Risky decisions typically do not involve isolated choices among abstract lotteries. Rather, there is often the opportunity to make an investment that affects the lottery structure. This additional element of choice increases the cognitive challenges posed by the risky decision, making it more difficult to ascertain the optimal choice. This article examines these individual decisions when made in a group context. Unlike existing treatments of herding effects, there is full information about probabilities and payoffs. The remaining uncertainty is with respect to individual preferences in the face of a complex task. Observing decisions by others in a group can potentially provide guidance with respect to the optimal choice. This article utilizes a series of experiments to explore this phenomenon.

Decisions that involve risk and require up-front investments often are made in a group environment. Examples abound. Families make down payments and finance improvements on their residence; they decide how much to spend and where to send children for their education; they save for retirement. Non-profit and for-profit boards approve major employment contracts, undertake new capital projects, and acquire other organizations or companies. Potentially large numbers of people vote on regulating business activity and funding community development. And in the context of our experimental design, groups consider whether to engage in litigation, where the cost of litigation is paid before the outcome is known. In general, risky financial decisions are arguably more prevalent in group environments than when individuals make decisions in isolation.

While the difference in decision-making behavior between groups and individuals has recently been the subject of much academic research, relatively little is known about group behavior in which there is an investment component to the risky decision. Individuals may act differently because of the separate and related effects of (1) being embedded in a group and (2) the group decision rule. Most theoretical and empirical models of risky decision-making assume that the decision-making group acts as a rational economic agent, without taking group informational dynamics and decision-making rules into account.

This article seeks to fill this void by presenting experimental evidence that illuminates how a group environment affects risky decisions. Individual investment decisions that affect the lottery structure are compared to those made in three different group environments in which the group faces the same range of risky investments as the individual. In each group context, participants have real-time information (RTI) that enables them to observe the desired investment amounts of others, and they can revise their investment recommendations based on these observations. Both RTI alone and the group decision rule—deciding how much to invest either based on the median value (as in majority rule) or the minimum value (as in unanimous rule)—may influence individual choices. The experimental design allows us to distinguish the separate effects of simply observing what others want to do and the group decision rule, track how people change, and test for significance.

Our experiment involves the choice of an investment amount, where higher investment levels at first increase the chance of obtaining a higher payoff, but after a point greater investment levels reduce the net expected payoff. To operationalize the investment decision in both an individual and group setting, we construct a decision context that makes people contemplate filing a lawsuit. In our scenarios, up-front investments must be made to earn an uncertain return.

Investing more in the lawsuit increases the probability of winning the case, but the expected payoff net of litigation costs eventually declines as the investment increases. Although subjects in our experiments are presented with this concrete decision problem, its general form is one that has a concave expected payoff schedule. Hence in terms of expected returns, too much can be invested to achieve a desired outcome. The temptation to throw money at an endeavor can easily be extended to other situations where emotions run high because of a strong desire to prevail, for example in paying for a child’s rearing and education, or providing for the health care of a loved one.Footnote 1

In the group settings, RTI allows every individual to instantly observe the amounts recommended by other members of the group; people can change their commitment to the endeavor as they see how others are committing. In two of the three group situations there is a common group decision based on either the median value or the minimum value that eventually determines an identical payoff for each member of the group. Because two treatment effects essentially take place in these group sessions, one being the decision rule and the other being able to observe what all group members want to invest in real time, we isolate the effect of RTI based on an RTI-only treatment, in which individuals are in a group that is strictly informational; they can observe what others do, but their payoffs depend only on their own decision.

A priori one would not expect there to be strongly different effects on an individual’s behavior from these group contexts, particularly for the RTI case in which the individual’s own investment determines the individual’s payoff. All experimental participants have full information regarding probabilities and payoffs, and they can presumably make decisions based on their own willingness to bear risk. Thus, providing information on other people’s decisions should have no effect if the individual’s payoff is governed solely by one’s individual choice. However, risky decisions pose well-known difficulties for individual decision-making. If individuals have noisy preferences and are uncertain about whether they have made their expected utility-maximizing choice, observing others’ choices may provide information on possible errors in their private decision.

The experimental results show a strong influence of the group context. Being able to observe the decisions made by others influences subjects’ choices irrespective of whether the lottery payoffs are based on the individual’s investment decision, the majority group decision, or a unanimous group decision. In all these group contexts, subjects should select their personal utility-maximizing choice. Nevertheless, there is both an influence of others’ preferences as well as the group decision rule. There are important framing effects on investment choices based on the group decision in conjunction with group members’ choices.

Section 1 reviews the pertinent literature, much of which deals with herding effects. Unlike previous treatments of group decisions in which risky choices are influenced by others’ behavior, our experimental subjects have full information about all probabilities and payoffs. Section 2 summarizes the experimental design, which consists of multiple components that make it possible to distinguish the informational impact of being in a group environment as well as the framing effects of the group decision rule. Section 3 presents our experimental hypotheses, several of which pertain to whether the group environment should lead to decisions that are more risky or less risky than when decisions are made in isolation. After providing an overall summary of the results in Section 4, Section 5 presents a detailed statistical analysis of the determinants of the levels of individual investment decisions, whether decisions made in a group context are more or less risky than decisions made in isolation, and the effect of the group decision rule. Section 6 concludes.

1 Comparison with related literature

Our analysis of decisions in both individual and group contexts intersects with several related literatures. It is instructive to briefly review these intersections, as doing so helps in formulating the experimental hypotheses and in highlighting the distinctive nature of our study.

Because of the information exchanged in group contexts, choices made in a group environment may be different than those made by an individual not exposed to the choices of other people. Models of group polarization, such as Glaeser and Sunstein (2009), recognize herding effects or information cascades generated by observing others’ choices, as this information may alter the assessed probabilities and consequently affect decisions in the group environment.Footnote 2 The distinctive aspect of our work is that unlike all such previous studies, people in our study always have full information about all probabilities and payoffs.Footnote 3 We find that participants alter their choices even though there is no uncertainty regarding the probabilities or the lottery payoffs; all participants have full information.

Unlike the findings in the existing literature, there is no rational basis for such an effect. What we suggest is that the complexity of making investment decisions that alter the lottery structure makes people unsure of their optimal investment amount. Observing decisions made by others can potentially be of assistance.

If people observe risky decisions made by others in the group, will there be systematic effects on the riskiness of decisions? Will people become more risk-taking or less risk-taking after observing others’ behavior? Changes in the riskiness of choices in the direction of taking greater risk are known as a risky shift; risk shifts associated with less risk are known as conservative shifts or cautious shifts.Footnote 4 Most studies have found evidence of a risky shift.Footnote 5 Shupp and Williams (2008) observe in a study on lottery valuation decisions that the difference in risk preferences between groups and individuals depends at least partly on the stakes: the average group is more risk-averse than the average individual in high-risk situations, while this is reversed for low-risk situations.

Our study differs from this literature in that for the experimental treatment that couples RTI with individual choice, there is no actual group interaction or group decision rule, only an exchange of information on choices. We compare the pure RTI results for individual decisions to the decisions individuals make when there is a group decision rule in order to analyze the nature of the risky shift across our different experimental treatments. In contrast to Shupp and Williams (2008), we do not allow for any form of communication even in treatments with group-decision rules.

Our experimental design includes a component in which subjects make individual choices in a group context subject to a group decision rule that specifies either majority rule or unanimity. Whether the group decision rule affects investment decisions provides an additional perspective on whether there is an effect of influences other than those dictated by rational utility-maximizing choice. In particular, are there influential framing effects of the group decisions rule?

For RTI group contexts in which the investment amount is guided by the median or minimum decision rule, one would not expect the group context alone to alter individual choices. When preferences are single-peaked, basing group decisions on the median value is equivalent to the results with simple majority rule. When unanimity is required, the lowest individual investment in the group guides the group decision. Thus, our case in which the lowest investment amount determines the outcome is analogous to the unanimous choice case though our experiment does not require agreement by the entire group. The person with the lowest investment amount in the minimum value treatment has no incentive to raise that amount, and the subjects with the higher investment amounts have no incentive to lower their amounts in this group setting.Footnote 6

When the group RTI environment is coupled with a group decision rule, we find framing effects and group norms at work even when group members interact in a relatively sterile environment that allows them to only register their investment “votes” on a computer screen. Median investor and minimum investor rules not only define the payoff structure of the experiment but also have a framing effect in highlighting the pivotal values in the group context. Framing effects are well established in the psychology literature, but the major task always has been to predict ex ante how the frame will affect the decisions.Footnote 7 The median and minimum value rules have well-defined, predictable focal points that are described in the experiments as being the instrumental value that will govern group decisions. By comparing the amounts spent as individuals alone and as individuals in a group, it is possible to quantify the effect of RTI and the framing and social norm effects of the group contexts on investments.Footnote 8

The group investment decision is made by the subjects revealing how much they are willing to invest, rather than for example simply asking members for a vote on whether to invest a specific amount or not. These features of the experiment create a rich data set on how people and groups make decisions in a context that has risk, and for which net gains are concave. The findings provide evidence of a strong influence of RTI both when choices are governed by a group decision rule as well as when individuals make their own decision after being exposed to RTI from other members of the group.

2 Experimental design

The experimental design compares an individual’s investment decision with a group of six people facing the same decision. Each treatment consists of four parts—two lotteries (Part I and Part II), one individual investment decision (Part III), and one group investment decision (Part IV). These parts are sequenced differently in experimental sessions. The Part I and II lotteries were always stages 1 and 2 of an experimental session and were identical across all treatments.

To develop a risk aversion variable to be used as a control variable in the analysis of the risky investment decisions, in Part I of the experiment subjects considered the Holt and Laury (2002) lottery choices used to measure an individual’s risk aversion. As described in Appendix A, subjects exhibited a moderate degree of risk aversion with a coefficient of relative risk aversion of 0.21. Only 17% of the subjects failed to express consistent lottery choices, and subsequent empirical analysis controls for this behavior. Appendix B describes the results of Part II of the experiment, which acquainted subjects with a lottery structure in which the expected payoff level rises then falls as the investment amount increases.

Part III, the individual investment decision, was also identical across all treatments, but in three treatments this part was conducted in stage 3 before the group decisions, which we refer to as original order, while in the other three treatments it was in stage 4 after the group decisions, which we refer to as reversed order. Finally, as we explain in more detail below, there were three variations of Part IV, the group investment decision. Table 1 provides an overview of the order of all parts in all six treatments. The treatments are different based on the order of the parts and the group environment in Part IV.

Table 1 Experimental treatments

We recruited 144 subjects from college undergraduate and graduate classes. Each treatment consisted of two sessions with groups of 12, which were later divided into groups of six for the group treatments. Subjects reported to a computer lab, where each person was seated at a terminal. The experiment was programmed and conducted with the software z-Tree (Fischbacher 2007). At the beginning of each stage of the experiment, instructions were read aloud as subjects followed along on their written copies. Instructions to a subsequent stage of the experiment were not given to subjects until they had completed all of their choices in the current stage of the experiment. Sessions ran for about forty-five minutes from start to finish, when subjects were paid in cash. Average earnings were about $18.00.

2.1 Individual investments

To implement the lottery decision and establish the context for the subsequent group decision, Part III of the experiment gives subjects a hypothetical product liability case in which they must make a decision on going forward as a plaintiff.Footnote 9 The instructions to subjects begin with the following case scenario.

Imagine a defective product has led to a serious injury to a member of your family. A product safety expert has reviewed the accident and concluded that the company was negligent in the manufacture of the product. Your attorney believes that you have a strong case to recoup damages from the manufacturer for the medical costs and pain and suffering associated with the accident.

The product manufacturer is a small firm that does not have a good safety record. The company has no insurance but relies instead on a policy of vigorously fighting any lawsuits against it. Your attorney advises you that the better you fund your potential case against the company the greater your chances of winning the case. However, the more you spend, the more the defendant spends, reducing the funds the company will have available to pay your claim. As a result, the amount of money you receive from winning the case falls as you spend more. If you lose the case you only have your original budget minus your payments.

Individuals in Part III of the experiment and groups of six in Part IV of the experiment are given a budget of $5.00 to invest in this potential lawsuit. They must choose how much to invest and can choose to not file a complaint. The instructions present decision-makers with a sample table of what they can expect when they go forward with the case. The payoff structure is reported in Table 2, where the subjects were not informed of the expected lottery values that appear in parentheses. Outcome A is winning the case and Outcome B is losing the case. Since the decision variable is continuous, but the table shows only nine discrete choices, subjects are told that the table should be thought of “as nine example payments and possible outcomes.”

Table 2 Lottery structure for the individual and group investment experimentsa

In addition to providing the information in Table 2, subjects are informed that the probability of Outcome A is (0.2 × payment) and the probability of Outcome B is (1 - probability of Outcome A). The net amount paid if Outcome A results is $15 - 2 × ($ payment) and the net amount paid if Outcome B results is $5 - ($ payment). Table 2 adjusts in fifty cent increments, but subjects were reminded that they could choose any dollar and cents amount from $0.00 to $4.99. The expected values of the outcomes are shown in parentheses in the far right column for each entry. These values were not given to subjects in the experiment. Notice that the expected value function is concave. It starts at $5.00, rises to a maximum of $6.25, and then falls to $5.45.

2.2 Group decisions

Part IV, which is conducted in stage 3 or stage 4 of the experiment, is the “group” decision. In all of the experimental sessions there were twelve subjects divided anonymously into two groups of six, half of whom considered individual and group decisions in the original (Original) order and half considered group and individual choices in the reversed (Reversed) order. We will refer to the case in which the median decision determines the group investment decisions as majority rule and the minimum investment determines the group investment decision as unanimous rule. Dollars are votes that not only determine the relative standings of subjects but also are a measure of intensity of preferences. These dollar votes do not necessarily describe “willingness to pay” because of the nonlinearity of payoffs and the voting rule.

The group contexts consist of majority (Majority) rule (either Original-Majority or Reversed-Majority), unanimous (Unanimous) rule (either Original-Unanimous or Reversed-Unanimous), and individual choice in a group of six with RTI so that they could observe (Observe) how the others were investing (Original-Observe or Reversed-Observe). In the latter RTI treatments without a group decision rule, subjects were told that they could observe the investment choices of the other five members of the group, but otherwise there was no interaction between members. Individuals in all group settings had a two-minute period in which to observe and revise their investment decisions as many times as they wished.Footnote 10 Subjects were told that in majority rule the fourth-highest amount determined what the group pays. In unanimous rule the smallest amount determined the amount paid to undertake the lawsuit. This is the most that all six subjects will pay to go forward. Alternatively, it could be viewed as the marginal amount required for one individual to not go along with the group investment in the lawsuit.

3 Hypotheses

The choice situations in both the individual and group contexts involve investment decisions that affect the probabilities of a lottery outcome. Let w be the individual’s initial wealth, x the investment amount, y the value of the top prize, z the value of the bottom prize, p(x) the probability of winning the top prize where p′(x)>0, and v(w) the utility function where v′(w) >0. The experimental task in person i’s initial choice in the baseline situation is

$$ \mathop {{Max}}\limits_{{x_i}} \;p\left( {{x_i}} \right)v\left( {w + y - {x_i}} \right) + \left( {1 - p\left( {{x_i}} \right)} \right)v\left( {w + z - {x_i}} \right). $$
(1)

We denote the optimal xi chosen during the RTI part by person i at time t by \( {\text{x}}_{\text{i}}^* \).

In the real-time information case, all participants can observe the entire vector of Xt of responses at any point t, where t is from 0 to 2 min. In the RTI environments, the value of xir will be the optimal choice conditional on observing this information, or

$$ {{\text{x}}_{\text{ir}}} = \left( {{\text{x}}_{\text{i}}^*\left| {{{\text{X}}_{\text{t}}}} \right.} \right). $$
(2)

Because the p(x) function is shared information for all participants, observing Xt does not provide information about p(x) as in the standard models of herding and information cascades.

Observing Xt may provide information about whether the individual has made the correct lottery decision.Footnote 11 Consider a simple case in which the person initially chose xi0 but thought that there was a nonzero probability that xi0−ε or xi0 + ε was the expected utility-maximizing choice, so that there could be errors in either direction. The error could arise because the individual may have difficulty performing the expected utility calculation for the lottery or may be uncertain about the underlying utility function that should guide decisions. If many group members pick xi values above xi0, the individual may increase the assessed likelihood that a higher investment choice is optimal even though there is no group aspect to the decision other than information regarding their decisions. Similarly, observing that others are disproportionately choosing lower investment levels may lead the individual to lower the chosen investment amount.

For the majority decision rule, an individual chooses an optimal xim and under the unanimity decision rule an individual chooses an optimal xiu, given both the information about Xt and knowledge of the group decision rule m or u, which affects the salience of the components of Xt. The experimental instructions specify that for majority rule the fourth-highest payoff will determine the decision affecting all members in the group, while for the unanimous choice rule it is the lowest, or sixth-highest investment amount in the group of six that determines the shared group’s investment. If the i values are used to denote the ordinal rank in the group decision context, the investment value is x4m for majority rule and x6u for unanimity.

We examine our first hypothesis of risky shifts in investment amounts by comparing the values of xi0 and xir, which are affected only by the information Xt and not by the framing effect of a group decision rule. While it may, for example, be the case that xim > xi0 and xiu > xi0, the group decision rule’s framing effects also may affect the observed shifts. For the range of choices selected by the respondents, increasing the investment in the group context raises the expected value of the lottery, and we examine both the direction of the shift and whether the investment level is beyond the point where the expected payoff is at its maximum value.

  1. Hypothesis 1.

    Providing real-time information about others’ choices will produce a risky shift.

Based on the initial distribution of investment values, x40 > x60 by definition. Unless the framing effect of the decision rule alters this ranking in an unexpected manner, the fourth-highest investment amount with majority rule will exceed the lowest investment amount with unanimity. There is no unambiguous theoretical prediction for the relation of the average investment in the observe environment \( {\overline {\text{x}}_{\text{ir}}} \) and x40 and x60, as that will depend on how the framing effect of the group decision rule alters the subsequent distribution of responses. We expect the majority rule and the unanimous rule to influence the group decision differently.

  1. Hypothesis 2.

    The group investment choice with majority rule x 4m should exceed the group choice with unanimity x 6u .

For the RTI group treatments we expect the following trends in investment behavior.

  1. Hypothesis 3.

    Each of the three group environments will generate changes in levels of investment. 3a) For the RTI observe treatment, there should be an increase in x ir levels above the x i0 values if there is a risky shift. There is no framing effect that will influence the distribution of these changes. 3b) For majority rule with RTI, there may be a risky shift, but there should also be a convergence toward the median with decreases in high values and increases in low values. 3c) For unanimous choice with RTI, there may also be a risky shift, but the low values may rise relative to the higher values, and there may be downward movement from the higher values because of the role of social norms and the asymmetry of the decision rule.

We test these hypotheses in two ways. First, we examine the direction of movement. Do more people increase their xi values or decrease them, and on balance is the magnitude of the increases greater? Second, we explore the within-group composition of the movement. Thus, do the particular ranks within the Xt group change their xi values in the predicted manner?

The experiments were run both in the normal order in which individuals made their own investment decisions and reversed order in which the group context was first and the individual choice followed. If the provision of RTI provides information about the optimal risky investment choice that subjects take into account when valuing the lottery decisions, then for the reversed order there should be a lasting effect of RTI that also influences the subsequent individual choice. Thus, there should not be a reversal of the effect of the RTI group information if there is actual learning and information acquisition associated with the RTI.

  1. Hypothesis 4.

    There should not be a reversal of the effects of RTI in the reversed order experiment if RTI has a lasting effect on the perception and valuation of lotteries.

Our fifth hypothesis examines the relation between the person-specific measures of the constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) obtained using the Holt-Laury procedure and the group investment decision. More risk-averse respondents should make lower investment levels. The effect of respondent gender, which may be correlated with risk attitudes, will also be examined.

  1. Hypothesis 5.

    Higher levels of individual risk aversion will tend to decrease the size of any risky investment.

4 Summary of individual and group investment decisions

Table 3 highlights data from Parts III and IV of the experiments with the choices in Table 2. Column (1) lists each group of six subjects by treatment. There are four groups in each treatment. In each treatment n = 24. There are three treatments that have individual choices before subjects are placed in a group choice environment, denoted by original order with a total n = 72. As already described, Part III and Part IV of the experiment may be switched. These are the reversed order treatments. There are three treatments that have individual choices after the group exposure, denoted by reversed order with a total n = 72.

Table 3 Individual and group investmentsa

Columns numbered 2–4 display the investment amounts. Column (2), labeled “Average Individual Investment,” is the amount that each person in the group of six would pay to go forward with the litigation. The Group Environment column, column (3), is the average that a group of six players would invest. This is Part IV of the experiment in its original order and may precede Part III in the reversed order treatment. This is not the actual amount paid when the decision was made by the majority or a unanimous rule. For the Original-Majority and Reversed-Majority groups the amount paid was decided by the fourth-highest amount. The amount that each person actually settled upon in the group environment is shown on the right side of Table 3 in column (4). For example, the average that group Original-Majority-1 wanted to pay was $1.46, and the amount paid based on the group decision rule was $1.25. The amounts listed from lowest to highest 1.25, 1.25, 1.25, 1.50, 1.50, 2.00 are what each person settled upon as their vote to pay, knowing that there was a majority rule enforced.

There are 72 subjects who make an individual choice in stage 3 before group interaction and 72 subjects who make the same choice in stage 4 after group interaction. Table 3 allows us to make some preliminary observations on how much a group invests compared to what members would do individually. Comparing the investments subjects make in and out of a group setting, it is clear that the Observe treatment in the bottom two panels of Table 3 has the greatest impact on individual behavior.

Individuals alone in the Original-Observe and Reversed-Observe treatments make an average investment of $2.01, but when they observe the decisions of others in the group, their investment rises to $2.62. This is about a 30% difference so there is a substantial risk shift consistent with the risky shift predicted by Hypothesis 1. However, this investment level is not different from $2.50 at 10% or less significance levels. Mandatory group action tempers the difference between what the individual would do alone and in a group setting. In the Original-Majority and Reversed-Majority treatments, individuals alone would invest $2.40, but with group input their average individual values rise to $2.45. In the Original-Unanimous and Reversed-Unanimous treatments individuals alone would invest $2.20, and with group input investments fall to $2.07. Tests for significant differences in means are conducted by a simple difference of means test.Footnote 12

The average individual investments in the Original-Observe and Reversed-Observe individual choice treatments are significantly different than the individual investments in the group setting at a critical level of 10% or less. Subjects invest significantly more when they are simply informed in an interactive process of what others are doing. In contrast, the average individual investments in the Original-Majority and Reversed-Majority treatments and the amounts actually paid in the group environment are not significantly different. As well, the average individual investments and those voted by the group in the Original-Unanimous and Reversed-Unanimous treatments are not significantly different.

Hence a group decision governed by either a majority or unanimous rule will not yield a group average that is significantly different than what the average individual would recommend for litigation. A majority rule will not yield an investment decision that is significantly different from what the average individual in the group would recommend. The investment will be significantly lower with unanimous rule, as predicted by Hypothesis 2. Table 3 shows that the Original-Unanimous and Reversed-Unanimous groups respectively pay 22% and 34% less than the average individual in the group. Hence while majority rule represents the average individual in the group, unanimous rule is substantially more conservative in amounts spent.

This is not the case when the people make an individual decision to move forward when they simply observe what other individuals are doing. The Original-Observe treatments in the experiment yield significantly higher investment amounts than when the investment amount is kept confidential. In the Original-Observe treatment subjects pay 45% more to go forward with a case in the informed setting as opposed to the confidential setting. In the Reversed-Observe setting they pay 19% more. We note that subjects in both the Original-Observe and Reversed-Observe group environments are inclined to invest more than the $2.50 amount that maximizes expected value. However, the respective $2.63 and $2.61 average investments are not significantly different from $2.50.

5 Analyses of individual choices in the group decision contexts

We now turn to a more careful comparison of the results in the different group decision contexts. Aggregated observations can cancel out differences in individual behavior patterns. Table 3 for example indicates that there are effects on the mean riskiness of decisions, but focusing on the means and abstracting from the composition of individual choices may give an inaccurate characterization of risk shifts. Participants in the group contexts all shared the same information about decisions by others and could use this information either in making a decision affecting their payoffs alone or as part of the majority or unanimous rule group decision process. How the information is used, however, may be conditional on outcomes in other stages of the experiment and other factors such as risk aversion and gender. We present the analysis beginning with the original order results so that we can analyze the individual decision, and the subsequent effect on individual decisions of decision making within the group and RTI environments. We then consider the reversed order treatments to examine the permanency of the effect of the information presented in the group contexts.

5.1 OLS regression results

The regression results in Table 4 analyze the determinants of the person’s individual investment amount in the Part IV group decision context for original order. All group contexts include RTI, and the dependent variable is the person’s individual investment level decision in Part IV of the experiment, not the total group investment level. The individual investment decisions variables in Table 4 all pertain to individual experiments in which there is no group component so that there is no interdependency of these variables across respondents. The first model includes the value of the individual investment in the Part III individual decision as well as indicators for Original-Majority and Original-Observe individual choice. The omitted category is that of group decisions when unanimity is required for decisions, Original-Unanimous. The second and third equations include four additional demographic variables—the measure r of the person’s CRRA, the number of safe choices made in Table 9, an indicator variable for whether the respondent is female, and an indicator variable for people who gave inconsistent answers to the choices in Table 9.Footnote 13

Table 4 Regressions of individual investments in group decision contexts, original ordera

The results indicate a consistent significant influence of Original-Observe. Consider first the results for model 1 in Table 4. Individual investments in group situations are not significantly increased by higher levels of individual investments in the earlier stage. Investments in the group context are higher for the Original-Observe treatments than for the omitted category of unanimous choice, consistent with the risky shift predicted by Hypothesis 1. The effect for majority rule is positive, not as great as Original-Observe, and not statistically significant at the usual levels. However, that treatment involves both RTI and framing effects that may affect any risky shift influence of RTI.

Models 2 and 3 in Table 4 add demographic variables to the analysis. The earlier effects remain the same. Female participants, who some studies suggest may be more risk-averse,Footnote 14 make larger investments in the group context, but this difference is not statistically significant. There is no statistically significant effect of the measure of CRRA in model 2 and the alternative measure of risk aversion, the number of safe choices, which is included in model 3, so that there is no evidence in support of the risk aversion predicted by Hypothesis 5.Footnote 15

Since previous studies on probabilistic decisions have found that success or failure in a previous decision has an impact on future decisions (even when the probabilities themselves did not change), we add the interaction of the individual investment with an indicator for whether the person won the lottery in Part III in model 4, but this variable is also not statistically significant. The only significant effect for the average group investment results in Table 4 is Original-Observe. Simply observing the investment behavior of other subjects, while continuing to ask each person for a personal decision on how much to spend, causes subjects to increase their investment by about $0.70 in the first three models. This result is consistent with the raw data reported in Table 3. Before observing others, subjects were investing $1.82 in the endeavor. The $0.70 increase after observing others is about a 38% increase.

To examine whether the RTI effects have a lasting impact on subjects’ decisions, Table 5 reports the counterparts of the Table 4 models for the reversed order sample. The dependent variable is the individual’s investment in a final individual decision stage, while the explanatory variables include variables from the prior group decision stage. One difference from model 4 is that there is an indicator variable for whether the person’s group had a successful lottery outcome in the initial group decision.Footnote 16 Moreover, for the reversed order regressions in Table 5, the individual expenditure variables are not independent of one another, as they were chosen within a group information context. To account for this relationship, all reported standard errors for Table 5 are clustered based on the subject’s group. These are the only regression results in which there is this group interdependence among the explanatory variables. The absence of a statistically significant effect of the Reversed-Observe variable in the individual investment round indicates that the original order effect of Original-Observe is not reversed when people receive the group information in the initial round. There is a lasting informational effect of RTI, consistent with Hypothesis 4. This result is also reflected in the positive effect of the level of individual investment in the prior group situation on subsequent individual choices. Whereas individual investments did not affect investments in a group in Table 4, the investment made after observing others in the group does affect individual investments. It is interesting that after leaving the group context, female respondents exhibit a downward risk shift so that the results indicate more risk taking behavior by females in the group context than the individual context.Footnote 17

Table 5 Regressions of individual investments in individual decision contexts, reversed ordera

The decision patterns giving rise to these effects are shown in Table 6, which presents the fraction of respondents for each treatment who have a greater investment amount, the same investment amount, or a lower investment amount in the different group RTI situations compared to the individual choice without RTI. Majority rule, in which the median person is most influential, is the neutral context as about an even number of people raise or lower their investments in the group situation. For the original order results, more people raise their values in the majority rule situation, while for the reversed order results the distribution of changes is more even. Overall, 90% of the people in the majority rule groups change their values from when the decision was personal, even though there is no reason to change if others’ choices have no information value.

Table 6 Investment decision transitionsa

In contrast, if unanimous choice governs the group decision, the focal point becomes the lower bound of the individual investments. Once again there is no conventional economic rationale for people to alter their investment as they should continue to express their own preferences. Yet almost twice as many people reduce their investment amount as compared to the number who raise the amount; 75% of the subjects in unanimous rule choose lower or the same amounts voted individually. For the unanimous choice original order case, almost twice as many people reduce their investment as compared to the number that raise the investment, and there is also a much greater tendency to not change one’s decision compared to the frequency of change under majority rule.

The strongest differential effect is that for the Observe treatment. For the original order case, three-fourths of the respondents raise their investments, and only one-fifth lower their investments. For the full sample, 58% raise their investment level when they can observe what others do. On balance, observing others’ choices makes people willing to incur a greater investment in the litigation. This pattern reflects the strong herding effects in Hypothesis 1 and 3a, which are not offset by any framing effects that would arise if there were a group decision rule. Knowledge of the greater investments by others may make people more willing to engage in similar behavior than they would otherwise be doing individually. Increasing investment amounts displays a risky shift that on average takes respondents, who are generally risk-averse, to an investment level slightly beyond expected value maximization.

5.2 Ordered probit results

The determinants of whether individual investments increase, stay the same, or decline when placed in a group situation can be explored through the ordered probit results in Table 7. Model 1 includes the individual investment amount, Original-Majority, and Original-Observe; model 2 adds the demographic variables. Higher individual investments in the initial round in Part III make it more likely that the respondent will reduce the investment rather than increase the investment in the group treatments in Part IV. The effect of the variable on the direction in which investment levels change in the group context is positive for both majority rule and the simple observing treatment, where these effects are relative to the unanimity treatment. RTI alone without majority rule has a greater positive effect than unanimity, but the difference of RTI compared to the majority rule case is not statistically significant. Neither the measure of risk aversion nor the variable for female respondents is statistically significant. Inconsistent respondents display a negative effect.

Table 7 Ordered probit regression for whether individual investment in group context is higher or lower than individual investment for original ordera

The results thus far do not pertain to how one’s relative position within a group affects the influence of the group decision treatments. Original-Observe has no focal point and is purely informational. Original-Majority makes the median the focal point; and individuals tend to pull toward the median from both extremes due to the social norm role of the median. Original-Unanimous makes the lower bound the focal point. The rule creates power for the lowest contributor.

The ordered probit regressions in Table 8 address these within-group effects on the composition of the determinants of whether people increase, do not change, or decrease their individual investment in the group context. The focus of this analysis is somewhat different than in Table 7, in that we consider who within the group is altering their behavior. Here we create dummy variables for whether the person’s individual investment in the individual choice case in Part III is in the top two investments or the bottom two investments in their group of six individuals. The omitted dummy variable category consists of the individuals who rank third and fourth in the level of their individual investments. Relative to this median group, how do individuals alter their investment amount in each of the three situations?

Table 8 Ordered probit regression for effect of relative position on whether group investment is higher or lower relative to median respondents for original ordera

The regressions in Table 8 address this question after breaking up the sample into the three pertinent group decision subsamples—whether the respondent was in the Original-Observe group, the Original-Majority group, and the Original-Unanimous group. Within the Original-Observe group, the bottom two investments rise after observing RTI. The provision of RTI creates a positive risky shift on the part of the participants with lowest rates of investment.

The existence of significant effects at the extremes for majority rule is consistent with the median focal point nature of majority rule. The top investment group decreases their investment, while those at the bottom raise their investment. This pattern indicates a convergence of the valuations toward the median within the majority rule treatment, where the change is exhibited at both extremes. This result is consistent with Hypothesis 3b.

For the unanimous choice rule, there is an asymmetric effect relative to the median, which is consistent with the unanimous choice rule’s focus on only the extreme lower end of the investment distribution and with Hypothesis 3c. The bottom two individual investments, which will be instrumental in driving the group decision, rise relative to the median within this group as these individuals apparently attempt to accommodate the preferences of the group by raising their valuations in the group context. However, the extent of the upward movement is far less than for either Original-Majority or Original-Observe, which are significantly larger than the Original-Reversed effect at the 1% level. Thus, the additional unanimous choice component leads the subjects with the bottom investment levels to display less upward flexibility than either the RTI or majority rule case. Information alone without the unanimity group decision rule creates more upward movement on the part of the low end investors than in the unanimity group decision context, so the presence of the low bid framing effect for unanimity has a marginal effect that lowers rather than raises the bottom bid.

6 Conclusion

In a standard simple economic model of group decisions, individual preference structures carry over to the group context.Footnote 18 Our work shows that group investment decisions are driven by individual preferences that are not the same as when people make individual choices in isolation. We believe the root cause of the shift is that people are undecided about the expected utility-maximizing choice when risky investment decisions must be made at a personal level.

Information about others’ choices has very strong effects. Even when people have full, accurate knowledge of the payoffs and the probabilities, observing others’ choices creates a risky shift. Unlike models of herding and information cascades, in our experiments people have full knowledge of both the probabilities and the payoffs. Moreover, unlike other studies of risky shifts in group contexts, there is no personal interaction within the group, only exchanges of real-time information. Observing others’ decisions with real-time information may enable people to make better decisions if their initial private choices are derived from noisy preferences in a complex decision environment where it is difficult to ascertain the expected utility-maximizing choice.

A second set of factors that alter individual choices stems from the group decision rule itself. How the decision rule is framed alters the individual choices people make even when their change in preferences will not alter the group decision in the majority rule and unanimity situations considered. The anchoring effect of focusing on the median group member for majority rule or the member with the lowest valuation for unanimity may influence social norms in a manner that alters individual choices when placed in a group context. The degree of accommodation of other group members’ preferences is greater for majority rule than for unanimous choice. These effects may become even more pronounced when there is greater personal interaction that goes beyond observing others’ decisions on a computer screen.Footnote 19

Movement from individual decisions to a group decision context often creates many economic ramifications, including strategic behavior and related game-theoretic effects. However, even apart from such influences, there are quite fundamental changes in individual choice behavior in terms of the information affecting decisions, how people use the information available in group contexts to make decisions when preferences are noisy, and how the group decision rule frames decisions in a manner that alters subsequent behavior. These alterations can have lasting effects on an individual’s subsequent decisions.