1 Motivation

The most relevant conceptual difference between left and right wing political parties relates to the different weights assigned to economic growth and income distribution. Implicit in this discussion is the assumption that faster growth can only come with increasing income inequality. For instance, progressive tax structures are good from an inequality reduction perspective, but distort the optimal allocation of resources and therefore hamper growth.

This discussion mimics the philosophical debate between utilitarianism and egalitarianism. The purest utilitarian view is concerned with the maximization of individual well-being while the purest egalitarian view puts the emphasis on the reduction of inequality. Due to the traditional skepticism of economists about subjective satisfaction indicators most of the utilitarian-egalitarian debate has been framed in terms of maximizing income or reducing income inequality. But neither from a utilitarian nor an egalitarian point of view is income an end in itself. Happiness research has picked up this debate and brought it closer to its original aims.Footnote 1

In this paper we estimate how much happiness inequality is reasonable to expect from a given level of income inequality, and compare this with real measures of happiness inequality. The gap between these two measures is an indication of the effect on happiness of non-pecuniary dimensions of life.

The basic microeconomic textbook assumes that utility is a function of consumption and that consumers maximize utility subject to their budget constraint. This permits the representation of an indirect utility function that depends positively on income. Reported happiness levels are supposed to reflect utility levels, and therefore establish a theoretical link between income and happiness.Footnote 2

Since utility depends on income, and income inequality is a stylized fact of modern economies, it is natural to expect happiness inequality. The textbook utility maximization model assumes that marginal utility decreases with income. This means that an extra dollar makes a poor person happier than a rich person. This implies that happiness inequality should be lower than income inequality. But how much lower?

2 Data and Methodology

2.1 Data

We use income and happiness data from the 2006 Gallup World Poll. The Gallup World Poll is probably the world’s most comprehensive database of behavioral economic measures. It continually surveys citizens in more than 140 countries representing about 95% of the world’s adult population. In this paper we use data for 113 countries.

The level of happiness in the Gallup World Poll is a personal assessment of general well-being. The question reads “Please imagine a ladder/mountain with steps numbered from zero at the bottom to ten at the top. Suppose we say that the top of the ladder/mountain represents the best possible life for you and the bottom of the ladder/mountain represents the worst possible life for you. If the top step is 10 and the bottom step is 0, on which step of the ladder/mountain do you feel you personally stand at the present time?”

Annual income data is reported in 29 brackets ($0, less than $1 a day, $1–$2 a day, more than $730 and less than $1,099 per year, more than $1,100 and less than $1,499 per year, etc.). We imputed the average of the bracket to each individual within the bracket. For the top bracket we imputed a value equal to double the previous imputed value (i.e. individuals in the bracket from $75,000 to $124,999 were assumed to have an annual income of $100.000 and individuals in the bracket of more than $125.000 were assumed to have an annual income level of $200.000).

2.2 Utility Levels

A common functional form for the utility function is

$$ \begin{aligned} u(y) & = \frac{{y^{1 - \rho } }}{1 - \rho } + k\quad {\text{if }}\rho \ne 1 \\ u(y) & = \log (y) + k\quad {\text{if }}\rho = 1 \\ \end{aligned} $$
(1)

where u is the utility level, y the income level and ρ and k are parameters.

For all positive values of ρ the utility function exhibits decreasing marginal utility. The larger ρ, the faster the marginal utility decreases as income increases. Therefore, the larger ρ the lower the level of inequality in utility levels. To compute individual utility level we need an estimate of ρ and k.

As explained in the appendix ρ bares a direct interpretation as a measure of relative risk aversion and has received a lot of empirical attention, especially in the financial literature. Many economists think that ρ is between 1 and 2, but there is a wide range of estimates, with some going up to 10 and others going as low as 0.2.

Another issue that we must address is that the inequality measure that we use (Gini) is defined only on the positives but the utility function can take negative values (when k = 0). In order to compute the Gini coefficient for utility we have to assume a positive value for k. The larger this parameter, the lower the level of inequality. Therefore, to make our computations as conservativeFootnote 3 as possible we calibrate k so that the minimum utility level for each country equals 0.Footnote 4

2.3 Measuring Inequality

There are several statistics that could be used to measure inequality. Kalmijn and Veenhoven (2005) discuss the pros and cons of nine different statistics for measuring happiness inequality. In particular, they consider the standard deviation and the Gini coefficient and conclude that the standard deviation is superior to the Gini for happiness inequality. Notwithstanding, in this paper we use the Gini to measure inequality in income, happiness and utility for the following reasons.

First, we need a measure of inequality that allows us to compare inequality in income, happiness and utility. As stated by Kalmijn and Veenhoven (2005), income is not expressed as a number only, but rather as the combination of a number and a unit of measure (dollars, euros, pesos, etc.). The inequality statistic needs to be dimensionless, i.e. changing the unit of measure must not change the inequality statistic. The Gini has this property but the standard deviation does not. This is one of the reasons why in the income inequality literature the preferred statistic is the Gini and not the standard deviation.

A second reason is that happiness inequality research is a very new field, while there is a much longer tradition of income inequality research. We do not have a large enough body of work to compare and draw conclusions about which standard deviation values imply large or small inequality levels. On the other hand, the availability of Gini estimates for almost every country in the world (and for several years) facilitates the comparison of our results.

A potential problem in measuring happiness and utility inequality is that both are ordinal concepts. Any inequality statistic implicitly treats these ordinal numbers as cardinal numbers, which means that happiness ratings are considered equidistant. That is to say, if individuals are given three options to rate their level of happiness (say 1, 2 and 3), the distance from the second level to the first is the same as the distance from the third level to the second.Footnote 5 This problem is not solved by the choice of statistic.

To check the robustness of our results, we applied a variation of the POLS transformation of variables proposed by VanPraag and Ferrer-i-Carbonell (2004) and estimated the inequality of this transformed measures of happiness. The results (not reported) were almost identical to the results reported here.

Finally, inequality measures may be affected by the disaggregation level at which the data is handled. The reported statistics use data at the maximum disaggregation available (11 brackets for happiness and 29 brackets for income) but we also performed a robustness exercise where we reduced the number of income brackets. The results are almost identical to those presented here.

At this point it is useful to introduce some additional notation. The measure of income inequality will be denoted G y , the Gini measure of happiness will be denoted G h and the utility inequality will be denoted G u (ρ) to make it clear that the utility dispersion is a function of ρ as discussed below.

2.4 Implications

The value of ρ determines how close G u (ρ) is to G y or G h . Table 1 presents four possible cases. If ρ = 0, the utility level is equal to the income level. In this case G u (0) = G y . If there are other elements that contribute to happiness that are not correlated with income this implies that G h  < G u (case 1)

Table 1 Parameter implication of utility dispersion

But when the utility function shows decreasing marginal utility of income (ρ > 0), the poorer the individual is, the larger an increase in utility an extra dollar generates. In this case G u (ρ) < G y . Suppose that initially every individual in a society has exactly the same income level and therefore the same utility level. Since there is no dispersion we have G u (ρ) = G y  = 0. Now suppose that half of the population receives additional income. The difference in income produces differences in utility levels and therefore both Gini indicators are positive, G y  > 0 and G u (ρ) > 0. Decreasing marginal utility of income implies G u (ρ) < G y . Moreover, the faster marginal utility decreases with income, the lower the dispersion in utility. Formally we have that \( \frac{{\partial G_{u} }}{\partial \rho } < 0 \). Therefore, it is likely that assuming a large enough ρ we could make the inequality measures of utility and happiness coincide. We denote the level of ρ that equalizes utility and happiness inequality as \( \bar{\rho } \), i.e. \( G_{u} \left( {\bar{\rho }} \right) = G_{h} \).

In Case 2, happiness inequality is equal to utility inequality. Since the only variable affecting utility is income; this means that happiness inequality can be explained simply by income differences

Cases 3 and 4 are the most interesting. Case 3 implies that income differentials generate a level of utility inequality above that of happiness inequality. Another interpretation of a situation when utility inequality is above happiness inequality is that there are other dimensions that affect the distribution of satisfaction with life as a whole that are not captured by an income based utility function. These non-pecuniary dimensions (e.g. satisfaction with family and friends) partially compensate for the differences in income so that in the end the differences in happiness levels are somewhat buffered.

Finally, in Case 4, happiness inequality is larger than the income derived utility inequality. This could be reinterpreted as a situation when the other dimensions of life that are not captured by the utility function are also positively correlated with income and therefore produce more happiness inequality that what we should except based only on income differences.

3 Results

In the appendix we present our estimations at the country level and a scatter plot of happiness inequality versus income inequality. In most cases the income Gini computed from our data is close to published Gini estimations. Table 2 presents the average measures of income and happiness inequality by region. As expected on theoretical grounds, the happiness Gini is lower than the income Gini. Worldwide, the ratio between these two indicators shows that the level of income inequality is about two times the level of happiness inequality.

Table 2 Gini income and Gini happiness by region

We observe that there is a clear difference between developed and less developed regions. Less developed regions show higher inequality both in income and happiness. The higher the income level, the lower the income and happiness inequality. We performed t tests of mean equality that confirm that income inequality is statistically significantly different between income-defined-regions. On the other hand, it is not possible to reject the null hypothesis of same happiness inequality levels between low, lower-middle and upper-middle income countries. At conventional significance levels, happiness inequality in high income countries is statistically lower than in lower income countries.

As argued above, the fact that happiness inequality is lower than income inequality is a natural consequence of the decreasing marginal utility of income. To have an idea of how much happiness inequality is due to income inequality we use Eq. 1 to compute utility levels under different assumptions of ρ, i.e. degrees of decreasing marginal utility of income. In Table 3 we present inequality measures of these simulated utility levels. As expected, utility inequality decreases with ρ. Table 4 presents the ratio between the utility Gini and the happiness Gini. It can be interpreted as the part of happiness inequality that is accounted for income inequality.

Table 3 Simulated levels of happiness inequality by region
Table 4 How much happiness inequality is reasonable? G u (ρ)/G h

It is striking that only in Sub-Saharian-Africa does the Gini for utility mimic the Gini for happiness for ρs above 1 (recall that the financial literature suggests that ρ is between 1 and 2).

If the true ρ is at least 1, this means that the non-pecuniary dimensions of life are also correlated with income (and utility) everywhere but in Sub-Saharian-Africa. Rich individuals are happier not only because they are rich and can consume more, but also because in other dimensions of life (e.g. family, social cohesion) they are more satisfied than poor people. This is case 4 in Table 1. It may be that family structure is more solid for richer individuals than poorer. This may also impact on family relations and health. Which are the non pecuniary dimensions producing this result and how this is channeled is beyond the scope of this paper.

Table 4 implies that for ρs above 1, about half of the happiness inequality can be accounted for by differences in income (with ρ = 1.0 it accounts for between 40 and 86% of the difference). The rest must come from other dimensions.

4 Conclusions

In this paper we report that happiness inequality is much lower than income inequality. This is a natural consequence of the decreasing marginal utility of income. This marginal utility of income can be calibrated using estimates of relative risk aversion (ρ), but the empirical literature on risk aversion has not yet achieved consensus on its value. Unfortunately, this precludes us from giving a definitive answer to the question of how much happiness inequality should be expected given a certain level of income inequality. If the coefficient of relative risk aversion is above one, as much of the financial literature mentioned earlier indicates, then there is a sizable part of happiness inequality that is not related to income inequality, and therefore governments should be interested in addressing the causes of these non-pecuniary inequalities. Our results are in line with earlier studies that found only a modest correlation (Ott 2005) between income and happiness and studies on change over time that observed a trend to lower inequality of happiness in spite of rising inequality of incomes (Veenhoven 2005).