1 Introduction

In Better Never to Have Been, David Benatar defends anti-natalism—the view that it is wrong to reproduce.Footnote 1 By bringing a child into the world, we cause it serious harm. Given the way the world is, every child will inevitably suffer a great deal. According to the most plausible accounts of what makes a life worth living, life is typically on balance bad.Footnote 2 Most important, suffering is entirely preventable; we merely need to abstain from procreation. The anti-natalist says that we should do just that. But, one worries, the anti-natalist prevents suffering at the cost of the goods of life. Surely we must weigh the goods against the bads. How could it be wrong to bring a reasonably happy person into existence?

Benatar presents two independent arguments for anti-natalism.Footnote 3 The first argument attempts to show that it is always prudentially bad to be brought into existence. This argument depends on a controversial asymmetry between goods and bads: The absence of pain is good, whereas the absence of pleasure is neither prudentially good nor bad for the non-existent. The prudential asymmetry grounds the anti-natalist moral claim. Accordingly, I will refer to this as the asymmetry argument.Footnote 4 The second argument does not depend on the asymmetry. Instead, it defends a wholesale pessimism about the human condition. We can call this the argument from pessimism.Footnote 5 I argue that neither argument is successful. Both arguments mistakenly assume that less good is bad. And an important underlying problem troubles both: Benatar does not provide an acceptable way to determine whether a life is worth living. I defend a novel, better way that avoids the anti-natalist conclusion.

My argument proceeds in a few steps. I begin with a presentation of Benatar’s asymmetry argument. Although I do not accept the asymmetry, I show that Benatar’s argument is unsuccessful either way. We do not wrong the one we bring into existence if she lives a life worth living (LWL)—a life that is high in various objective goods.Footnote 6 However, we should not bring anyone into existence who will live a life worth avoiding (LWA).Footnote 7 These are lives replete with objective bads and poor in objective goods. Happily, not all lives are like this. Benatar anticipates this style of objection and develops a reply in the argument from pessimism. I argue that his reply to objective list modes of evaluating lives is unsuccessful. To be worth living a life need not be the best that we can conceive; it merely needs to be preferable to non-existence.

2 Benatar’s Asymmetry Argument

Benatar argues that it is wrong to bring someone into existence if they will suffer. He thinks that if someone will suffer even the tiniest pinprick, it is prudentially bad for them to be brought into existence, no matter if the rest of their life was spent in ecstasy.Footnote 8 Hence, given the facts of human life, it is always prudentially bad to be brought into existence.Footnote 9

Benatar arrives at this counter-intuitive conclusion through a short series of controversial premises. The most controversial is the good and bad asymmetry claim. It seems clear that pleasure is good and pain is bad. And, on first blush, we might think that the absence of pain and pleasure are both neutral. If you lack both, then you are in a neutral state. Benatar disagrees. He argues that the absence of pain is good. It is good for someone to avoid a painful toothache. But unlike the goodness of the absence of pain, the absence of pleasure is neither good nor bad, at least for the non-existent; hence, the asymmetry.

It is important to be precise about the kind of good and bad at issue. One might think that preventing bad is morally more important than the mere promotion of good, that there is a moral asymmetry. The moral asymmetry is plausible.Footnote 10 In fact Benatar thinks that it is probably true.Footnote 11 But the moral asymmetry does not capture the kind of badness at issue. Instead of a moral asymmetry, he thinks that the absence of pain is good for the one who does not feel the pain: “this absence is good when judged in terms of the interests of the person who would have otherwise existed,” whereas the absence of pleasure (for the non-existent) is simply not bad.Footnote 12 That is, he seems to think of the asymmetry is in terms of the welfare impact of the absence of pleasure and pain. Hence, the kind of good and bad at issue is prudential.Footnote 13 The prudential asymmetry grounds the anti-natalist moral claim.

Benatar thinks that the anti-natalist conclusion follows quickly from the asymmetry if we understand another important detail. He claims that the “absence of good things, such as pleasure, is bad only if there is somebody who is deprived of these good things.”Footnote 14 For instance, although it might be bad for someone to fall into a coma for 5 years, it is not bad for someone who is never born to miss out on the joys of life.Footnote 15 It is not bad precisely because there is no one to be deprived. The absence of good for the non-existent is neither bad nor good, but the absence of bad is good.Footnote 16 The person who would have existed is benefited by the absence of the bads of life and is unaffected by the absence of the goods.Footnote 17

To summarize, the asymmetry involves two independent claims: (1) the absence of bad is prudentially good for the non-existent person who would have lived, and (2) the absence of good is neither prudentially good nor bad for the non-existent person who would have lived.Footnote 18 It appears that the first claim also applies to those who exist. The second does not.

Putting the two parts of the asymmetry together, Benatar concludes that it is always prudentially bad to be brought into existence: “coming into existence, far from constituting a net benefit, always constitutes a net harm.”Footnote 19 If the choice is between bringing someone into existence and not bringing her into existence, we should always choose the latter. No human lives are worth starting. Benatar argues that the asymmetry shows why. Compare existence with non-existenceFootnote 20:

Benatar thinks that the asymmetry tells us that when evaluating scenario A, we should consider both the good and the bad (quadrants 1 and 2). But when evaluating scenario B, we should only count the prudential good that is the absence of pain (quadrant 3). We should ignore the absence of pleasure (quadrant 4).Footnote 21 Benatar thinks that the calculation will always prefer scenario B as long as there is the tiniest bit of pain to be had from existing.Footnote 22 Hence, anti-natalism follows from the asymmetry.

There is much to take issue with here. I think that both parts of the asymmetry are wrong, but I will not pursue this line of objection.Footnote 23 In the next section, I argue that Benatar draws the wrong conclusion from the asymmetry. His calculation is mistaken. The asymmetry does not support anti-natalism.

3 Comparing Lives

Even if we grant Benatar his most controversial premise—the asymmetry between the absence of good and bad—his anti-natalist conclusion lacks support. Benatar miscalculates according to the most plausible version of his own schema. If we assume that the absence of bad is good for those who would have existed, it still might be far better to exist.

It will help to get a bit more precise. To be concrete, I will assume that we can talk about commensurable units of prudential bad and good.Footnote 24 Consider the life of X. It has 10 units of bad and 30 units of good. If you think that the order in which the goods arrive in the narrative of a life is important, make any necessary adjustments: arrange more of the goods near the end.Footnote 25 The net good of X’s life is 20. Now, we should ask, would it be better for X never to have been, as Benatar suggests? Does “coming into existence, far from constituting a net benefit, always constitute a net harm”?

In order to perform the calculation, we need to know how good the absence of bad is. For the sake of argument, assume that it is of equal positive value. Accordingly, the absence of 10 units of bad would be worth 10 units of good. Hence, the scenarios look like this:

Scenario B is worth a mere 10 units of prudential good, whereas Scenario A is worth a net 20. According to the prudential calculation that Benatar suggests—a calculation performed while assuming the good and bad asymmetry—Scenario A is better for X. It is twice as prudentially valuable. Hence, it is fair to say that there is no (net) harm done in bringing X into existence. Benatar draws the wrong conclusion. Although never being born might always constitute a net benefit, it is not the case that coming into existence is always a net harm.

A formalization of Benatar’s argument will help expose the error. Here is the core argument:

  1. (1)

    The absence of bad is prudentially good for the non-existent person who would have lived.

  2. (2)

    The absence of good is neither prudentially good nor bad for the non-existent person who would have lived.

  3. (3)

    Hence, “coming into existence, far from constituting a net benefit, always constitutes a net harm.”

The flaw should be apparent. The conclusion does not follow. Rather than (3), Benatar should have concluded:

  1. (3′)

    Hence, not coming into existence always constitutes a net benefit for the non-existent person who would have lived.

But this conclusion does not get us anti-natalism, not even close. It does not tell us that coming into existence is always better than not existing. It simply tells us that not coming into existence is always a net good. This does not mean that coming into existence could not be better, that the net good could not be greater. To the contrary, it most certainly can.

Benatar anticipates something much like this objection: Footnote 26

Now some people might accept the asymmetry represented [. . .], agree that we need to compare Scenario A with Scenario B, but deny that this leads to the conclusion that B is always a harm. The argument is that we must assign positive or negative (or neutral) values to each of the quadrants, and that if we assign them in what those advancing this view take to be the most reasonable way, we find that coming into existence is sometimes preferable. [. . .] Doing this, we find that A is preferable to B where (2) is more than twice the value of (1).Footnote 27

In reply, he says that there are numerous problems with the objection, but he only refers to two quick issues.Footnote 28 Neither adequately addresses the problem. I will start with the second, an analogy.

3.1 The Analogical Reply

Benatar argues that favoring existence over non-existence, as I did above, is much like saying that it is better to be sick and have the capacity for quick recovery than it is to never to get sick.Footnote 29 But, of course, it is better not to get sick. It does not matter if the person who never gets sick lacks the capacity for quick recovery. It is still better to never get sick.

In this analogy, never existing is compared to never getting sick (Scenario B). Conversely, existing with a net good life is supposed to be akin to getting sick and having a capacity to recover quickly (Scenario A). Benatar argues that the kind of reasoning that led to the conclusion that it is better to exist, would also suggest that it is better to get sick if one would have the capacity to recover quickly. Clearly this is not the case. So, the reply concludes, we should reject this mode of reasoning.

But what other mode do we have? How should we do the comparison? And, as Benatar notes, it is a comparison that we are after: “We are comparing possible worlds—one in which a person exists and one in which he does not.”Footnote 30 The problem is that no other candidate for how to run the comparison on the table. Surely we should not ignore the goods of life when assessing whether it would be better to be than not be. Surely the good matters when trying to determine whether a life is worth starting.

The problem is not in the reasoning behind my objection, but in Benatar’s analogy. Having the capacity to recover quickly is not analogous to the goods of life. The capacity to recover quickly is merely instrumentally prudentially good. It is good merely because it allows us to regain health and enjoy life, both of which are intrinsically good.Footnote 31 Hence, the sickness example does not contain any intrinsic prudential good in the equivalent of quadrant 2—the quadrant where the goods of life appear in the objection. There is nothing in quadrant 2 worth having that makes up for the bads of quadrant 1. This is not the case with existence. Therefore, the analogy is inapt. Benatar’s reply does not meet the objection.

Benatar recognizes this problem and defends the analogy in an obscure paragraph. He argues that if the analogy had used an intrinsic good, then one might think its absence in quadrant #4 would be a deprivation. This would bias the analogy. So, he is forced to use an instrumental good—the capacity to recover quickly. Remember, he is trying to come up with a case where there is no bad in quadrant #4. The asymmetry tells us that the absence of pleasure is not bad for the non-existent. However, a deprivation would be bad. So, quadrant #4 cannot include a deprivation. Instead, the analogy needs the mere absence of a deprivation. He argues that there is no way to indicate an absence of a deprivation for a living person except by using instrumental goods. Again, the worry is that absence of an intrinsic good for an existing person is a deprivation. But the absence of a deprivation is not. The lack of the capacity to recover works because it is a mere absence of a deprivation. That is why he uses it in the analogy. Since this avoids the potential problem of using an intrinsic good, he thinks that the analogy is fair.Footnote 32

Benatar’s defense of the analogy is not convincing. The chief problem is that the absence of a defect does not make an analogy apt. The analogy is most certainly inapt. There is no way around that. Just because it does not have additional flaws does not mean that it does not have others. Further, the motivation for the use of instrumental goods is questionable. The absence of a good is not always, perhaps not even typically, a deprivation, if by “deprivation” we mean bad. The absence of a good is not always bad; sometimes it is just less good.

Consider an analogy: Lucky has a mild headache, but finds a good deal of cash on the way home. Not-So-Lucky does not have a headache, but he does not find a pile of cash on the way home. Who is better off? It is not entirely clear. If the pile of cash is big enough, then it sure seems that Lucky is better off, despite the headache. If not, then Not-So-Lucky looks to be better off. This does not provide support for Benatar’s claim, but it is not for the reasons he mentions. There is no worry here that the absence of the cash is bad for Not-So-Lucky. No, it is just not as good. It is akin to the absence of pleasure for the non-existent. It is “not bad, but not good either.”Footnote 33 Hence, the analogy tracks the asymmetry and avoids the problems Benatar was trying to side-step, but it does not support anti-natalism. It takes a false analogy to do that.

The problems with Benatar’s analogy are not confined to worries about intrinsic and instrumental goods. There is a more significant defect. The value of the capacity to recover quickly is exhausted by the amount of health that it saves. Someone who never gets sick will have more health than someone who does, other things being equal. Hence, in lives of equal length, column A could never have more goods than B. The problem is that when we compare existence with non-existence, there is no reason to think that the situation is the same as it is between Sickly and Healthy. Sickly can never have more of the relevant good than can Healthy. But there can be more net good on the existence side than the non-existence side of the original chart. Since the Sickly vs. Healthy analogy does not allow for this, the analogy is false. It fails to properly model the comparison between existence and non-existence. This gives us an additional reason to reject Benatar’s reply.

3.2 The Underlying Problem

We can put aside the analogy. In reply to Skott Brill’s criticisms of the Sick vs. Healthy analogy, Benatar argues that the failure of the analogy would not show that the asymmetry is a failure.Footnote 34 But that’s not what’s at issue. What’s at issue is how we should assign values to the diagram given the asymmetry. Benatar seems to suggest that the asymmetry requires that we black out the pleasure in quadrant 2 and just compare the boxes in the top row—the pain and the absence of pain: “One does not need the analogy to show that absent pleasures in the never existing [quadrant 4] should not be assigned the value of zero.”Footnote 35 If we followed his lead, this would indeed get Benatar an anti-natalist result, but the asymmetry does not support such a move.

Benatar thinks that the asymmetry has the implication that quadrant 4 could never be less good than quadrant 3. This is because he thinks that existence is not a “real advantage.”Footnote 36 He thinks that a “real advantage” is an advantage that it would be bad to lack. The line reasoning seems to be as follows:

  1. (1)

    According to the asymmetry thesis, it is not bad for the non-existent to lack the goods of life.

  2. (2)

    For good G to be a real advantage for subject S, S’s lack of G must be bad for S.

  3. (3)

    If it is not bad for the non-existent to lack the goods of life, then the goods of life do not constitute a real advantage for the existent.

  4. (4)

    Hence, the goods of life do not constitute a real advantage for the existent.

If what it is for something to be better is for it to constitute a real advantage, then the goods of life would not be better than their absence for the non-existent. It would follow that the goods of quadrant 3 are not relatively better than their absence in quadrant 4.Footnote 37 Hence, it wouldn’t ever be better to have been.

The above formalization reveals that anti-natalism is not supported by the asymmetry alone; Benatar also requires a dubious notion of what constitutes an advantage. But I see no reason to adopt this notion of real, or genuine, advantages. There are real advantages that it would just be less good to lack. It is not bad for me that I didn’t find Aladdin’s lamp on the way home from the grocery store today; no, it is just less good. Nor is it bad for me that I was born without the powers of Superman, though it would surely be an advantage to be able to fly like a bird and leap over tall buildings in a single bound.Footnote 38 My life would be better for me with super-powers, but it is not bad for me that I am not Superman. Hence, if we reject Benatar’s claim about what constitutes a real advantage, then we have no reason to think that existence isn’t sometimes better than—a real advantage over—non-existence.

Here is another way to think about the problem: The absence of pleasure might not be bad for the non-existent. Sure. This is what the asymmetry says. But this does not mean that the presence of pleasure is not good for the existent. Of course the goods of life are good. Benatar argues that “for the good to be an advantage over non-existence, it would have to have been the case that its absence were bad.”Footnote 39 But, again, this is simply not so. Benatar is wrong. This is key: A good can be better than something that is not bad. Lots of a good is better than just a little. And a little good is better than no good at all. But less good is not bad. Confusing the two leads Benatar to incorrectly conclude that the asymmetry has larger implications than it actually does.

There are two issues here: (1) Is it bad for the non-existent to not get the goods of life? And, (2) is it better to get some goods rather than no goods? I agree that we might want to say that the absence of pleasure is not bad for the non-existent.Footnote 40 Perhaps, as Benatar suggests it has no intrinsic value—“it is intrinsically value neutral.”Footnote 41 But something that is not bad can still be less good than an alternative.Footnote 42 In the case of a life of pronounced net good, it is less good to not exist, but it is not bad.Footnote 43 That’s all the asymmetry implies. Hence, even if we accept the asymmetry, the anti-natalist conclusion does not follow. Consider a life of pronounced net good: “When we compare two possible worlds and we judge the matter in terms of the interests of the person who exists in one but not in the other of these worlds, we judge the world in which he does [. . .] exist to be better.”Footnote 44

It might be that it is never bad to not be brought into existence. It might always be a net good for the non-existent. It also might be the case that it is sometimes bad to be brought into existence. But none of this implies that that it is never better to have been. The asymmetry gives us no reason to think otherwise.

. . .

In the next section, I will provide additional defense of this mode of comparison. But it will help to respond to his first reply as well. His first reply to my objection raises an important insight about lives worth living. Although some lives might enjoy a net balance of pleasure, they still might not be worth living. At certain levels, pains can be so intense as to make a life not worth living.Footnote 45 If so, simply subtracting the prudential good from the bad will not tell us whether a life is worth starting. Indeed, I think this is probably the case, but it does not provide much defense for the asymmetry argument. It only shows that this style of calculation can go wrong, not that it does in nearly all cases. For that, Benatar would have to show that nearly all human lives exceed the pain threshold. As we will see, the argument from pessimism does not get us nearly that pessimistic of a conclusion.Footnote 46 But it does present a serious reply to my objection. To see why, I first need to a bit more about what I think makes a life worth living.

In the next section I paint a general theory for evaluating the worth of a life.

4 A Life Worth Living

The question, “Would it be better never to have been?” is ambiguous. The ambiguity concerns the kind of better at issue. There are many kinds. For instance, we might ask the question in terms of prudential value: Is it better for the one who will live to be born or not? The phrase “good for” identifies this as a question about welfare. But this is not the only question we can ask. In fact, I think that it is not the most important question.Footnote 47

Alternatively, we might ask whether it is all things considered better for a person to have been born. Here we are not so much concerned with whether the life was good for the one who lives it, but whether it was valuable in the wider scheme of things: Was the life causally responsible for more good than bad? We might say that this is a question about the significance of the life. More controversially, we might even say that this is a question about the meaningfulness of the life.Footnote 48

Once again, I am not sure this is exactly the question we should be asking. I think Benatar is right to suggest that what we want to know is whether a life is worth starting. That is, we want to know if the life is worthwhile, if it is worth living. Although related, this is not the same question as whether the life is meaningful.Footnote 49 Nor is it the same question as whether it is sufficiently high in welfare. Here is where I differ with Benatar.Footnote 50 Perhaps the two questions will have the same answer, but most likely worth is not strictly a matter of welfare.

Just as some things that do not promote our self-interest are nevertheless worth doing, some lives low in welfare appear to be worth living. When we wonder whether some activity is worth doing, our only thought isn’t “What’s in it for me?” Intuitively, the same should hold for lives. Conversely, some lives high in welfare are not worth living. Most plausibly, a supremely happy Hitler does not live a life worth living. It would be highly counter-intuitive to suggest otherwise. More needs to be said, but these considerations suggest that worth and welfare are distinct.

One can live a life of great hardship and suffering—one low on most theories of welfare—that might nevertheless be worth living. Conversely, one can live a life high in prudential value that is not worth living. The same goes for a meaningful life. What we are after is a concept larger than either welfare or meaning.Footnote 51 We want to know what makes a life worth living.Footnote 52

It is out of scope to defend a fully fleshed out theory here. I can only provide a sketch. As a tool to theory development, I suggest a rough test to help track the general extension of the concept of a life worth living. As we shall see, the test cannot serve as an analysis, but it narrows in on the notion.

Here’s the test: a life worth living (LWL) is a life that a benevolent caretaker, given a synoptic preview, would allow someone to live rather than to never have been.Footnote 53 Imagine that the caretaker is a sympathetic judge who wants everyone to live a life they should not resent given all the facts. This suggestion comes from Bernard Williams: “I see no way of denying that one who resents his own existence prefers that he should not have existed; and no way of interpreting that preference except in terms of thinking that one’s life is not worth living.”Footnote 54

This is a pre-existence test (PET) for the worth of a life.Footnote 55 This is not the same question as whether one would choose to live one’s life over again.Footnote 56 One can coherently decide not to live a life over again that one should choose to start. At the end of life we have excellent reasons not to repeat ourselves, reasons that we do not have prior to existing.

I offer this test for inclusion in the history of other failed, but instructive tests for related concepts. Feldman proposes a “crib test” for isolating the concept of welfare: Imagine looking down at your infant child in its crib.Footnote 57 Think of all the things that you want for the child: close friends, a good education, an interesting career, etc. These are things that contribute to the child’s welfare.Footnote 58 The crib test is designed to hone in on welfare considerations. But it does not do so cleanly. An insane parent might have strange desires for her child. She might want him to become the first person to consume an entire helicopter by grinding it up and eating it bit by bit.Footnote 59 Or a religious fanatic might want her child to become a martyr for the faith. But these desires are not for the welfare of the child.

The problems for the crib test are not confined to the desires of insane and fanatical parents. Most people, apart from gangsters and other psychopaths, prefer that their children be decent people, even if virtue does not always make them better off prudentially.Footnote 60 Hence, it appears that the crib test does a better job at tracking the sane, moral parent’s conception of what makes a life all-things-considered good than it does at tracking what is merely good for their child.

The pre-crib test is designed to explicitly incorporate broader considerations, such as concerns about meaning. Many think that meaning is best evaluated from a synoptic first-person perspective—the deathbed.Footnote 61 Imagine lying on your deathbed thinking about all the things you wish you had done. Such thoughts likely concern meaning. For instance, you might wish that you had taken a rare chance to do something big, rather than chosen the safe, comfortable option. The deathbed test is a useful tool for tracking concerns about meaning, but it, too, suffers from over-inclusiveness. In the moments before death, just as one might regret a dearth of accomplishments, one might also regret not having had enough fun. Perhaps, once again, the deathbed test better tracks what makes a life all-things-considered good than it does at tracking meaning alone.

I suspect that the crib test and the deathbed test both help us identity what we think makes a life worth living. But neither is wholly adequate to the task. The pre-existence test fares better. PET is designed to incorporate concerns about both welfare and significance. It differs from the others in who makes the evaluation. PET is superior to the crib test and the deathbed test because it avoids the troublesome relativity of both. A selfish parent wants the wrong things for her child. And an evil person on his deathbed might regret not causing enough pointless suffering. In contrast, the ideal evaluator in the pre-crib test suffers no such defects.

It is important to note that, unlike Saul Smilansky, I am not speaking of subjective preferences, but of whether the life is objectively worth living.Footnote 62 This does not mean that the pre-existence test excludes the subjective experience or the felt satisfaction of the one living the life. Most plausibly, these are factored into the overall welfare value. And certainly the welfare value of a life is an important factor to consider when determining whether it is worth living. Once again, the question is not whether given your preferences would you choose to be born, but rather, would, perhaps, a benevolent caretaker who knows all the facts of your future existence allow you to be born.Footnote 63

As a criterion for what makes a life worth living, the pre-existence test has come under some criticism.Footnote 64 Smilansky argues that one might think that one’s life is worthwhile, but also think that it would have been better not to have been born, or vice versa. One might think this for a variety of reasons. For instance, severe self-loathing might make one wish to have never been born, but one might still live a life worth living. Alternatively, an intense episode of pain might make one’s life not worth starting, but not make it not worth living.

I cannot deal with all of Smilansky’s objections here, but I do not think any of them are compelling. Consider a self-loathing person, the otherwise happy child-molester: Why should we think that the happy-child molester lives a life worth living? Is it because he is happy? Why would that be sufficient? Most plausibly, a life that significantly advances horrendous evil is not worth living. Hitler, Pol Pot, and Stalin lived worthless lives. It does not matter if they were all blissfully happy. Moral repugnance is sufficient to sap a life of positive worth.Footnote 65 And the happy child-molester lives a morally repugnant life, at least in one regard.

Or, consider Smilansky’s other example, that of the cancer survivor who finds her life worth living, but thinks that an intense bought of suffering in the past makes it such that it would have been better if she were never born. This objection fails as well. It confuses two distinct questions. The confusion is between: (1) a life worth starting and (2) a life worth continuing. Benatar helpfully suggests that the term “a life worth living” is ambiguous. It might mean either. What we are concerned with is whether life is worth starting, not whether it is worth continuing.

I propose that the best way to understand the difference is to see it at as one of duration. A life worth continuing is one where the period ahead is worth living.Footnote 66 A life worth starting is one where the entire life is worth living. When I refer to “a life worth living,” I have in mind the entire life. Smilansky’s cancer survivor’s life is worth continuing, since the period ahead is worth living, nevertheless, the life might not be worth starting. Given the choice, if the suffering were as bad as we are asked to imagine, then perhaps the life as a whole is not worth living. There is no problem for the pre-existence test here.

A more pressing problem for the pre-existence test is that it has trouble with border-line cases. Putting Benatar’s worries aside for the moment, there are clear cases of lives worth living. They are high in various objective goods, such as friendship, love, knowledge, pleasure, meaning, and moral worth. Informed of all the facts of such a life, a benevolent caretaker would surely allow someone to live such a life. Conversely, some lives are clearly not worth living.Footnote 67 A life that significantly advances horrendous evil is not worth living. Again, it is not controversial to say that Hitler, Pol Pot, and Stalin lived worthless lives. Likewise, lives spent in persistent, incapacitating agony are not worth living. As these examples indicate, there are clear cases of lives not worth living, and there are clear cases of lives worth living.

The problem is that there are not so clear cases. Worth comes in degrees. Lives entirely consumed by meaningless activities, such as collecting rubber bands or making handwritten copies of War and Peace, appear to be less worth living than those spent in pursuit of valuable ends.Footnote 68 They appear to be wasted.Footnote 69 But are they not worth living? It is hard to say. In addition to the problems that one encounters when trying to weigh various kinds of goods and bads, there appears to be a grey zone. Yeates proposes that between the thresholds of lives worth living (LWL) and lives worth avoiding (LWA), there are lives worth nothing (LWN).Footnote 70 Although I am not sure that this is the best term for the category, since these lives might have some worth, his suggestion that there is a middle category seems plausible. We can refer to these as “lives worth neither” (LWN).

Assuming that there is a middle category, the question is this: Should a benevolent caretaker prevent one from living a LWN? It is not clear. But the test forces a decision. If the caretaker does not consent, then we are certainly not in life worth living territory. However, we also might not be faced with a full fledged life worth avoiding. But then why should the caretaker prevent it? The problem is that the test is binary, but threshold concepts are not. This problem is not insurmountable. A plausible solution is to say that LWN’s are simply those where the balance of reasons favors neither.

There is no need to explore this issue further here. Since the pre-existence test is not an analysis of the concept of a life-worth living, the objection does not cast doubt on its usefulness in helping us track the general extension of the term. For present purposes, what matters is what makes a life worth living. The question is: What should ground the decision of the benevolent caretakers?

I have already put a suggestion on the table. Although flawed, the pre-existence test is useful for showing the virtues of my suggestion. I propose that lives worth living are those high in various objective goods and low in objective bads. A life worth avoiding is the opposite: it is one high in bads and low in goods.Footnote 71 I claim no originality in the list of goods, but for the sake of simplicity, we can think of them as involving two main categories, those of welfare and meaning.Footnote 72 The theory I offer is an objective list theory (OLT) of what makes a life worth living.Footnote 73 Its principle virtue is that it helps capture the importance of a wide swath of concerns that do not clearly impact one’s welfare. For instance, it seems that I can self-sacrificially pursue ends that do not make me better off prudentially, but nevertheless enhance the worth of my life.

So far, I have painted only a hazy picture of what makes a life worth living. I have left much unspecified. Other than reply to a few concerns about the pre-existence test, I have not offered much in the way of argument for this view, nor do I intend to here. It would take at least another paper to develop the view in detail. Here, I simply propose that the theory; the distinctions between LWL, LWA, and LWN; and the pre-existence test are useful conceptual machinery to be defended in more detail elsewhere. If you do not accept the proposed distinction between welfare and worth, simply see my theory as an objective list theory of prudential value. The implications for Benatar’s position are roughly the same.

Regardless of whether we should distinguish between welfare and worth as I suggest, in order to determine whether we have wronged someone by bringing them into existing according to objective list style of assessment, we should look to the objective goods of that life. Consider a LWL: If you have brought someone into existence who lives a life worth living, it defies credibility to suggest that you have wronged that person.Footnote 74 How could it be wrong to bring someone into existence who lives a life high in net objective good?Footnote 75 However, if you bring someone into existence who lives a life worth avoiding, then matters are far different. These are the lives that we should avoid causing. Happily, many lives are not LWA’s. Accordingly, anti-natalism is implausible.

5 Benatar’s Argument from Pessimism

Benatar anticipates this style of objection. His second argument for anti-natalism—the argument from pessimism—concludes that all human lives are LWA’s. Even if we do not accept the argument from asymmetry, he argues that we have good reason to think that everyone is overall wronged by being brought into existence. Benatar’s second argument has two main parts. The first part is intended to explain away our general optimism about the value of our lives. I will not consider this part of the argument.

The second part is where the real work is done. Benatar argues that according to the most plausible theories of what makes a life good for the one who lives it—hedonism, preferentism, and objective list accounts—human life is bad, very bad. I will only consider in depth Benatar’s arguments against objective list style evaluations. Although hedonism and preferentism are plausible theories of what makes a life good for the one who lives it (i.e. welfare), they are not plausible theories of what makes a life worth living. Both imply that a happy Hitler (or a Hitler who had more desires satisfied than frustrated) lives a life worth living. This disqualifies both as theories of worth.

Since the hedonic value of a life is one of the objective goods that count according to the OLT, it will pay to raise a brief worry for his hedonic pessimism. Following Schopenhauer, the putative undesirableness of desiring plays a central role in Benatar’s pessimism. It seems that we are more often than not in a state of desiring. Our lives are on balance bad in this regard, since desiring is bad state to be in. But there is good reason to think that this argument rests on a false generalization about the undesirableness of desiring.Footnote 76 If the pain of desire were so bad, we should be willing to eat a meal that would forever satiate our hunger, drink a libation that would forever quench our thirst, or take a pill that would do away with our libido. But we refuse. These are curses, not cures.Footnote 77 It appears that desiring is not as undesirable as Benatar and Schopenhauer make out.

I will put the issue aside. Although the hedonic value of a life is a likely component of the objective worth of the life, it is not decisive. We can concede Benatar’s pessimistic hedonic calculus and still deny his rejection of objective list optimism.

As I noted in the previous section, I see no reason to deny that many human lives are high in the objective goods that make a life worth living. However, Benatar argues that our lives are poor on an objective list theory. If Benatar is right, this would be a significant problem for my optimistic conclusion. Benatar begins by looking at the criteria by which items get to be included on the objective list. He thinks that the items on the list are not necessarily good from the perspective of eternity, but merely good compared to other human lives:

They are taken to be objective only in the sense that they do not vary from person to person. They are not taken to be objective in the sense of judging what a good life is sub specie aeternitatis. Constructing lists sub specie humanitatis would be reasonable if one wanted to determine how well a particular life goes in comparison with other (human) lives. But knowing how well a particular life goes in comparison with other lives tells us very little about the baseline—how good human life is.Footnote 78

The complaint seems to be that the objective list style assessment includes goods that are only valuable in comparison to other human lives. But if we thought about what was genuinely, non-comparatively good, we would see that these lowly human goods are not worth having. We should set our sights higher.

It is more appropriate to assess human lives sub specie aeternitatis. That is just the case when we wish to determine how good human life in general is. The quality of human life is then found wanting.Footnote 79

Benatar offers some evidence in support of the claim that we are indeed evaluating human lives from the perspective of humanity. We find it tragic if someone dies at 40, but we do not think it is a misfortune that we do not live a few hundred years. He notes that “we do not take that which is beyond our reach as something that would be a crucial good.”Footnote 80 This suggests that we are using the normal human life span as the basis of comparison. But if we really want to know how good human life is, if we want to know whether human lives are worth living, we need to consider them from the perspective of the universe.

Considered from the perspective of the universe, we find that the core goods on the objective list are meager at best. Consider meaning: Benatar echoes Richard Taylor, saying:

Conscious life, although but a blip on the radar of cosmic time, is laden with suffering—suffering that is directed to no end other than its own perpetuation. [. . .] From the perspective of the universe, the lives of both the philanthropist and the grass-counter are meaningless.Footnote 81

When we assess human life from the outside, we will find that our lives are meaningless. Curing cancer is no more objectively meaningful than eating excrement, since the ultimate outcome of both is the same: The ultimate outcome is a cold, lifeless entropic universe. Bertrand Russell puts it succinctly:

all the labors of the ages, all the devotion, all the inspiration, all the noonday brightness of human genius, are destined to extinction in the vast death of the solar system, and [. . .] the whole temple of man’s achievement must inevitably be buried beneath the debris of a universe in ruins.Footnote 82

The argument against meaning appears to be this: The final outcome of all human actions is worthless. And nothing can be meaningful if the ultimate outcome is worthless. Hence, no human activities are any more meaningful than any others.

There is much to take issue with here. Each move in Benatar’s argument from pessimism contains errors in reasoning. I will move backwards, beginning with his skepticism about the possibility of meaningful human lives. Benatar rejects subjectivist theories of the meaning of life. Subjectivist theories hold that the meaning one’s life is constituted by one’s reactions. Typically, subjectivists hold that meaning is strictly a matter of fulfillment. Benatar thinks that the available alternatives to subjectivism all imply that life is objectively meaningless. It is objectively meaningless because it leads to nothing. This is a familiar argument. Wielenberg calls it the “Final Outcome Argument.” Footnote 83 The problem is that the final outcome argument is not sound.

Benatar, Taylor, and Russell give us good reason to think that the meaning of life cannot come from enduring accomplishments, since nothing we do will endure for long at all. But this does not give us any reason to think that all projects are of equal worth. Why would it? The argument contains a false premise. There is no reason to think that the value of an activity is entirely determined by its ultimate outcome. Certainly there is value in making someone laugh, even if they do not laugh forever. Surely there is value in providing a hot meal for the hungry, even if they are not satiated for all eternity. And surely it is good to cure cancer, even if humanity does not endure until the end of time. Something need not be permanent in order to be valuable while it exists. As Paul Edwards notes, to think otherwise is to exhibit an irrational, arbitrary preference for the distant future.Footnote 84 If we recognize that there is value in doing good, certainly we should think that this enhances the meaning of one’s life. Hence, I see no reason to accept Benatar’s claim that human lives are meaningless from the perspective of the universe.

Moving step back further in the argument, I think that we have good reason to doubt Benatar’s claim that the OLT optimist must adopt the perspective of humanity. His example is that of a tragic death at a relatively early age. Perhaps this is best described as a misfortune. It might be that we evaluate some kinds of misfortunes via such comparisons. We do not think it a misfortune that we cannot fly through the air or leap tall buildings in a single bound.Footnote 85 But this does not show that according to an OLT assessment, a life of only 40 years is not worth living. Isn’t that what we are concerned with? If so, we should stick to the subject. Would a life of a mere 40 years be worth starting? If such a life is filled with objective goods, it sure seems to be a LWL. Benatar gives no reason to think otherwise.

About our cognitive capacities, he argues that they make our lives richer than those of primates, but “we must concede that it would still be better if we were better equipped cognitively.”Footnote 86 But what is this concession supposed to imply? It does not imply that our lives are bad. It does not give us reason to think that our lives are not worth living. No, it merely tells us what we already know: things could be better. We could be smarter. We could live richer lives. Indeed. But this does not provide any support for pessimism.

Benatar argues that from the perspective of the universe “the quality of human life is [. . .] found wanting.” This statement is ambiguous. By “wanting” he might mean “could be better.” Alternatively, he might mean “bad,” or “not good.”Footnote 87 Surely, compared with the lives of gods, human life could be better.Footnote 88 There is no denying that. But this does not mean that human life is bad. If happiness is good, it is good. If helping others is good, it is good. If making something of beauty is good, it is good. If falling in love is good, it is good. Who cares if we can conceive of an even greater state of happiness, better forms of care, more fantastically beautiful creations, or richer forms of love? The fact that things could be better does not make them bad. This is not a case of seeing the glass half empty, but of calling a half full glass completely empty. That is wrong, not just pessimistic. To be worth living a life need not be the best conceivable life. No, it merely needs to be better than never to have been.

Once again Benatar fails to see that the opposite of better is not always bad; sometimes it is just less good. This mistake is fatal to his argument against OLT optimism, just as it undermines the asymmetry argument.

6 Conclusion

Benatar offers two arguments for the claim that one is always seriously wronged by being brought into existence. I argue that both arguments fail.

The first argument is the asymmetry argument. Its major premise is the asymmetry between the absence of goods and bads for the non-existent. Although I think that the asymmetry is untenable, I show that the argument fails either way. Even if we accept the asymmetry, we have no reason to think that coming into existence is always a net harm. The goods of life can, and often do, outweigh the bads. Many lives are worth living. Further, even if we accept the asymmetry, we have no reason to think that not coming into existence is always better than coming into existence. If we follow Benatar’s suggestion and apply a positive value to the absence of pain, many lives still have more positive value than non-existence. Although it might not be bad never to have been, it might sometimes be less good. Hence, the asymmetry argument fails.

The second argument is the argument from pessimism. It attempts to show that most, if not all, actual human lives are on balance bad for the those who live them. Accordingly, they are not worth starting. I argue that this is not always the case. Some lives are very good. They are high in objective goods. They might not be the best possible lives, but they are nevertheless worth living.

I briefly develop an objective list theory of what makes a life worth living. Lives worth living are those high in various objective goods such as knowledge, loving relationships, appreciation of beauty, achievement, moral worth, meaning, and happiness. Most plausibly, in standard cases we only wrong those we bring into existence who live lives worth avoiding. Happily, many lives are not like this. Those of us fortunate enough to have read Benatar’s book are likely living lives worth living. For us, it is better to have been. Benatar gives us no reason to think otherwise.Footnote 89