1 Introduction

Despite the traditionally individualistic approach of the field, mainstream epistemology has lately started being increasingly perceptive to the social dimensions of knowledge (Alston 2006; Fuller 2007, 2012; Goldman 1999, 2004, 2010; Palermos and Pritchard 2013). Nevertheless, this shift, or rather widening, of focus, raises the following question: How can we allow our epistemic inquiries to be socially oriented without abandoning the methodological individualism that underlies mainstream epistemology? Or, to put it the other way around, how can we pursue mainstream epistemology while accommodating our socio-epistemic intuitions?

This is a pressing question and, indeed, there have already been some attempts to outline such an approach. Each time, however, the focus has only been on the details of the partly social nature of specific types of knowledge, in isolation. Lackey’s dualism in the epistemology of testimony (2008) and Goldberg’s case for ‘coverage-support’ (2010)Footnote 1 are perhaps the most noteworthy examples, both of which constitute remarkable attempts to spell out the particular ways in which these two types of knowledge are—each in its own way—partly social. What seems to be missing from the literature, however, is a general approach to knowledge that could potentially reveal the partly social nature of knowledge anytime this may be the case. In some more detail, even though Lackey (2007) has launched an attack against the Credit Account of Knowledge (CAK)—i.e., roughly put, the idea that if S knows that p, then S deserves credit for believing truly that p—on the basis of testimony, she does not classify her dualism in the epistemology of testimony (2008) into any of the alternative, general approaches to knowledge. And even if Goldberg’s (2010) attempt to provide an explanation of the social nature of testimonial justification in terms of process reliabilism—according to which knowledge is true belief that is the product of a reliable process—is deemed satisfactory, his treatment of coverage-supported beliefs does not deliver the requisite result of ‘socializing’ coverage-support justification. In other words, a general account that could bring to the fore possibly all the ways in which knowledge might be partly social is yet to be disclosed.

The aim of this paper is to rectify this. Specifically, it will be argued that we can arrive at such an account by elaborating—pace Lackey’s renunciation of the view—on a virtue reliabilist version of CAK.Footnote 2 As we shall see, despite its orthodox pedigree, CAK—with its focus on the attribution of epistemic credit—is particularly apt for unraveling the exogenous, social nature of several distinct types of knowledge-acquisition: It can provide a promising account of the social nature of both testimonial and coverage-supported knowledge, but it can display additional explanatory power by also revealing the social nature of knowledge produced on the basis of epistemic artifacts (in fact, accommodating this type of knowledge may be thought to be quite a demanding test for virtue reliabilism, though, as we shall see, not an insurmountable one): In all these cases, according to CAK, the cognitive success may indeed be creditable to the cognitive agency of the individual subject whose knowledge status is being assessed, but only to a limited degree; the rest of the credit should, or so the argument will go, be attributed to other specific individuals, or to the epistemic society that the individual subject is embedded in. Accordingly, CAK can provide a unified approach to several and perhaps all cases of what we may call ‘weak epistemic anti-individualism’ within mainstream epistemology: i.e., the claim that the nature of knowledge can occasionally be both social and individual at the same time.

One important caveat is in order, however. The point here won’t be that knowledge might, in certain cases, be entirely social—i.e., the objective is not to argue for the possibility of strong epistemic anti-individualism within mainstream epistemology. In order to make this clear we need to examine Hardwig’s claim (1985) that the sort of epistemic dependence exhibited in cases like the ones mentioned above leads to either of the following two, seemingly unpalatable conclusions: (1) Either we must reject the individualist idea that in order to know one needs to be intellectually autonomous in possessing evidence (such as sound arguments and factual information) for the truth of what one knows; or (2) accept that such knowledge is not possessed by any individual alone, but by the epistemic community as a whole.Footnote 3 As we shall see, the present approach is an attempt to avoid the second option while explaining how it is possible to retain the first, but in a way that preserves the methodological individualism that underlies mainstream epistemology.

2 The Credit Account of Knowledge

Before we turn to any of the specific ways in which knowledge can be partly social in nature, it is important to first introduce the general approach to knowledge that we will be here focusing on and against the background of which the most specific social aspects of knowledge will be later accounted for. The Credit Account of Knowledge (CAK), as captured by virtue reliabilism,Footnote 4 can be defined as the combination of the following two intuitions: (1) The ability intuition on knowledge—i.e., the idea that knowledge is belief that is true in virtue of the manifestation of cognitive ability Footnote 5; and (2) the intuition that credit is rightfully attributed only in cases of success through ability. Specifically, according to CAK, knowledge—or, at least, a necessary aspect of it—is creditable true belief (Greco 2007, p. 57), which is creditable to a specific individual S, because, not only is it a belief that is true, but it is true in virtue of the manifestation of S’s cognitive ability.Footnote 6

On this view, cognitive ability is understood as a reliable belief-forming process that has been appropriately integrated into the agent’s cognitive character, where the agent’s cognitive character mainly consists of the agent’s cognitive faculties of the brain/central nervous system (CNS), including her natural perceptual faculties, memory, and the overall doxastic system. In addition, however, it can also consist of “acquired skills of perception and acquired methods of inquiry including those involving highly specialized training or even advanced technology” (Greco 1999, p. 287). Here is a relatively weak formulation of virtue reliabilism we can work with:

COGA weak Footnote 7

If S knows that p, then S’s true belief that p is the product of a reliable belief-forming process, which is appropriately integrated within S’s cognitive character such that her cognitive success is to a significant degree creditable to her cognitive agency (Pritchard 2010a, pp. 136–137).

What is the reason virtue reliabilists turn to an account of knowledge that stresses the creditable nature of the cognitive success (i.e., the true belief) as well as its origin in the agent’s cognitive ability? Mainly, the knowledge-undermining luck involved in Gettier cases. As Gettier demonstrated, one’s justified belief may turn out to be true without thereby counting as an instance of knowledge. In the typical scenario, one’s belief, which is the product of a faulty justificatory process, just happens to be true for reasons that are extraneous to one’s justification: In a lucky turn of events, one’s belief, which would otherwise be false (given it is produced in a defective way), turns out to be true. Contrast this with cases of success through the manifestation of ability. “There is a sense of ‘luck’ on which lucky success is precisely opposed to success through virtue or ability” (Greco 2007, 58). When one’s true belief is the product of the manifestation of one’s ability then believing the truth cannot have been lucky. Of course, one may still be lucky to believe anything at all (because, say, one could have easily been killed), but believing the truth is not lucky itself. Accordingly, and since credit is normally attributed in cases of success through ability, virtue reliabilists hold that when some agent knows, his belief must be true because of his cognitive ability, such that the cognitive success be, more or less,Footnote 8 creditable to him.

Moreover, and before we can leave CAK temporarily to the side, it will be helpful to settle one more question: According to virtue reliabilism, in order for a belief-forming process to count as a cognitive ability it must be part of the agent’s cognitive character. Accordingly, an important question to ask is what could it be required in order for a process to be so integrated? As far as common-sense intuitions are concerned, Greco (1999, 2010) has noted that the relevant belief-forming process must be neither strange nor fleeting (i.e., it must be a normal, dispositional cognitive process).Footnote 9 Despite such broad intuitions, however, Greco has noted in later work (2010) that in order for a process to be appropriately integrated within one’s cognitive character it must interact cooperatively with it. Specifically he writes: “cognitive integration is a function of cooperation and interaction, or cooperative interaction with other aspects of the cognitive system” (2010, p. 152).

3 The Dual Nature of Testimonial and Coverage-Supported Knowledge

While keeping the above in mind, it is now interesting to examine the existing attempts to construe certain types of knowledge as both social and individual. Specifically, the focus will be on Lackey’s dualism in the epistemology of testimony and Goldberg’s process reliabilist treatment of testimonial and coverage-support justification. All of these accounts constitute remarkably insightful attempts to accentuate the epistemic distribution of labor that takes place in these specific types of knowledge. Nevertheless, they fall short of providing a general approach to knowledge; one that can reveal the sense in which the nature of knowledge is partly social in several, and hopefully, all instances whereby this may be the case. In particular, even though Lackey rejects CAK on the basis of considerations having to do with testimonial knowledge, she does not classify her view under any of the existing alternative, general approaches to knowledge, and even if one accepts Goldberg’s process reliabilist explanation of the social nature of testimonial knowledge, his attempt to ‘socialize’ the justification of coverage-supported beliefs is not likely to be equally convincing. The aims of this section are (1) to critically examine the insights provided by the aforementioned attempts to reveal the particular ways in which these specific aspects of knowledge are social in nature and (2) to demonstrate that, despite Lackey’s renunciation of the view, CAK—with its focus on the attribution of epistemic credit—can in fact prove particularly helpful in accommodating and spelling out the social aspects of both testimonial and coverage-supported justification.

If this section is successful in demonstrating the above, the effect will be that CAK will start figuring as a strong candidate for providing a general approach to knowledge—one that can account for all known, and perhaps all possible, ways in which knowledge may be partly social in nature. Subsequently, the following Sect. 4 will seek to corroborate this expectation of theoretical progress by demonstrating how CAK can also reveal the social nature of knowledge produced on the basis of epistemic artifacts.

3.1 Testimonial Knowledge

Testimonial knowledge has always been a central topic in epistemology. The reason is simple: Very many of our everyday beliefs appear to have testimonial origins. Accordingly, any adequate account of knowledge should be able to accommodate this powerful source of knowledge.

Traditionally, the two opposing sides within the debate concerning testimonial knowledge are those of reductionism, which assigns the entire epistemic burden to the hearer, and non-reductionism, which shifts the epistemic burden to the speaker.Footnote 10 In some more detail, reductionists ascribe to the ‘positive reasons’ thesis, according to which, justification or warrant is attached to testimonial beliefs only by the presence of appropriate positive reasons that depend on sense perception, memory and inductive inference. Testimonial justification or warrant is therefore ultimately reducible to the justification/warrant of these basic epistemic sources.Footnote 11 On the contrary, according to non-reductionism, testimony is as epistemically basic as sense perception, memory and inductive inference. Therefore, acquiring testimonial knowledge does not require the possession of any positive reasons on the part of the hearer but only the absence of any negative ones: So long as there are no relevant undefeated defeaters,Footnote 12 hearers can acquire testimonially based knowledge merely on the basis of a speaker’s report.Footnote 13

In any case, however, regardless of whether one is a reductionist or a non-reductionist, there is no doubt that the speaker does play at least some role in the testimonial exchange, and this is a claim we need to examine in far closer detail for the following two reasons. Firstly, it renders testimonial knowledge the perfect candidate for a type of knowledge that is partly social in nature. Secondly, it is this particular, social aspect of testimonial knowledge that Lackey has exploited (2007) in order to argue against CAK. Accordingly, before we can continue we need to first put this worry to rest.

To appreciate Lackey’s objection, consider the following example:

Jenny Footnote 14

Jenny gets off the train in an unfamiliar city and asks the first person that she meets for directions. The person that she asks is indeed knowledgeable about the area, and gives her directions. Jenny believes what she is told and goes on her way to her intended destination.

Obviously, unless we want to deny a great amount of knowledge that we suppose we have, we must admit that Jenny can gain knowledge in this way. On the basis of this thought experiment, however, Lackey (2007) has argued that, apparently, given the way Jenny gains knowledge, her cognitive character does not have much to do with her true belief. Instead, it is the informant’s cognitive character that figures most importantly in the explanation of how Jenny believes the truth.

While this remark may initially sound harmless, Lackey argues that, if true, it is actually very problematic for proponents of CAK. This is because, if they want to account for testimonial knowledge in a way that will accommodate the Jenny case, they must loosen their demands by requiring that the agent’s cognitive success of believing the truth only be significantly (as opposed to primarily) creditable to the agent’s cognitive agency. By doing so, however, virtue reliabilists run the risk of rendering their view impotent with respect to the problem it was initially called to resolve. Remember that virtue reliabilists turn to an account of knowledge that stresses the creditable nature of the cognitive success precisely in order to do away with the knowledge-undermining luck involved in Gettier cases. If, however, in order to accommodate testimonial knowledge, virtue reliabilists demand only a weak—as opposed to strong—degree of creditability, they run the risk of loosing their grip on the problem posed by Gettier: Even though the agent’s belief is only luckily true in Gettier cases, he still deserves credit for employing his cognitive ability in order to believe something—no matter whether it is true or false—as opposed to nothing at all. Accordingly, it seems that on a weak version of CAK, victims of Gettier cases incorrectly count as knowing.

This may sound worrisome for COGAweak, which does indeed demand that the cognitive success be only significantly creditable to the agent’s cognitive agency. But if we pay attention to the details of what we have said so far, we will see that it is actually not worrying at all. First, remember that COGAweak is only a necessary condition on knowledge that may as well be supplemented with an anti-luck condition in order to account for Gettier cases.Footnote 15 But even if we don’t want to supplement COGAweak with any such modal principle, but we want, instead, to treat it as a full account of knowledge, we can still avoid the problem laid out above. This is because, as Greco (2010) has pointed out, virtue reliabilism (COGAweak included) does not merely require that one believe in virtue of cognitive ability and that one’s belief happen to be true. Instead, virtue reliabilism, properly understood, requires that one’s belief be true in virtue of cognitive ability—a crucial qualification that allows virtue reliabilists to deal with Gettier cases without necessarily requiring that the cognitive success be primarily creditable to one’s cognitive agency. To wit, so long as we demand that one believes the truth in virtue of one’s cognitive character—as opposed to merely demanding that one’s belief be true independently of how one arrived at it—we can do away with knowledge undermining luck (in the sense operating in Gettier cases), without worrying ourselves with whether the cognitive success may only be significantly, as opposed to primarily, creditable to one. Accordingly, in principle, virtue reliabilists can also account for testimonial knowledge, no matter that, in such cases, the credit for the hearer’s cognitive success is not predominantly down to her.Footnote 16 Therefore, virtue reliabilism, in general, and COGAweak, in particular, are well positioned to avoid Lackey’s worries with respect to the dilemma posed by Gettier cases and testimonial knowledge.

And in fact, as we are about to see, Lackey (2008) has recently offered a detailed account of testimonial knowledge that—despite her previous attack to CAK—is quite in line with COGAweak. Of course, this is an interesting observation on its own, but unpacking here Lackey’s account in terms of COGAweak can also reveal how CAK is well positioned to spell out the distribution of epistemic burden that takes place in cases of testimonial knowledge—a first, yet significant step towards demonstrating that CAK can provide a unified approach to possibly every instance of weak epistemic anti-individualism.

To start with, the first thing we need to note is that, contrary to reductionism that puts all of the epistemic responsibility on the hearer and non-reductionism that assigns at least the lion’s share—if not the entirety—of the epistemic work to the speaker, the main idea that motivates Lackey’s dualist account is that it “takes two to tango”: “[A]n adequate view of testimonial justification or warrant needs to recognize that the justification or warrant of a hearer’s belief has dual sources being grounded in both the reliability of the speaker and the rationality of the hearer’s reason for belief” (Lackey 2008, p. 177). Accordingly, Lackey formulates her account this way:

Dualism in the Epistemology of Testimony

For every speaker, A, and hearer, B, B knows (believes with justification/warrant) that p on the basis of A’s testimony only if:

(D1) B believes that p on the basis of the content of A’s testimony;

(D2) A’s testimony is reliable or otherwise truth conducive;

(D3) B is a reliable or properly working recipient of testimony;

(D4) The environment in which B receives A’s testimony is suitable for the reception of reliable testimony;

(D5) B has no undefeated (psychological or normative) defeaters for A’s testimony;

(D6) B has appropriate positive reasons for accepting A’s testimony. (Lackey 2008, pp. 177–8)

Now, before explaining how COGAweak can accommodate Lackey’s dualism on testimonial knowledge, we should make clear that the former can (easily) handle the Jenny case: Although the cognitive success is not primarily creditable to Jenny—but instead a significant part of the credit goes to the stranger—Jenny, by being responsive to epistemically relevant factors (for example, to epistemically reliable contexts and contextual figures, reliable classes of report and reliable speakers)Footnote 17 has the right sort of abilities and employs them in the right sort of way so as to deserve significant credit for accepting the stranger’s report. After all, she wouldn’t believe someone who is obviously drunk or evasive and she wouldn’t accept the suggestion to go past the city hall while she is obviously in a village. Therefore, according to COGAweak, Jenny can gain knowledge in this way.

Should we then be confident that COGAweak is in agreement with Lackey’s dualist account? And more importantly to the purpose of this paper, can it accommodate the distribution of the epistemic burden that Lackey’s account brings to light? Putting aside conditions D1 and D4, which are only meant to ensure that B comes to believe p on the basis of A’s testimonial report (D1) and that there is nothing tricky in the environment the testimonial exchange takes place (D4), it is important to see whether COGAweak can encompass conditions D2, D3, D5 and D6.

Consider, first, conditions D3, D5 and D6, according to which the hearer must: (D3) be a reliable or properly working recipient of testimony; (D5) have no undefeated defeaters for the speaker’s testimony; and (D6) have appropriate reasons for the speaker’s testimony. The incentive for discussing these three conditions together is that they are jointly meant to ensure the rational or at least, not irrational, acceptance of the speaker’s report. Moreover, notice that the absence of any undefeated defeaters against and the possession of positive reasons for a testimonial report—all the while the agent is a proper recipient of testimony in that had he had any negative or positive reasons in mind he would respond appropriately—Footnote 18can be thought of as the two sides of the same coin. Specifically, both conditions require that one be aware of, able and expected to detect any such reasons, should they become evidentially available. The only difference is that in order to acquire testimonial knowledge, no undefeated defeaters must remain in the end, while positive reasons must have been acquired. Importantly, however, both conditions require a fairly active stance on the part of the hearer in the sense that she must be on a continuous lookout—even if subconsciously so—for satisfying them.Footnote 19 Satisfaction of D3, D5 and D6 therefore ensures that acquiring a true belief on the basis of a speaker’s report will at least be significantly creditable to the hearer’s cognitive agency, such that, according to COGAweak, her testimonially derived true belief will amount to knowledge.

This leaves us with condition D2, which is the only condition that pertains to the speaker: The speaker’s testimony must be reliable or otherwise truth-conducive. First, we should here concentrate on the epistemic burden distribution entailed by D2. As previously noted, Lackey’s dualism, contrary to reductionism and non-reductionism that only focus on the hearer or the speaker, distributes the epistemic burden across both parties of the testimonial exchange. So how can COGAweak account for the dual origins of the epistemic justification/warrant?

Remember that according to COGAweak, knowledge can be attributed to S only if the cognitive success of believing the truth can be significantly credited to S’s cognitive agency. Crucially, however, COGAweak denies that the cognitive success must be wholly attributed to the hearer’s cognitive agency, thereby allowing, in cases of testimonial knowledge, for the rest of the credit to be, at least in part, attributed to the speaker’s epistemic effort. We can go back to the Jenny case to see how this works in practice: It is not that Jenny’s cognitive character has nothing to do with her believing the truth; it is just that the informant’s cognitive character is also important. In some more detail, a significant part of the credit can indeed be attributed to Jenny’s cognitive agency for employing the right sort of belief-forming processes so as to detect an appropriate speaker and rationally accept her words on the basis of positive reasons and the lack of any negative ones with respect to the offered report. At the same time, however, the rest of the credit can be, at least in part, attributed to the speaker’s cognitive agency for delivering a reliable report on the basis of which Jenny forms her true belief. COGAweak, therefore, can accommodate the very essence of Lackey’s dualism in the epistemology of testimony—i.e., the distribution of the epistemic credit across both the speaker and the hearer: The hearer deserves a significant amount of the epistemic credit for detecting an appropriate informant and rationally accepting her report, whereas the relevant speaker can be credited with delivering a reliable or otherwise truth-conducive statement that shapes the content of the hearer’s true belief.Footnote 20

Overall then, even though Lackey has argued that testimonial knowledge appears to pose a problem for CAK as captured by virtue reliabilism, we see that a virtue reliabilist condition on knowledge, viz., COGAweak, can accommodate Lackey’s own account of testimonial knowledge—admittedly one of the most promising and detailed accounts on offer.Footnote 21 For the purposes of the present discussion, however, what is distinctive of Lackey’s account is that it explicitly points out the dual sources of testimonial justification. That is, testimonial justification is not fully reducible to the hearer’s reasons for detecting an appropriate speaker and rationally accepting her report. Instead, it also supervenes on the reliability of the speaker’s report. Remarkably, COGAweak, which captures at least a necessary aspect of knowledge, allows the hearer to acquire knowledge, because the cognitive success can be significantly creditable to her cognitive agency. At the same time, however, it allows for the rest of the credit to be attributed to the speaker for offering a reliable report. Accordingly, COGAweak has the resources to do justice to Lackey’s insight regarding the distribution of epistemic burden that takes place in cases of testimonial knowledge. And since knowledge is here understood as creditable true believing and credit must be attributed to both parties of a testimonial exchange, testimony appears to provide a first instance of weak epistemic anti-individualism within mainstream epistemology: i.e., the claim that knowledge can occasionally be both social and individual in nature.

3.2 Epistemic Coverage Support

In his recent book, Goldberg (2010) appears to share Lackey’s insight with respect to the epistemic burden distribution that occurs in cases of testimonial knowledge. In fact, in order to accentuate the speaker’s involvement in the production of a reliable testimonial belief, he goes so far as to claim that the belief-forming process that produces the hearer’s justified true belief is a single belief-forming process that supervenes on both the hearer and the speaker’s cognitive sub-processes: “far from being merely local features of the subject’s environment, the testimony itself, along with the cognitive processes implicated in the production of that testimony, are more appropriately regarded as part of the testimonial belief-forming process itself. Call this the ‘extendedness hypothesis’” (2010, p. 79).Footnote 22

In some more detail, and to familiarize with Goldberg’s terms, his argument follows a Goldman-style Process (Historical) Reliabilism (1979), according to which, in order for a belief p to be reliable, it is not enough that the final phase of the process that leads to p be reliable; it is also necessary that the entire history of the process be reliable. For instance, in cases of belief-dependent, belief-forming processes like memory—where the input to the process of recollection is a belief that has been encoded at some point in the past—the reliability of the final, recollected belief does not only depend on the reliability of the process of recollection. Instead, it also rests on the reliability of the initial process of storing the original belief.

Moreover, early on in his book, Goldberg makes a point about distinguishing between what he calls local and global reliability (2010, p. 12): On one hand, a process is globally reliable (G-reliable) if it produces, or would produce, a preponderance of true over false beliefs, when employed in circumstances similar to the ones it is standardly used. On the other hand, a process is locally reliable if it produces, or would produce, a preponderance of true over false beliefs in circumstances that are relevantly similar to the ones it is being currently used.

Accordingly, as Goldberg further notes on the basis of the above distinction, a true belief will count as known if is both globally and locally reliable, but in order for it to count as doxastically justified, it only needs to be globally reliable (bid., p. 159). This is the reason why—and since he is not committed to virtue- but only to process-reliabilism as an account of doxastic justification—Goldberg attempts to unravel the partly social nature of testimonial beliefs by specifically ‘socializing’ testimonial (G-) reliability. Testimony is a ‘quasi-belief dependent’, belief-forming process, whose overall reliability is a function of the reliability of its input which, in turn, depends on the reliability of the cognitive processes that go on in the speaker’s head. Accordingly, “doxastic justification [i.e., G-reliability] of a testimonial belief depends [also] on the reliability of the relevant cognitive processes in the hearer’s informant” (ibid., p. 81).Footnote 23

There is no doubt that Goldberg’s account of testimonial knowledge is very interesting indeed, and despite any possible shortcomings,Footnote 24 it does remarkably well in exposing the social dimensions of testimonial knowledge in process reliabilist terms. There is, however, no need to further dwell on its details here, as the aim of this section is to focus on another very interesting epistemological phenomenon, which, even though it is somewhat related to testimony (or, rather, the lack thereof), it is not, as Goldberg himself notes, an instance of his “extendedness hypothesis”. I am referring to the ‘coverage-reliability’ of one’s community—an epistemic phenomenon that is nowadays increasingly effective due to the widespread use of information media such as the printed press, TV, radio and, most importantly, the World Wide Web.

To illustrate Goldberg’s point, consider that you know that there is no World-War taking place at the moment, that none of your colleagues was fired in the past few days (especially since it was only yesterday that you saw Jim the gossipmonger), that there are no protests taking place at the city center right now (as you’ve had the radio on for the last 20 min and there has been no relevant report), that Messi has not signed a contract with Real Madrid (nothing remotely related to this was mentioned last night during the sport news) and that Madonna, this morning, was still alive (your daughter, who avidly follows her on twitter, looked perfectly fine during breakfast). One of the underlying reasons for all these instances of knowledge, Goldberg claims, is that if any of those beliefs were true, you would have heard about it by now. Call the italicized conditional the ‘true-to-testimony conditional’ (TTTC).

In some more detail, coverage-supported beliefs are a “species of inferential belief, where one of the premises involved is none other than (something like) the truth-to-testimony conditional itself” (Goldberg 2010, p. 174). Specifically, a subject’s coverage supported belief that p is justified by her current belief that she has no memory of having been informed that not-p, together with her belief in the relevant instance of the truth-to-testimony conditional. Of course, there will also be relevant inferences that will not hold. Accordingly, Goldberg (2010, pp. 158–164) provides the following set of five conditions that he deems jointly sufficient for a subject’s coverage-supported beliefs to count as knowledge:

  1. i)

    Source existence condition: there must be some subgroup of members of the hearer’s community—we will call this group “the source”—who are disposed to report about the relevant sort of matters.

  2. ii)

    Reliable coverage condition: the relied-upon source must be reliable in uncovering and subsequently publicizing truths about the domain in which the subject is exhibiting coverage-reliance.

  3. iii)

    Sufficient interval condition: there must be some sort of coordination between the time-related expectations of [the hearer], on the one hand, and the abilities of [the source] to make any relevant discoveries, on the other.

  4. iv)

    Silence Condition: in point of fact, H has not encountered any relevant report to date.

  5. v)

    Receptivity Condition: H must be such that she would come across whatever relevant reports were offered by the source(s) on whom she was relying, were one to be made.

Now, letting the details aside, the above conditions should be relevantly uncontroversial; coverage-supported knowledge does exist, and it most likely behaves in ways very close to what Goldberg’s innovative account suggests.

Goldberg’s analysis, however, appears to face some serious problems when he attempts to account for the social nature of coverage support justification. As mentioned above, Goldberg avoids accounting for coverage-supported beliefs in terms of his ‘extendedness hypothesis’, primarily because, in such cases, the agent’s environment does not contribute any input to the agent’s belief-forming process. Granted, just like testimony, coverage-supported beliefs, on Goldberg’s construal, may still count as the product of belief-dependent, inferential processes: “The relevant inference would be from the subject’s currently formed belief that she has no memory of having been informed that not-p, together with her belief in the relevant instance of truth-to-testimony conditional, to the conclusion that p” (ibid., pp. 174–175). Since, however, there is no input from the social environment (if anything, the social environment affects the agent’s belief-forming process via the lack of any input to it), coverage-supported beliefs cannot be construed in terms of the extendedness-hypothesis. But then, if the reliability of coverage-supported beliefs does not depend on the reliability of any input received from the agent’s social environment (as in the case of testimonial beliefs), how can Goldberg account for the social nature of such doxastically justified beliefs?

Goldberg summarizes his strategy by noting the following: “The doxastic justification of coverage-supported belief will depend on the doxastic justification of the subject’s belief in the relevant truth-to-testimony conditional; and this, in turn, will depend on whether the subject is sensitive to the conditions under which she has relevant reliable coverage” (bid., p. 175). Specifically, Goldberg draws our attention to the “process by which the expectations of the coverage-relying individual are calibrated so as to be brought in line with the prevailing social practices and institutions in her community (ibid., 178).

The problem with the above claims, however, is that, contrary to Goldberg’s aim to ‘socialize’ the doxastic justification of coverage-supported beliefs, they actually accentuate the importance of the individual’s efforts to pitch her expectations about the relevant TTTC at the right level. In fact, Goldberg’s further remarks confirm this: “While the social institutions and practices I have been discussing constitute the background conditions on a subject’s coverage-supported belief, it is the subject’s sensitivity to the existence and nature of these institutions and practices, and her sense of what they portend in terms of the coverage that she is receiving, that determine the G-reliability of her coverage-supported beliefs (ibid., pp. 179–80; my italics). In other words, the social practices and institutions of one’s community do constitute the enabling (background) conditions that may allow one to form expectations of coverage-reliability and thereby coverage-supported beliefs. But even though such conditions are necessary for the subject to be able to form any coverage-supported beliefs whatsoever, the very G-reliability (i.e., doxastic justification) of her coverage-supported beliefs depends on her ability to form the right coverage expectations and thereby on herself, alone.

Clearly, however, this is not the requisite result of ‘socializing’ the reliability of coverage-supported beliefs. One would, therefore, expect Goldberg to have an ace up his sleeve that could help him turn the tables somehow. Curiously, however, the only move he makes is to offer the following remarks:

Two different coverage-relying subjects, as alike skin-in as any two distinct individuals can be, might nevertheless differ in the G-reliability of their respective coverage-supported beliefs, as one subject lives in a community in which these institutions and practices provide her with highly reliable coverage on the issue at hand, whereas the other lives in a community where the coverage is less highly reliable (and where there are more issues of interest to her that are not covered). Whatever difference there is in the G-reliability of their respective beliefs supervenes on more than what is going on in their respective heads: it also supervenes on the social practices and institutions that surround them.

Above, I say ‘curiously’, because, given Goldberg’s previous remarks (1) that a process is G-reliable if it is reliable in the environment it is standardly employed and (2) that the G-reliability of coverage-supported beliefs is a matter of the subject’s sensitivity to the nature and existence of the relevant institutions and social practices, one would have expected Goldberg to have presented a story that is substantially different from the one provided above. Specifically, for any two different coverage-relying subjects, who are as alike skin-in as any two distinct individuals can be, but who live in communities with different social practices and institutions, if they both are to be G-reliable in their respective coverage-supported beliefs at all, they must differ internally in one crucial respect: They must have different expectations about their communities and thereby relevant TTTCs.Footnote 25 Accordingly, for any given domain of beliefs, and for any two individuals who are both G-reliable in their coverage-supported beliefs in general, any belief p (under the given domain) must be equally coverage-supported G-reliable—that is, G-reliable simpliciter (see also fn. 25)—for both of them, because they are both in a position to hold some appropriately pitched TTTCs with respect to the relevant domain. Otherwise, if the two individuals differ with respect to their doxastic justification with respect to p, it will be because one of them does not even hold a coverage-supported belief in p, because her community does not even provide the necessary background conditions in order for her to form (on the basis of some appropriately-pitched TTTC) such a doxastically justified (i.e., G-reliable) coverage-supported belief in p. In any case, however, the G-reliability of their respective coverage-supported beliefs—if any—supervenes only on their internal goings-on. Specifically, their respective communities provide only the necessary structure for the two individuals to be in a position to merely form coverage-supported beliefs in the first place—G- or not-G-reliable alike. But whether any of these beliefs will end up being G-reliable indeed is a whole other issue, which depends solely on whether the individuals have managed to calibrate their expectations to the relevant TTTCs appropriately.

Accordingly, even though Goldberg’s analysis demonstrates that the existence of coverage-supported beliefs would be impossible in the absence of one’s social environment, it fails to reveal the epistemically social nature of such beliefs on the basis of process reliabilism, as it falls short of making the case for the social nature of the doxastic justification (i.e., G-reliability) of coverage-supported beliefs. Nevertheless, there might be an alternative, easier way to account for the epistemically social nature of coverage-supported beliefs on the basis of CAK.

Specifically, drawing on the above discussion, it is obvious that, in cases of coverage support, believing the truth (i.e., believing that p when p is the case) is due to the agent’s cognitive abilities: It is because of her abilities to calibrate with the relevant informational channels, recall that she has not encountered a report of not-p in the past, and draw the relevant inference on some appropriately pitched TTTC, that she comes to believe the truth with respect to p. Undoubtedly then, the agent’s cognitive success will at least be significantly creditable to her cognitive agency. Therefore, according to COGAweak, a subject can gain knowledge on the basis of coverage support. At the same time, however, given that in order for the individual to be in a position to draw inferences on the basis of relevant TTTCs, such that coverage supported beliefs can even be part of her doxastic repertoire, the relevant relied-upon source must be in place, part of the credit for the agent’s cognitive success must also go to the relevant aspects of her community.

Of course, it may be objected here that, by analogy of reasoning, in cases of knowledge on the basis of, say, vision, we should give credit to light (and so on and so forth to every environmental factor that makes the rest of our beliefs possible). There is a crucial difference, however, between this sort of natural causal contribution and the effect of one’s community in cases of coverage support; a difference that has to do with the fact that credit attributions have been traditionally associated with intentional agents. Accordingly, even though several extra-organismic factors may contribute causally in almost every case of belief-formation, credit for the resulting true beliefs should only be directed to those factors that, somehow, contribute intentionally. And since in the case of coverage support, the relied-upon source clearly intends to report information on matters that it is being relied upon, part of the credit can plausibly, and quite intuitively, be directed to it.

In other words, given (1) it is clear that one’s epistemic community does contribute causally and intentionally to the acquisition of coverage-supported true beliefs—even if only as a background, enabling condition and not by ensuring that the subject gets to the truth of the matter—and given (2) we also have a strong intuition that, in such cases, the individual subject does not deserve the entirety of the credit for her true belief, the remaining part of the credit for the ensuing cognitive success should be directed to the relevant relied-upon source.

Accordingly, if the epistemic phenomenon that Goldberg has unearthed obtains—and indeed it appears that it does—we can here finish the job that Goldberg’s attachment to process reliabilism appears to prevent him from running to completion. Specifically, if instead of process reliabilism we here follow CAK—according to which knowledge is understood as creditable true belief—and given that the credit for any cognitive success resulting from coverage support must be attributed to both the individual and the community she is relying upon, we can successfully claim that coverage-supported true beliefs constitute another important fragment of our everyday knowledge, which is both social and individual in nature.

4 The Dual Nature of Knowledge on the Basis of Epistemic Artifacts

When unpacked in terms of CAK, testimonial and coverage-supported true beliefs demonstrate the social nature of individualistic knowledge, as in both cases the subject’s success is not only creditable to her cognitive agency but also to other individual epistemic agents who have either offered the reliable testimonial reports that the subject rationally accepts as true, or have contributed to the source that allows the subject to have expectations of coverage and thereby coverage-supported beliefs. In this section, the aim is to demonstrate how CAK can go even further than these two testimony-related cases, by accommodating yet another type of cases that falls under the general heading of weak epistemic anti-individualism.

The cases I have in mind are cases whereby the agent comes to know something on the basis of the operation of some epistemic artifact. Think, for example, of perceiving a chair through a tactile visual substitution system (TVSS),Footnote 26 detecting the existence of a specific molecule by using a microscope, or coming to know the position of a satellite on the basis of a telescope. Before moving on to uncovering the social nature of this type of knowledge, however, we must focus on its details first, because, on closer inspection, it could turn out to be a particularly problematic type of knowledge for CAK—especially as motivated by virtue reliabilism.

To see why, consider that, according to the underlying ability intuition on knowledge, belief must be true in virtue of cognitive ability.Footnote 27 In the cases we here have in mind, however, the agent’s true belief arises out of the interaction of his organismic cognitive abilities with the epistemic artifact: An interaction, during which the artifact plays an integral and particularly crucial role with respect to detecting the truth. To make clear how this may be so, think of a well-trained agent, whose telescope has been recently broken. Even though the agent may still be able to form many relevant beliefs (if, say, he still wants to take his chances), none of them will be non-accidentally true, no matter how much he tries. By contrast, think of another agent in possession of a properly working telescope. In this case, not only will the agent be able to form pertinent beliefs, but, unlike the first agent, his beliefs will also come out systematically true. Therefore, it seems that, in such cases, the epistemic artifact is a crucial factor in one’s cognitive success that explains not why the agent merely possesses relevant beliefs but why his beliefs come out true.

To be clear, this is not to claim that one’s internal processes are not a significant factor in how one forms one’s beliefs. The factor, however, that seems to explain how one believes the truth of the matter is the artifact. Accordingly, in order to hold fast to the ability intuition on knowledge, virtue reliabilists must find a way to account for the artifact as being part of the agent’s cognitive character.Footnote 28 No doubt, this sounds like a counterintuitive or even intractable demand that can put virtue reliabilists in a particularly awkward position. Nevertheless, there may actually be a promising way to meet this challenge by invoking the hypothesis of extended cognition.

According to the hypothesis of extended cognition, “the actual local operations that realize certain forms of human cognizing include inextricable tangles of feedback, feedforward and feed-around loops: loops that promiscuously criss-cross the boundaries of brain, body and world (Clark 2007, sec. 2). Cognitive processing, in other words, can, and under the appropriate conditions, literally extends to the agent’s surrounding environment. Think about solving a mathematical problem by using pen and paper. According to the hypothesis of extended cognition, the involved artifacts are proper parts of the ongoing cognitive processing.

In fact, it has been previously argued that virtue reliabilism in general and COGAweak in particular are apt for an interpretation along the lines suggested by the hypothesis of extended cognition (Pritchard 2010a; Palermos 2011a, 2014a). First of all, as the reasoning goes, there is nothing in the formulation of COGAweak that restricts knowledge-conducive cognitive abilities to processes within the agent’s head. To the contrary, the idea of a cognitive character that may consist of “acquired methods of inquiry including those involving highly specialized training or even advanced technology”(Greco 1999, p. 287) seems to be compatible with or even prefigure the hypothesis of extended cognition (Clark and Chalmers 1998; Clark 2007, 2008; but also see Palermos 2014b).Footnote 29

If we focus on the details of the two theories, however, we can make a much stronger claim. Specifically, both theories put forward the same condition in order for a process to count as part of the agent’s cognitive system/character (and, thereby, by the lights of virtue reliabilism, as knowledge-conducive): Just as Greco claims that cognitive integration of a belief-forming process (be it organismically internal or external) is a matter of cooperative interaction with other parts of the cognitive system, so cognitive scientists have recently argued that in order for an artifact to count as a proper part of an agent’s cognitive system all that is required is that the two of them be non-linearly related on the basis of ongoing mutual interactions (Sutton 2008; Chemero 2009; Froese et al. 2013; Palermos 2014b; Theiner et al. 2010; Tollefsen and Dale 2012; Wegner et al. 1985).Footnote 30 Specifically, the claim is that in order to have an extended cognitive system—as opposed to a cognitive system that is merely embedded in the sense of being dependent on, but not constituted by, certain environmental aspects (cf. Adams and Aizawa 2001, 2008; Rupert 2004, 2009)—all we need is that the contributing parts (i.e., the relevant cognitive agents and their artifacts) interact continuously and reciprocally with each other.Footnote 31

We see, then, that both virtue reliabilism and the hypothesis of extended cognition put forward the same criterion (viz., cooperative interaction with the rest of the agent’s cognitive system) in order for a process to count as integrated into an agent’s cognitive system, and thereby as knowledge-conducive. Accordingly, there is no principled theoretical bar disallowing extended belief-forming processes from counting as knowledge-conducive: An agent may extend his cognitive character by incorporating epistemic artifacts to it.Footnote 32

So, for example, in this way, we can explain how a subject might come to know the position of a satellite on the basis of a telescope, while holding fast to the idea that knowledge is belief that is true in virtue of cognitive ability. Even though the belief-forming process in virtue of which the subject believes the truth is for the most part external to his organismic cognitive agency, it still counts as one of his cognitive abilities as it has been appropriately integrated into his cognitive character.Footnote 33 Moreover, the subject satisfies COGAweak, since his overall cognitive success is significantly creditable to his cognitive agency (i.e., his organismic cognitive apparatus): It is the subject’s organismic cognitive faculties that are first and foremost responsible for the recruitment and sustaining of the extended belief-forming process (i.e., telescopic observation) in virtue of which the truth with respect to the satellite’s position is eventually arrived at.

In cases like this, therefore, even though it is the external component that accounts for the truth-status of the agent’s belief, the agent’s cognitive agency—i.e., his organismic cognitive faculties—is still significantly creditable for having appropriately integrated the relevant external component into his cognitive system, and so the agent can, by the lights of COGAweak, count as knowledgeable.

Interestingly, however, at this point, the following question may arise: Whereto should the rest of the credit be attributed? This is a fair worry, for as it was argued above, in such cases, the prevailing factor in the causal explanation of the agent’s overall cognitive success is the integrated, extended belief-forming process that consists of both of one’s cognitive agency and the epistemic artifact, operating in tandem. Accordingly, since a significant part of the credit has been attributed to the agent’s cognitive agency, should we attribute the rest of the credit to the external aspects of the relevant reliable belief-forming process? That is, should we attribute credit to telescopes, microscopes, computers and so on? It seems that the answer to these questions should be negative.

The reason has to do with a consideration we have already alluded to in the discussion of credit attribution in cases of coverage-support: Even though, as Greco (2003) claims, credit attributions are very much akin to causal explanations, attributions of responsibility, praise, or merely neutral action i.e., attributions of positive, negative or merely neutral credit, respectively) have been traditionally associated with intentional agents. Therefore, to attribute credit to artifacts would be a categorical mistake. Notice, however, that artifacts can be defined as objects that have been intentionally made or produced for a certain purpose. Accordingly, the remaining credit should be attributed not to the artifacts themselves but to the individuals that intentionally brought the relevant extended belief-forming processes about. Notice further, however, that, frequently, it won’t be possible to attribute the rest of the credit to only one single individual, because, in most cases, a (potentially very large) number of individuals has contributed to the development of such reliable belief-forming processes, by having, for example, provided even more belief-forming (sub-) processes or relevant data produced on the basis of the latter. Accordingly, many times, the remaining credit, i.e., the credit that is associated with the external portion of the epistemic agent’s extended cognitive ability, will have to spread among a large part of the agent’s epistemic community.Footnote 34

To make the above more intuitive, let us pause to consider the interesting example of the FIA Formula One Championship. The F1 season consists of a series of races, the results of which are combined to determine two Annual World Championships; one for the drivers and one for the constructors. Accordingly, the analogy to be drawn is that the drivers play the role of the cognitive agents and the cars that of the epistemic artifact.Footnote 35 Now, what is remarkably to the point is the fact that, according to FIA’s rules, the credit for winning cannot be solely attributed to the drivers; hence the two championships. Moreover, quite reasonably, the points for the second championship do not go to the cars themselves, but to the constructor’s team that built the cars. In other words, the credit for winning does not get to be attributed solely to the cognitive agent that drives the car, but, also, to the team that brought his racing artifact (i.e., the car) about.

Now, if we think about it, very similar considerations may apply, mutatis mutandis, to the case of telescopic observation. In order to come to know the position of the satellite, the astronomer has to rely on an extended belief-forming process that was brought about on the basis of knowledge of long generations of mathematicians, physicists, opticians, machinists, astronomers, computer scientists (depending on the kind of telescope we are talking about) and, in general, a series of experts whose length could go on for a while. Had the astronomer not been part of this epistemic community, and therefore lacked the necessary reliable belief-forming process, he would be incapable of gaining knowledge of the target proposition.

Overall, then, the cognitive success of coming to believe the true position of the satellite is to a significant degree creditable to the particular astronomer—it is he who came to know the target proposition by employing the necessary belief-forming process—but the rest of the credit must be attributed to the individuals and in general the epistemic community that brought about the necessary belief-forming process.

If that’s true, however, consider how a similar description of the process of gaining propositional knowledge could apply within the fields of mechanics, physics, biology, chemistry, neuroscience and in general any discipline that involves the operation of epistemic artifacts. In order to come to know the truth of some proposition p, many times, epistemic agents have to employ reliable belief-forming processes produced by long generations of mathematicians, engineers, experimentalists, scientists, philosophers and many other experts.Footnote 36

In all these cases, therefore, just as in cases of testimonial knowledge and knowledge by coverage support, the epistemic credit for the agent’s cognitive success must spread between the individual agent and the relevant parts of her epistemic community. Before closing this section, however, it is perhaps worth pointing out what the difference is between the distribution of epistemic credit that takes place in cases of knowledge on the basis of epistemic artifacts and the spread of credit that occurs in the rest of the cases that the previous sections were dedicated on.

The main contrast has to do with the role that the social factors play in the cognitive ability that the agent employs in order to detect the truth. According to CAK and virtue reliabilism, the agent must not only believe the truth but he must arrive at it on the basis of his cognitive ability. In cases of knowledge by testimony, the agent ends up with a true belief on the basis of her own cognitive capacities that allow her to detect an appropriate informant and then rationally accept the offered report—provided the hearer deems the report reliable or at least not unreliable. The speaker therefore plays only a background role in how the agent forms a true belief, by offering a report that is in fact reliable, and which subsequently forms the content of the hearer’s belief. Similarly, in cases of coverage support, it is the agent’s internal cognitive abilities that allow her to believe the truth of the matter by appropriately calibrating with the relevant informational channels, recalling that she has not encountered a report of not-p in the past, and drawing the relevant inference on some appropriately pitched TTTC. Accordingly, the relevant parts of her epistemic community play again only a background role in how the agent forms a true belief, by making it possible for her to draw inferences on the basis of appropriately pitched TTTCs.

By contrast, in cases of knowledge on the basis of epistemic artifacts, the relevant aspects of the agent’s community do not merely play a background role. Admittedly, they affect the agent’s cognitive success only indirectly, since the agent does not interact with the other individuals themselves, but only with the artifact these individuals produced. Nevertheless, as noted above, in such cases, the artifact plays an integral role in how the agent detects the truth of the matter. Put another way, in such cases, the agent does not interact with the relevant external components in a linear, one-way dependence in order, for instance, to merely access information or enable herself to draw further inferences. Instead, the agent detects the truth by interacting with the artifact in a mutual, non-linear way. What this means, according to HEC, is that, in contrast to testifiers or the channels that support coverage support, in such cases, the external component does not play just a causal but a constitutive role in very process that is responsible for the agent’s cognitive success. Accordingly, when the agent knows on the basis of epistemic artifacts that she has appropriately integrated to her cognitive character, the epistemic community plays a much deeper role—even if indirectly so—and thereby deserves a bigger part of the epistemic credit in comparison to cases of knowledge by testimony or coverage-support.

So with that said, and to return to our overall argument, the upshot of this section is this: In all cases where the agent comes to believe truly on the basis of a belief-forming process that extends to some epistemic artifact, the knower is the individual, because the cognitive success is to a significant degree creditable to her cognitive agency for appropriately employing the relevant reliable belief-forming process that she has integrated into her cognitive character. Crucially, however, the rest, and perhaps the greatest part of the credit for the agent’s cognitive success will have to be attributed to the individuals, and, in general, to the epistemic community that brought the relevant extended belief-forming process about. Therefore, and since according to the CAK, as captured by virtue reliabilism, knowledge is creditable true belief, knowledge acquired on the basis of epistemic artifacts is yet another type of knowledge that is both social and individual in nature, in a rather substantial sense.

5 Conclusion: Epistemic Dependence and Weak Epistemic Anti-individualism

So far, it has been argued that individual knowledge, understood in terms of creditable true believing, often appears to be also social in nature. In particular, it was demonstrated that CAK cannot only account for the partly social nature of testimonial and coverage-supported knowledge, but it can also reveal the social nature of knowledge arrived at via the operation of epistemic artifacts. Admittedly, there are probably several other types of knowledge that are both social and individual in nature, but the above three cases represent a particularly significant and diverse set of a social subject’s overall means for acquiring knowledge. Accordingly, and contrary to any of the previous attempts to unravel the particular ways in which specific types of knowledge are partly social in nature, CAK looks very promising as a candidate for providing a unified account of all the possible ways in which weak epistemic anti-individualism may be instantiated.

Specifically, despite their variegation, it was argued that what all the above cases have in common is that they all satisfy the following claim: The subject’s cognitive success is significantly creditable to her cognitive agency and thus, according to COGAweak, the individual can be knowledgeable. What is also true in all these cases, however, is that the rest of the credit must go to one or more individual members of the individual subject’s epistemic community. This is so, either because those individuals offer reliable reports, form epistemic channels on which the subject can rely on for her coverage-supported beliefs, or have produced some reliable belief-forming process that the subject can integrate within her cognitive character so as to reliably form true beliefs. Therefore, to repeat the claim, if knowledge is to be understood in terms of creditable true believing and if, in all the above diverse cases, significant part of the credit must be attributed both to the individual subject and the epistemic community of which the subject is a proper part, then individual knowledge, in all these cases, turns out to be also social in nature, thereby clearly qualifying as an instance of weak epistemic anti-individualism.Footnote 37

But does this partly social nature of knowledge suggest, as some epistemologists have argued, that we should stop considering the individual as the proper object of our epistemological inquiries? To answer this worrying question, let us briefly go through what Hardwig thinks concerning the following case:

A knows that m

B knows that n

C knows (1) that A knows that m, and (2) that if m, then o

D knows (1) that B knows that n, (2) that C knows that o, and (3) that if n and o, then p.

Having the above in mind, Hardwig writes: “Suppose that this is the only way to know that p and, moreover, that no one who “knows” that p knows that m, n and o except by knowing that others know them” (1985, p. 348). If that’s the case, then we must agree that either “one can know without possessing the supporting evidence [for the truth of the relevant proposition] or accept the idea that there is knowledge that is known by the community, not by any individual knower” (Hardwig 1985, p. 349). In some more detail, according to Hardwig, cases such as the above demonstrate that knowledge and intellectual autonomy—in the sense of being self-sufficient in possessing the necessary evidence (such as sound arguments and factual information) for the truth of one’s belief—should come apart. Otherwise, if the link between knowledge and intellectual autonomy is to be preserved then knowledge, in cases such as the above, is not possessed by any individual alone, but by the relevant community as a whole, because it is that community alone that can be intellectually autonomous in possessing the relevant evidence.

Of course, the latter option is obviously problematic for mainstream epistemology and the methodological individualism that underlies it. Hardwig, however, assumes that the former option of abandoning intellectual autonomy as a prerequisite for knowledge is equally unpalatable for individualism and mainstream epistemology. But how so?

One possible answer is that Hardwig appears to implicitly rely on a popular internalist understanding of knowledge and justification, according to which S’s reasons for his true beliefs must be accessible to him by reflection alone.Footnote 38 Consequently, on the basis of this, Hardwig also comes to believe that the epistemic agent must be intellectually autonomous and that, crucially, a rejection of this requirement signifies a departure from mainstream epistemology and the underlying methodological individualism.

This doesn’t have to be so, however. For one, it is possible that such an interpretation of epistemic internalism is too strong and that not all formulations of epistemic internalism entail that one must be intellectually autonomous in possessing evidence for the truth of the relevant proposition. In other words, it is an open question whether internalism can account for the fact that one can have no evidence with respect to p but still know that p, simply by knowing that someone else knows that p.Footnote 39 But even if this is impossible, we can still bring into question the epistemic internalism that Hardwig seems to implicitly rely upon.

It is a happy incident, then, that virtue reliabilism in general and COGAweak in particular are externalist, though mainstream approaches to knowledge all the same, which have been proposed as alternatives to the classical internalist account. This is a happy incident, because COGAweak can easily accommodate Hardwig’s first and arguably rather intuitive conclusion that the individual is a proper epistemic agent, even though not autonomously so. To see how this might be, consider that, according to epistemic externalism, in order for one’s true beliefs to count as knowledge, they need not be backed up by reasons that one should in principle have introspective access to. And by so denying the demand for introspective access to one’s justification for one’s beliefs, epistemic externalism also makes the demand for intellectually autonomy appear under-motivated.

COGAweak, however, takes these considerations a step further. In particular, by allowing knowledge to be acquired merely on the basis of reliable belief-forming processes, such that the cognitive success can only be significantly creditable to one’s cognitive agency, it actually anticipates—if not ascertains—the denial of intellectual autonomy. Either the presence of the relevant input to, the enabling conditions for, or even the very existence of the belief-forming process itself may heavily depend on one’s epistemic community (or at least parts of it), and this is a fact that can be explicitly accommodated: COGAweak allows (the rest of the) credit to be attributed to those exogenous (or rather extra-organismic) epistemic factors as well. Nevertheless, at the same time, it recognizes the individual as the proper epistemic subject and stresses his/her importance by demanding that the cognitive success be significantly creditable to his/her cognitive agency.

Overall, then, COGAweak provides a way out of Hardwig’s dilemma: The phenomenon of epistemic dependence does not mean that we need to abandon epistemic individualism by admitting that there can be knowledge that is not known by any individual alone, but by the relevant community as a whole. Instead, COGAweak allows mainstream epistemologists to embrace Hardwig’s first conclusion that one can know a proposition p—even if not autonomously so—all the while remaining well in line with methodological individualism.

It should be made clear, however, that the above is not to claim that all externalist epistemology points away intellectual autonomy and strong individualism (as we may call the view that knowledge should be fully down to the individual). Having the reasons of one’s justification out of one’s reach of awareness is certainly not the same as partly having those reasons out of one’s bodily boundaries. For one thing, there can certainly be externalist conditions on knowledge, which are individualistic in nature. Take for example Lackey’s (2007) interpretation of Greco’s (externalist) Agent Reliabilism, according to which the cognitive success must be primarily creditable to S’s cognitive character. Such an account can clearly qualify as a form of weak individualism; and, if instead it demanded that one’s cognitive success be solely creditable to one’s cognitive agency, it would even qualify as a case of strong individualism, while being an externalist approach to knowledge all the same. Therefore, the internalism/externalism distinction is by no means the same as the individualism/anti-individualism distinction. And even though internalist conditions on knowledge are likely to be always tied to strong individualism,Footnote 40 externalist conditions appear to come in degrees, with the potential to occupy any available area on the continuum that the individualism/anti-individualism distinction defines.

COGAweak, however—with its lenient demands on the creditability of the cognitive success to one’s cognitive agency—is able to account for the whole spectrum of the continuum defined by the individualism/anti-individualism distinction. So far, we have been liberated from the demand of intellectual autonomy and the concomitant ‘duopoly’ of strong and weak epistemic individualisms, by pointing out how, on the basis of COGAweak, knowledge can be creditable to both some individual and the society of which he/she is a part, thereby arguing for what we have here called weak epistemic anti-individualism. Of course, this leaves open the even more liberal possibility of strong epistemic anti-individualism, according to which certain instances of knowledge may be entirely social in that they may be creditable only to a group of people as a whole—a rather interesting dialectical possibility, which is diametrically opposite to strong individualism, and about which more needs to be said in the future.

For now, however, it suffices that we have here taken the first steps towards an outline of how mainstream epistemology can provide a unified account of perhaps all the possible cases whereby our seemingly individualistic knowledge turns out to be social in nature as well: According to CAK, on a multitude of diverse occasions, the cognitive success of having a true belief turns out to be creditable not just to the relevant individual, epistemic agent but to his/her epistemic community as well. At the same time, however, in all these cases, the individual agent’s central role is also clearly acknowledged, thereby allowing for mainstream epistemology’s methodological individualism to be applied in such weakly anti-individualistic cases equally well.