultimate reality and other uniquely Buddhist mystical experiences are seen by Buddhists as being accessible only through conditioning in the traditions that teach such experiences and realizations. Otherwise, they are not treated as uniquely Buddhist, and either placed under the category of the “mundane paths” mentioned above or seen as simply extraneous. Nevertheless, within the limits of Buddhist traditions themselves, certain mystical experiences, such as the realization of selflessness of persons (Skt. pudgalanairātmya), are often seen as being accessible to followers of all Buddhist systems because those systems provide efficient tools for their realization and because those tools do not seem to be contradictory.

Furthermore, Buddhist thinkers do believe that certain experiences and realizations can be accessed by different means. Although Buddhists often make minute distinctions between different views and practices, they also propose reconciliation of at least some of them. They might argue, for example, that there are several ways of accessing the subliminal level of consciousness, including direct realization of ultimate reality. Buddhist tantric systems address two distinct ways of accessing the fundamental innate luminous mind mentioned above: through initially dissolving subtle bodily energies into the central energy channel (and thus replicating the death process) and through direct exposure to that luminous mind itself.Footnote 59 In other words, it can be accessed either after coarser levels of mentality have been stopped (through the dissolution of energies) or while still having them (in the case of direct exposure). In the non-Tantric context too, one can meditate on emptiness or selflessness of phenomena (Skt. dharmanairātmya) either having determined it through logical reasoning outlined in Madhyamaka treatises or through quintessential instructions on meditation.Footnote 60

In other contexts, Tibetan thinkers of the Sakya (Tib. (sa skya), Nyingma (Tib. rnying ma), and Kagyü (Tib. bka’ brgyud) traditions argue that both Svātantrika (Autonomist) and \( \Pr \overline{{\text{a}}} {\text{sa}}{\mathop {\text{n}}\limits^. }{\text{gika}} \) (Consequentialist) systems of Madhyamaka hold valid views on ultimate reality; thinkers of the Geluk tradition believe that the \( \Pr \overline{{\text{a}}} {\text{sa}}{\mathop {\text{n}}\limits^. }{\text{gika}} \) view of emptiness is shared by Buddhist Tantra, while such thinkers as Shakya Chokden demonstrate the equal validity of \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) Madhyamaka and Alīkākāravāda Yogācāra approaches to reality. It can also be argued that direct realization of reality does not necessarily have to be preceded by its conceptual understanding based on reasoning because tantric practitioners can access that realization by using alternative techniques, such as the wisdom-primordial mind empowerment (Skt. \( praj\widetilde{n}\overline a j\widetilde{n}\overline a n\overline a bhi\mathop{s}\limits_{ \cdot } eka \)) and the stage of self-blessings (Tib. rang byin gyis brlabs pa’i rim pa).Footnote 61

Restrictions nevertheless apply. For example, Buddhist thinkers argue that no progress on the path is possible unless one first generates renunciation of worldly existence, and no realizations on the Mahāyāna path are possible unless one has first developed the mind of awakening (Skt. bodhicitta).Footnote 62 Nor is it possible to directly realize emptiness of all phenomena unless one uses specific Buddhist techniques for doing so. Likewise, Buddhist tantric thinkers argue that it is impossible to acquire genuine realizations on tantric paths without receiving tantric empowerments and instructions. The overall Buddhist position, therefore, is that although doors to some mystical experiences are at least partially open, not everybody can easily cross the threshold.

We should also note that tantric empowerments, renunciation, logical reasoning, etc., are much more than simply disposable tickets one has to buy in order to board Buddhist vehicles to awakening. On the contrary, they comprise important parts of those vehicles. Cultivation of bodhicitta, for example, does not just precede but necessarily accompanies Mahāyāna practices, and bodhicitta is carried all the way into the state of buddhahood. Tantric empowerments do not only initiate but are incorporated into tantric practice through visualizing oneself as a tantric deity accompanied on more advanced levels by self-empowerments (Tib. bdag ’jug). Furthermore, certain meditative states and experiences “make sense” only when conjoined with other practices. For example, direct realization of emptiness within the Mahāyāna context is believed to be brought about not by sole contemplation of reality, but by that contemplation in tandem with other Mahāyāna practices and states of mind, such as great compassion (Skt. \( mah\overline a karu\mathop{n}\limits_{ \cdot } \overline a \)).Footnote 63

The topic of Buddhist approaches to realization of ultimate reality is a part of this larger context. Although all Buddhist systems provide descriptions of reality and tools of realizing it, those descriptions and tools often conflict with each other and seem to be irreconcilable. As I have mentioned above, the dominant Mahāyāna position is that direct realization of ultimate reality is not mediated by words and concepts, although it is necessarily prepared by certain conditioning processes. In the non-tantric Mahāyāna Buddhism, these processes are usually considered to be conceptual, and consist of logical reasoning aimed at deconstructing and destroying dualistic thinking. The most complicated questions to ask in this context are how conceptual processes can trigger non-conceptual realization, what the relationship between conceptuality and direct perception is, and whether different conceptual tools can trigger the same direct realization of reality.

These issues are greatly clarified by Shakya Chokden, whose interpretive approach illuminates key elements of the widespread Buddhist approach to non-conceptual experience of ultimate reality: that such experience is not mediated by words and concepts when it occurs; that it nevertheless has to be triggered by specific conditioning processes that usually involve words and concepts; and that those triggering processes can be different. His approach, therefore, is very useful for connecting analysis of the Buddhist position on this seminal type of mystical experience with the broader issue of mediation of mystical experiences that occupies contemporary researchers of mysticism.

More specifically, Shakya Chokden’s contribution to the question of (un)mediated mystical experience lies in his unique interpretation of the nature and relationship of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka. In Tibet, these two rival systems are nearly universally viewed as the most important of all Buddhist philosophical traditions, although Madhyamaka is elevated to the top position. Shakya Chokden fully acknowledges differences between the two systems and provides a detailed analysis of their mutual polemical refutations of each other, but in his works written from 1477 onwardFootnote 64 he ultimately argues for their fundamental compatibility and shared vision. The majority of Tibetan thinkers treat Madhyamaka as synonymous with the system of \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) (Proponents of Entitylessness), and Yogācāra as synonymous with Cittamātra (Mind Only), and further subdivide the latter into two systems of Alīkākāravāda (Proponents of False Representations) and Satyākāravāda (Proponents of True Representations).Footnote 65 In contrast, Shakya Chokden accepts neither that Yogācāra and Cittamātra are the same system nor that Madhyamaka is limited to the system of \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) only. Although he accepts the twofold division of Yogācāra into Alīkākāravāda and Satyākāravāda, he identifies Satyākāravāda as synonymous exclusively with Cittamātra, and Alīkākāravāda as a subdivision of Madhyamaka on an equal footing with \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and surpassing Cittamātra. His unique position is that Alīkākāravāda is both Yogācāra and Madhyamaka.

Clarifying differences between Alīkākāravāda and \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and at the same time showing their compatibility, he draws a sharp distinction between the views realized in the meditative equipoise of Mahāyāna āryas and the views conceptually determined by reasoning prior to meditative equipoise or described during its subsequent attainment. This distinction allows him to bring the two systems together on the level of direct realization of ultimate reality while keeping them distinct on the level of the conceptual approach to it. He shows that interpretive differences between \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and Alīkākāravāda pertain to the view of ultimate reality determined through reasoning on the conceptual level, but despite those differences they provide means for accessing the same ultimate reality directly realized through meditative experience.Footnote 66 Consequently, by following different conceptual approaches to ultimate reality, followers of both systems can access the same direct realization of it. Likewise, he explains that descriptions of that realization on the level of its subsequent attainment are also distinct in the two systems. Nevertheless, both are equally valid divisions of Madhyamaka, because both have the capacity to dispel the most subtle obscurations and thereby enable the achievement of buddhahood.Footnote 67

Comparing the two systems in the context of the self-emptiness (Tib. rang stong)/other-emptiness (Tib. gzhan stong) distinction, Shakya Chokden explains that \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) determines reality in terms of self-emptiness of all phenomena, while Alīkākāravāda does it in terms of other-emptiness.Footnote 68 When determining the view of reality on the conceptual level, \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) treats it as a total negation of the entities of all phenomena, including emptiness itself. In contrast to that, Alīkākāravāda selectively negates some phenomena (imaginary natures, Skt. parikalpita) on the basis of other phenomena (dependent natures, Skt. paratantra), and preserves the entity of non-dual primordial mind (thoroughly established nature, Skt. \( parini\mathop{s}\limits_{\cdot} panna \)), left as the remainder of that negation.Footnote 69 The \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) position of self-emptiness entails the view of non-affirming negation (Skt. \( prasajyaprati\mathop{s}\limits_{ \cdot } edha \)), because it entails negation of all phenomena without positing anything in its stead. On the other hand, the Alīkākāravāda position of other-emptiness entails the view of affirming negation (Skt. paryudāsa), because it casts the non-dual primordial mind as the remainder of the negation of the object of negation. Shakya Chokden further argues that a non-affirming negation is an object of concepts only and therefore cannot be directly experienced in the meditative equipoise of Mahāyāna āryas. The affirming negation can be experienced directly in meditative equipoise, because the self-cognizing primordial mind is both an affirming negation and a functional thing (Tib. dngos po).Footnote 70

Thus, Alīkākāravādins conceptually determine through reasoning and meditate directly in meditative equipoise on the same primordial mind. They describe that realization afterwards also as meditation on the primordial mind. \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{dins}} \) through reasoning arrive at the non-affirming negation and afterwards claim that the non-realization of anything by anything is simply given the name of direct realization of emptiness. Nevertheless, both the Alīkākāravāda view of affirming negation and the \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) view of non-affirming negation are effective in terms of being able to trigger the same direct realization of ultimate reality. Despite differences in techniques used for accessing that realization, followers of both systems directly realize the same reality as a result of applying those techniques. This sameness is not damaged by the fact that Alīkākāravādins afterwards describe that realization as an affirming negation while \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{dins}} \) describe it as not realizing anything by anything (they cannot describe it as a non-affirming negation because that would entail that such realization is conceptual).

Shakya Chokden argues that followers of both \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and Alīkākāravāda are “destined” to directly realize the same ultimate reality. No matter which of the two systems one follows, she eventually will break through the thicket of conceptuality and directly experience the same non-dual primordial mind. But we also learned that \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) negates the reality of all phenomena, including the primordial mind, while Alīkākāravāda does not negate its reality. Then how can the two systems be compatible? Shakya Chokden’s answer is that whether their followers negate reality of primordial mind prior to meditative equipoise or not, they can get access to this primordial mind within meditative equipoise. This position raises the following question: how is it possible to negate grasping at the reality of primordial mind without negating it through reasoning? Shakya Chokden handles this question by arguing that there are two different ways of negating grasping: using reasoning that focuses on negating the objects of grasping and using reasoning that focuses on negating the grasping itself.Footnote 71 The first approach is used by \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{dins}} \), the second by Alīkākāravādins.

Describing the tools that negate conceptual proliferations, \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{dins}} \) argue that without negating the object, its subject cannot be negated. This is because the \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) system treats subjects and objects as dependently established. Because they are established in mutual dependence, they have to be negated in mutual dependence too. According to the Alīkākāravāda system, on the other hand, it is possible to negate grasping at objects by negating just subjects that grasp. One does not necessarily have to negate the objects those subjects grasp at. In other words, by negating grasping subjects, their grasping function will be cancelled automatically. We might think of cutting off a hand as an analogy: the moment it is cut off its grasping or grabbing function stops on its own accord, without unnecessary removal of objects of grabbing. In particular, it is possible to negate grasping at reality of primordial mind by negating consciousness that takes primordial mind as its object and grasps at it as real. Shakya Chokden treats both the \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and Alīkākāravāda approaches as valid and argues that it is possible to abandon all obscurations by following either one.Footnote 72

Highlighting this sharp distinction between \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and Alīkākāravāda views of emptiness on the conceptual level, Shakya Chokden demonstrates that they are different Madhyamaka systems. In spite of that, he argues that this difference itself does not go beyond conceptually determined views. Even though on the conceptual level followers of the two types systems determine emptiness differently, both of them abandon the same proliferations and acquire the same direct realization of ultimate reality within the meditative equipoise of Mahāyāna āryas.Footnote 73 Put in terms of mystical experience, his position is that at least within the limits of these two systems, Mahāyāna āryas acquire the same mystical experience of ultimate reality that is not mediated by any concepts or words at the time of its occurrence. This is despite the fact that it is necessarily mediated prior to its occurrence, i.e., prepared and triggered by different conceptual tools, and its subsequent description is also affected by divergent philosophical categories of the two systems.

Conclusion and final remarks

It is clear that Shakya Chokden’s position hinges upon his basic claim that both \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and Alīkākāravāda approaches are efficient for dispelling obstacles to direct realization of ultimate reality. As we have seen, he argues that it is possible to negate the same obstructing concepts by focusing on either negating their referents (as \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{dins}} \) do) or those concepts themselves (as Alīkākāravādins do). To translate this position into the “mystical language,” he claims that one can access the same mystical experience of reality in different ways as long as those ways are equally effective for destroying obstacles to that experience. What allows Shakya Chokden to make such claims?

A crucial point to note here is that his claim of the same non-conceptual mystical experience being triggered by different conceptual processes is possible only as long as those processes are treated as deconstructive in nature. As an example, we can think of demolishing a wall: whether one uses bare hands, feet, hammers, sledges, explosives, etc., as long as he can completely demolish it, he will achieve the same end result―disappearance of the wall and breaking through it to the open space it has been blocking. Likewise, as long as techniques used by \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and Alīkākāravāda practitioners are treated as deconstructive, and as long as it can be demonstrated that they are equally effective in destroying impediments to the direct realization of reality, it can be claimed that the direct realization they trigger and the reality accessed through that realization are the same.

Such claims would be unfounded were Shakya Chokden treating the processes leading to direct realization of reality―as well as that realization itself―as constructive, i.e., consisting of building, developing, and strengthening different ideas and concepts, be they concepts of ultimate reality, emptiness, primordial mind, and what not. Were he to argue that \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and Alīkākāravāda contemplatives engage in constructing and augmenting discordant ideas as the means of realizing their respective versions of ultimate reality, how would he be able to claim that despite constructing and cultivating those different ideas in contemplative practice, \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and Alīkākāravāda practitioners can somehow achieve the same realization as a result of that practice? It would be similar to claiming that a person who meditates on a white square and a person who meditates on a red triangle can achieve a vivid vision of one and the same phenomenon as a result of those meditations. Another example we can think of is constructing different houses with different materials, giving them different shapes and sizes, and painting them with different colors. To claim that such construction activities can somehow result in building absolutely identical houses would indeed be mystical!

Note another important element of Shakya Chokden’s approach: he is far from claiming that all mental impediments can be destroyed with any deconstructive technique. After all, is it possible to destroy all types of walls with just any tools? Of course not! Shakya Chokden’s position is likewise much more specific and restrictive: he is claiming that in the non-tantric context only \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) and Alīkākāravāda tools are sufficient for destroying impediments to direct realization of ultimate reality. And here he is not different from other Tibetan thinkers who also treat systems “lower” than Madhyamaka as insufficient for achieving this objective because according to them those “lower” systems do not provide valid means for destroying impediments to that realization. In fact, this is one of the main reasons why Shakya Chokden works so hard to demonstrate in his writings that Alīkākāravāda Yogācāra is Madhyamaka and not Cittamātra: treating it as Cittamātra (or any other system below Madhyamaka) would immediately exclude it from the category of those systems that provide effective means for realization of ultimate reality.

The lesson we learn from Shakya Chokden, therefore, is much more nuanced than something along the lines of “different traditions can bring their followers to the same mystical experience despite the fact that they describe such experience differently.” Rather, his position suggests that in order to understand whether, when, and how followers of different traditions can achieve similar mystical experiences, we have to analyze the deconstructive processes that they utilize in contemplative practice. Were those processes not deconstructive, any claims of common mystical experiences achieved as their result would be groundless.

Consequently, besides exploring the questions of whether mystical experiences are constructed or not and whether they are mediated or not, we also have to explore in more detail the actual processes leading to those experiences. If we want to explore similarities between different mystical traditions―including those that claim their mystical experiences are unmediated at the time of their occurrence―we have to analyze what their followers attempt to deconstruct, what they claim to have deconstructed, and most importantly what tools they use to achieve that deconstruction. If it is possible to demonstrate that those tools are equally effective, we might go ahead and claim that despite different cultures, backgrounds, worldviews, etc., followers of those traditions can achieve the same mystical experience. Otherwise, we might as well be satisfied to conclude that they simply have irreconcilable differences and particularities. But obviously a survey of that breadth is beyond the scope of this paper.

The approach outlined here is, I believe, beneficial in several respects. First, it provides an alternative way of analyzing the issue of (un)mediated mystical experience by shifting our attention from the question of the possibility of such an experience to the actual techniques designed to induce it. Second, it takes us beyond the boundaries of the “Western” intellectual world, drawing our attention to perspectives on mystical experience developed by Buddhists such as Shakya Chokden who―together with numerous thinkers from other Asian religious traditions―concur that it is possible to have a non-conceptual, unmediated experience of their version of the ultimate that nonetheless has to be intentionally triggered by particular contemplative techniques.Footnote 74 And last, but not least, it might take us beyond purely textual studies of mysticism to the world of field research that would consist of observing contemplative techniques practiced by followers of different traditions, discussing with them their experience of relationship between those contemplative processes and their intended results, and perhaps even personally participating in those practices as a means of personal intimate understanding.

This article was primarily concerned with what Buddhists themselves have to say about―and contribute to―the question of (un)mediated mystical experience. It is self-evident that similar to varieties of mystical experiences that emerge as a result of specific conditioning used in other religions, in Buddhism too there are reported different mystical experiences that are conditioned by uniquely Buddhist techniques. The problematic question raised in this article was whether Buddhism allows for unmediated mystical experiences. In my analysis of the processes involved in the key Buddhist mystical experience―direct realization of ultimate reality―I argued that most Buddhist thinkers (represented in this paper by Shakya Chokden) treat this experience as unmediated by words and concepts at the time of its occurrence. Nevertheless, such realization is seen as necessarily mediated in terms of being triggered by preceding conditioning processes that are uniquely Buddhist in character.

Buddhists diverge in their interpretations of the nature of ultimate reality and the processes leading to its realization. The main question targeted throughout this article was whether, despite that diversity, Buddhism allows for the same mystical experience to be triggered by different conditioning processes. My analysis of Shakya Chokden’s position demonstrated that according to at least some thinkers this is possible, but only in limited cases, such as those of Alīkākāravāda and \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \).

This article was not concerned with possible commonalities between Buddhist and non-Buddhist mystical experiences in general (except for the category of “mundane paths” that Buddhists take as common to themselves and some groups of non-Buddhist contemplatives). Analysis of the direct realization of ultimate reality in terms of Buddhist mind and path models demonstrates that it is necessarily triggered by uniquely Buddhist means. In contrast to the Alīkākāravāda and \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) approaches addressed above, we cannot claim the sameness of this particular mystical experience in Buddhism and other religions. The reason is that the Alīkākāravāda and \( {\text{Ni}}\mathop{\text{h}}\limits_{ \cdot } {\text{svabh}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{vav}}\overline {\text{a}} {\text{da}} \) systems rely on conditioning processes based on reasoning aimed at the deconstruction of concepts; as long as it can be demonstrated that their reasoning is equally valid, it is also possible to claim that it can eventually bring about the same mystical experience―the direct realization of ultimate reality. This is clearly not the case in other religious systems that provide neither such reasoning nor conditioning processes based on that reasoning. And even in the Buddhist context, such an option is open within the narrow confines of some Mahāyāna traditions only.

Nevertheless, this research might be profitably extended by exploring whether certain specific practitioners within certain Buddhist and non-Buddhist traditions might share at least some types of mystical experience. It is too early to anticipate any specific results at this point. But even if such research demonstrates more differences than similarities, more plurality than commonality between the mystical experiences of different traditions, that finding itself might be significant and serve an important purpose.