1 Introduction

Four main sustainability paradigms have been suggested in the literature (Zagonari 2016): weak sustainability, a-growth, de-growth, and strong sustainability. Note that in this context, the economic general equilibrium framework is similar to weak sustainability, whereas the ecosystem services framework is close to strong sustainability.

Two main value changes have been evoked to achieve sustainability: a sense of responsibility, whether this is for nature (Pedersen 2015; Saniotis 2012; Van der Werff et al. 2013) or for current and future generations (Caselles 2013; Koukouzelis 2012); and an aversion to inequality, whether this is with respect to current or future generations (Golub et al. 2013; Kopnina 2016). Note that improved environmental technology, a decreased world population, and modified consumption patterns can be considered here as context changes for any combination of paradigms and values.

The purpose of this paper is to develop a model for the four sustainability paradigms within a single framework that accounts for changes in five values (a sense of responsibility for nature, for the current generation, or for future generations; an aversion to intra- or inter-generational inequality). The goal is to assess the feasibility of global environmental sustainability solutions that depend on changes in one or more of these values. In particular, I will characterise analytical and numerical solutions for cases based on extreme and estimated parameter values using data on the consumption level, the direct and indirect use of Earth’s environmental resources (hereafter, environment use), and the welfare level for representative individuals in both developed countries (i.e. the 35 OECD countries) and developing countries (i.e. the non-OECD countries). This will rank solutions in terms of feasibility classes: a reduction in welfare by > 25%, by 12.5–25%, and by < 12.5% will be considered unfeasible, slightly feasible, and moderately feasible, respectively, whereas an increase in welfare will be considered feasible.

Moreover, these characterisations will let us identify efficient solutions (i.e. Pareto and Kaldor–Hicks efficiency with respect to welfare) and measure equality (i.e. inequalities with respect to consumption, environment use, and welfare) at both intra- and inter-generational levels. This will reveal the internal consistency of the solutions with the assumptions of the four sustainability paradigms with respect to equality (e.g. weak sustainability cannot be linked to a large aversion to inequality) and efficiency (e.g. weak sustainability must be coupled with Kaldor–Hicks efficiency).

Finally, these calculations will identify which sustainability solution is consistent with a utilitarian approach (i.e. Harsanyi), an egalitarian approach (i.e. Arneson for welfare; Dworkin for consumption or environment use; Sen for consumption and environment use), or a contractarian approach (i.e. Rawls) (Habib 2013). This will characterise the sustainability solutions in terms of distributive justice (hereafter, equity).

In other words, this study can be read from a normative perspective so that, for a given sustainability paradigm or approach to equity, the framework defines which global environmental sustainability conditions should be achieved, if any. Alternatively, this study can be read from a positive perspective so that, for any sustainability paradigm or approach to equity, it identifies which value changes (i.e. demand policies vs. production policies such as taxes and standards) are crucial to meet sustainability conditions.

Note that all insights about feasible sustainability for the current generation are based on per capita data for representative individuals in OECD and non-OECD countries, weighted according to the country’s proportion of the world’s population. Moreover, sustainability conditions are checked for the main context changes (i.e. improved technology, decreased population, and modified consumption). Finally, a current, globally representative individual is compared with a future globally representative individual to describe inter-generational equity and efficiency, without splitting future generations into OECD and non-OECD countries.

This study provides several novel contributions to our knowledge. First, this study characterises the main sustainability paradigms (i.e. weak sustainability, a-growth, de-growth, strong sustainability) in terms of a few essential features (i.e. efficiency, equity, and consistency) and formalises these paradigms as constrained maximisation or minimisation problems using a few quantitative variables (e.g. GDP and ecological footprint). This allows comparison and ranking of the sustainability paradigms in terms of their feasibility, efficiency, equity, and internal consistency. Note that these sustainability paradigms represent continuity (weak sustainability and strong sustainability) and minimisation of environmental and social impacts (a-growth and de-growth) as typical aspects of sustainability, which Salas-Zapata et al. (2017) defined as “social and ecological resilience”. In particular, my analysis shows how some sustainability paradigms might be unfeasible in certain contexts (e.g. a-growth is unfeasible without improved technology) or how they require specific contexts to be feasible (e.g. de-growth can be feasible if combined with modified consumption, improved technology, or a reduced population).

Second, this study is the first to integrate the main value changes evoked to achieve sustainability (i.e. responsibility for nature, responsibility for future and current generations, and aversion to inter and intra-generational inequality) in a single framework. This allows a comparison and ranking of value changes in terms of their feasibility. Note that these values can be defined as “secular principles”, with “religious precepts” sometimes considered in addition to secular principles (e.g. the dignity of non-humans and harmony with nature in Hinduism or Buddhism, stewardship in Judaism, trusteeship and parsimony in Islam, love of neighbours in Christianity). Such religious precepts are sometimes similar to secular principles (e.g. responsibility for nature in Hinduism or Buddhism, responsibility for future generations in Judaism and Islam, responsibility for the current generation in Christianity). Alternatively, secular principles are sometimes considered in addition to religious precepts, as in the cases of efficiency or aversion to inequality.

Third, this study is the first to relate sustainability paradigms to the value changes required to achieve global sustainability. This will reveal feasible couples of sustainability paradigms with value changes that meet equity and efficiency criteria, feasible couples that satisfy the internal consistency criterion, and feasible couples that do not meet any criterion. In other words, this study contributes to the discussion of the most evident value changes required to achieve global sustainability by considering feasibility, efficiency, and equity. It accomplishes this goal by linking the value changes to the most common sustainability paradigms within a single framework that also depicts essential features such as modified consumption, improved technology, and reduced population.

Fourth, I apply the developed framework using real data at a national level by measuring concepts such as efficiency and equity.

This study also has certain implications for society. First, I stress that the choice of a given feasible sustainability paradigm might clash with criteria such as efficiency, equity, or consistency. As a result, it may require difficult trade-offs. Second, I distinguish among alternative value changes by linking them to a proportion of GDP expenditures on well-established items in national accounting procedures, such as environmental protection, environmental R&D and patents, and development assistance. This lets the numerical results translate easily into policy suggestions. Third, I reveal the consequences of commitments to criteria such as efficiency, equity, and consistency. For example, if global sustainability cannot be achieved by relying on responsibility for nature, responsibility for future and current generations, and aversion to inter- and intra-generational inequality (i.e. secular principles), a change in context may be required (e.g. modified consumption, improved technology, or reduced population), with potential moral problems (e.g. policies based on reducing a nation’s population). Alternatively, reference to other values could be suggested (e.g. dignity of non-humans, harmony with nature, stewardship, trusteeship, parsimony, or love of neighbours from religious precepts), with potential development problems (e.g. policies for restraining domestic demand). In other words, I provide a consistent framework to favour choices among value changes and sustainability paradigms to achieve global sustainability. Fourth, by applying this framework to real data at a national level, I quantify the required proportional value changes.

2 Paradigms, concepts, and approaches

In this section, I concisely define the efficiency concepts, equity approaches, and the four sustainability paradigms that I identified in the Introduction.

A sustainability solution is Pareto-efficient if the current generation in both OECD and non-OECD countries obtain greater welfare than in the status quo situation. In other words, there are no losers. A sustainability solution is Kaldor–Hicks efficient if current OECD and non-OECD generations together obtain greater welfare than in the status quo situation so that the losers can potentially receive compensation from the winners. A sustainability solution reduces inequalities between the current OECD and non-OECD generations in terms of consumption, environment use, or welfare level if the Gini index for one of these variables is smaller than the Gini index for the same variable in the status quo situation; this situation is defined as Gini-equitable. A sustainability solution improves the conditions for the current non-OECD generation in terms of consumption, environment use, or welfare if the minimum value of one variable is larger than its value in the status quo situation; this situation is defined MaxMin-equitable.

The main assumptions behind weak sustainability (i.e. development that meets the needs of the present generation without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs) can be summarised as follows (Schlör et al. 2015): needs are used as the unit of measurement; the same weights are used for current and future generations; and there is unconditional substitution among current economic, social, and environmental forms of capital at both intra- and inter-generational levels. A sustainability solution is consistent with the weak sustainability paradigm if it is at least Kaldor–Hicks efficient, and if it assumes small aversion to inter- and intra-generational inequality.

A-growth is an ecological and economic strategy focused on indifference to or neutrality about the economic level and growth, with both the economic level and growth considered to be non-robust and unreliable indicators of social welfare and progress (Van den Bergh 2010, 2011). It can be characterised as follows: welfare is used as the unit of measurement, as deduced from the aim of moving from wrong prices that result from the many neglected non-market transactions (e.g. informal activities and relationships) and the many unpriced environmental effects to the right prices (i.e. prices that account for both non-market and unpriced values); different weights are used for current OECD and non-OECD generations; and substitution between forms of capital is possible. A sustainability solution is consistent with the a-growth paradigm if it is Gini-equitable in welfare, and if it assumes small aversion to inter-generational and intra-generational inequality.

De-growth is an ecological and economic perspective based on achieving a socially sustainable and equitable reduction (and eventually stabilisation) of the materials and energy that a society extracts, processes, transports, distributes, consumes, and returns to the environment as wastes (Kallis 2011; Kallis et al. 2012). It can be characterised as follows: happiness is the unit of measurement, with a priority on meeting the needs of the poorest individuals, as deduced from the aim of introducing a basic income; the same weight is assigned to current and future generations; and substitution among forms of capital is acceptable. A sustainability solution is consistent with the de-growth paradigm if it is MaxMin-equitable in welfare and if it assumes a large aversion to inter- and intra-generational inequality.

The main assumptions behind strong sustainability (i.e. a development that allows future generations to access the same amount of natural resources and the same environmental status as the current generation) can be summarised as follows (Jain and Jain 2013): requirements for some incommensurable categories as unit of measurement; possibly assignment of different weights to current and future generations; and no substitution between current or future forms of capital, with natural and physical or social capital considered to be complementary. A sustainability solution is consistent with the strong sustainability paradigm if it is Gini-equitable for consumption and environment use, and if it assumes a large aversion to inter- and intra-generational inequality.

Utilitarianism, in the version I consider here (Harsanyi 1982) can be characterised as follows: equally weighting everyone’s welfare, with welfare defined as the satisfaction of rational, well-informed, and self-interested preferences, by maximising the total social welfare. A sustainability solution is consistent with the utilitarian approach if it is Pareto-efficient or Kaldor–Hicks efficient and if it assumes a small aversion to inter- and intra-generational inequality.

Egalitarianism, in the main three alternative versions that I focus on here, can be summarised as follows: it involves (1) levelling of resources or primary goods, as in Dworkin (1981); (2) equalising capabilities, as in Sen (1993); or (3) equalising opportunities for welfare, as in Arneson (1989). A sustainability solution is consistent with these egalitarian approaches if it assumes a large aversion to inter- and intra-generational inequality, and if it is Gini-equitable in consumption or environment use for case 1, Gini-equitable in consumption and environment use for case 2, and Gini-equitable in welfare for case 3.

Contractarianism, in the version considered here (Rawls 1971), can be characterised as follows: it arranges social and economic inequalities to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged people by opening offices and positions to everybody. A sustainability solution is consistent with the contractarian approach if it is MaxMin-equitable for consumption, environment use, or welfare, and if it assumes a large aversion to inter- and intra-generational inequality.

Note that I have disregarded libertarian approaches, both in terms of positive rights (Lomasky 1987) and negative rights (Nozick 1974), because it is arguable whether future generations or nature have rights in this context (Gosseries 2008). Moreover, sustainability solutions in terms of value changes could be turned into policy suggestions; for example, a sense of responsibility for nature, for future generations, or for the current generation could be translated into the proportion of the income allocated to environmental protection, environmental R&D, and aids for poor people. Finally, equality is assumed to be instrumental (Kershnar and Purves 2016), since a value is attached to consequences for people.

3 The model

This section provides simple formalisations for the four sustainability paradigms identified in Sect. 2 with the goal of requiring as little data as possible about representative individuals in OECD and non-OECD countries. For simplicity, and with full recognition that this approach ignores some exceptions, I have used the subscript N (northern hemisphere) to label parameters for OECD countries and the subscript S (southern hemisphere) for non-OECD countries. Appendix 1 lists all the abbreviations used in this model.

Let us assume that EN and ES identify the per capita use of the global environment by the current OECD and non-OECD generations, respectively. The per capita equilibrium level consistent with the current world population is η. Let us assume that XN, XS, and XF identify the per capita consumption levels in the OECD current generation, non-OECD current generation, and the future generations, respectively. Thus, the use of the environment for the OECD current generation is given by EN = θNXN, for the non-OECD current generation is given by ES = θSXS, and for the future generations is given by EF = θFXF, where θN, θS, and θF represent the use of the environment for each consumption unit for the current OECD generation, current non-OECD generation, and the future generation, respectively: θN and θS will be set at current values based on the current technology, and then simulated as smaller than current values to analyse the impacts of technological improvement.

Two main sustainability conditions can be formalised. The weighted sustainability condition requires that the use of the environment must be weighted according to the proportions of the global population in the OECD and non-OECD countries (pN and pS, respectively):

$$E_{{\rm C}} = p_{{\rm N}} E_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} E_{{\rm S}}$$

where EC stands for the total weighted use of the environment by the current generation in both OECD and non-OECD countries. The non-weighted sustainability condition requires that the use of the environment must be averaged between the representative individuals in the OECD and non-OECD countries:

$$E_{{\rm C}} = 1/2E_{{\rm N}} + 1/2E_{{\rm S}} .$$

Thus, in terms of consumption levels, these sustainability conditions become, respectively:

$$\eta = E_{{\rm C}} = p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}}$$

And

$$\eta = E_{{\rm C}} = 1/2\theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + 1/2\theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} .$$

The non-weighted sustainability condition will be used for the strong sustainability paradigm, and the weighted sustainability condition for the other sustainability paradigms. Let us assume that the utility for the future generations (UF) depends only on the consumption level:

$$U_{{\rm F}} = X_{{\rm F}}^{{\alpha_{{\rm F}} }} .$$

This is a Cobb–Douglas utility function in which αF represents the future preference for consumption. Indeed, I have optimistically assumed that socioeconomic development will gradually raise non-OECD countries to the same level as the OECD countries so that there is no future non-OECD generation and, consequently, future OECD countries cannot be concerned about non-OECD countries. Next, I have assumed that the use of the global environment is in its long-run equilibrium so that people do not need to feel a responsibility to preserve the environment for subsequent generations. See Supplementary Materials I for a discussion of the stability of pro-environmental equilibria. Let us assume that the welfare of the current non-OECD generation (US) depends on their consumption level, the use of the environment, and the welfare of the future generation:

$$U_{{\rm S}} = X_{{\rm S}}^{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} }} E_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \beta_{{\rm S}} }} U_{{\rm F}}^{{\gamma_{{\rm S}} }} .$$

This is a Cobb–Douglas utility function in which αS represents the preference for consumption, βS represents the degree of concern over use of the environment, and γS represents the degree of concern for future generations. Indeed, the current non-OECD generation is less affluent and cannot afford to be heavily concerned with people from OECD countries. Let us assume that the welfare of the current OECD generation depends on their consumption level, their use of Earth resources, the welfare of the future generation, and the welfare of the current non-OECD generation:

$$U_{{\rm N}} = X_{{\rm N}}^{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} }} E_{{\rm N}}^{{ - \beta_{{\rm N}} }} U_{{\rm F}}^{{\gamma_{{\rm N}} }} U_{{\rm S}}^{{\delta_{{\rm N}} }} .$$

This is a Cobb–Douglas utility function in which αN represents the preference for consumption, βN represents concern over the use of Earth resources, γN represents concern for future generations, and δN represents the concern for the current non-OECD generation (Lauwers 2012). In other words, both OECD and non-OECD countries are assumed to be concerned about their own environment (i.e. EN and ES, respectively) rather than about the overall world environment (i.e. EC = pNEN + pSES). Indeed, non-OECD countries might not be concerned about the environment in OECD countries, whereas OECD countries are assumed to be concerned about consequences of the use of the environment on the welfare level in non-OECD countries. Moreover, the concern for the total environment seems to be more plausible in the case of a specified common environment (e.g. a closed sea such as the Baltic Sea) to be shared by a specified group of countries. Appendix 2 presents a formalisation of this analysis in the case of a shared common environment. Finally, maximising the total welfare first and then accounting for sustainability conditions (rather than in the opposite sequence) would lead to higher production and consumption in the more efficient OECD countries, at levels even larger than current production and consumption, with sustainability conditions for the weak sustainability and a-growth paradigms being less feasible.

Note that a logarithmic transformation of the Cobb–Douglas utility functions permits analytical solutions. Moreover, in addition to being affected by nature, welfare could be directly affected by other types of capital such as social, physical, and human capital, where these forms of capital, like nature, contribute to achieving a given consumption level. Finally, each parameter attached to an item of the Cobb–Douglas utility function (e.g. α to consumption, β to the environment, γ to the welfare of future generations, δ to welfare of the current non-OECD generation) can be related to the proportion of the budget spent to purchase it. Let us assume that a representative individual in the current generation is concerned about welfare inequality between OECD and non-OECD countries:

$$U_{{\rm C}} = \left[ {(p_{{\rm N}} U_{{\rm N}} )^{1 - \varepsilon } + (p_{{\rm S}} U_{{\rm S}} )^{1 - \varepsilon } } \right]^{{1/\left( {1 - \varepsilon } \right)}} .$$

This is a constant elasticity of substitution utility function in which ε is the degree of aversion to intra-generational inequality (Asheim et al. 2012). Thus, the overall utility is given by:

$$U = \left[ {U_{{\rm C}}^{1 - \zeta } + U_{{\rm F}}^{1 - \zeta } } \right]^{{1/\left( {1 - \zeta } \right)}} .$$

This is a constant elasticity of substitution utility function in which ζ is the degree of aversion to inter-generational inequality. Alternatively, a representative individual in the current generation could be concerned about inequality in use of the global environment between OECD and non-OECD countries:

$$W_{{\rm C}} = \left[ {E_{{\rm N}}^{1 - \varepsilon } + E_{{\rm S}}^{1 - \varepsilon } } \right]^{{1/\left( {1 - \varepsilon } \right)}} .$$

Thus, the overall welfare would be given by:

$$W = \left[ {E_{{\rm C}}^{1 - \zeta } + E_{{\rm F}}^{1 - \zeta } } \right]^{{1/\left( {1 - \zeta } \right)}} .$$

Note that the time discount rate is assumed to be 0, as this is the only value that is consistent with long-run equilibria. Moreover, each social utility or welfare function can be linked to an Atkinson inequality index, in which parameters ε and ζ have the same meaning. Finally, extreme values of ε and ζ (i.e. at 0 and 1) permit analytical solutions.

Many theoretical definitions of the four sustainability paradigms can be suggested (Aznar-Marquez and Ruiz-Tamarit 2016). Here, I will apply the analytical definitions summarised in Table 1. Note that the “grand simplification” criticised by Norton (2005) (i.e. the preferences and needs of people in the future are unknown, present prices reflect future values, and resources are substitutable for each other; thus, sustainability boils down to maintaining capital stocks across time) and the “(strong) economic sustainability” suggested by Norton (2005) are close to the weak and strong sustainability paradigms formalised in Table 1, respectively. In contrast, the environmental ethics of Norton’s “normative sustainability” applies to all sustainability paradigms. In particular, OECD and non-OECD countries are both assumed to adopt a cooperative rather than a non-cooperative attitude, leading (for example) to a Nash equilibrium. This is realistic because currently, there is no coalition of OECD countries playing against the interests of non-OECD countries. Moreover, a non-cooperative context seems to be more plausible in the case of a specified group of countries exploiting a common environment. See Appendix 2 for a formalisation of this analysis in the case of a shared common environment. Finally, referring to a non-cooperative context disregards the aversion to inter-generational inequality.

Table 1 The analytical definitions of the four sustainability paradigms

Note that the analytical definition of de-growth does not depend on EN. This is consistent with the main critiques of this paradigm. Moreover, the four sustainability paradigms share couples of conditions: for example, Max U is shared by weak sustainability and a-growth; UF ≥ UC is shared by weak sustainability and de-growth; and EC ≤ EF is shared by a-growth and strong sustainability. Finally, the analytical definition of strong sustainability assumes that the parameters ε and ζ are set at 1. This is consistent with the main feature of this paradigm (i.e. maximum aversion to inequality).

By solving for the sustainability requirements for consumption level and environment use in non-OECD countries, and by using these expressions as inputs for the maximisation or minimisation problems that identify the four sustainability paradigms, it becomes possible to characterise these problems in terms of the variables for the OECD countries, for which solutions for XN and EN represent solutions for the world that meet global sustainability conditions.

Note that weak inequalities will be solved as equalities. Moreover, because other changes could affect the equilibria, a ceteris paribus analysis will be performed. Finally, dynamic stability conditions will not be considered, and static sustainability equilibria will be obtained.

Some methodological remarks are noteworthy here. The model employed in this study (i.e. the utility functions used to represent preferences) can be justified both theoretically and empirically.

In terms of its theoretical foundations, one should use a Cobb–Douglas utility function, which is based on the assumption that the preferences for a set of items are likely to be almost constant. Here, values such as a sense of responsibility for nature (β), for future generations (γ), or for the current generation in developing countries (δ) are likely to change slowly, if at all. Consequently, an almost constant proportion of the total budget will be allocated to these items (here, to environmental protection, green R&D and patents, and development assistance). Whenever items for which preferences are expressed can be considered to be pure substitutes, pure complements, or mixed substitutes and complements (here, the welfare of current and future generations), one should use a constant elasticity of substitution utility function. In terms of the model’s empirical foundations, the proportions of the total budget allocated to environmental protection, green R&D and patents, and development assistance (below, obtained from national statistics and expressed as a percentage of GDP) can be used to estimate all parameters of the Cobb–Douglas utility function (i.e. β, γ, and δ, once the values have been normalised with respect to α, as described in Sect. 4). This can be done by relying on the optimal solution of the usual utility maximisation problem subject to an income constraint in the case of a Cobb–Douglas utility function. For instance, the optimal expenditure for an item associated with β in the Cobb–Douglas utility function is given by [β/(α + β + γ + δ)] y, where y is the available income. The degree of aversion to intra- and inter-generational inequality (below, assumed to depict alternative scenarios) can be used to estimate all parameters of the constant elasticity of substitution utility function (i.e. ε and ζ) by relaying on the one-to-one relationship between the Atkinson inequality measure and a constant elasticity of substitution utility function, in which welfare increases if inequality decreases. In particular, the Atkinson inequality measure is given by 1 − [(1/n)∑(xi/x*)1−ε]1/(1−ε), with xi representing the value of item i, x* representing the mean of the total of n items, and ε representing the inequality aversion parameter.

4 Data and normalisations

Some parameters of the model developed in Sect. 3 can be directly estimated. In particular, the proportions of the world’s current population in OECD and non-OECD countries, based on World Bank world development indicators (http://data.worldbank.org) data for 2012, are pN = 0.18 and pS = 0.82. If the per capita use of the global environment is measured by the ecological footprint (i.e. the biologically productive area needed to provide everything an individual uses), sustainability of a representative individual for the world at the current population level requires EF to be at η = 1.7 ha (http://www.footprintnetwork.org), whereas the values for use of the environment in OECD and non-OECD countries, based on data for 2012, are 5.74 and 2.15 ha, respectively. The actual individual consumption as a percentage of GDP is available for each OECD country, with an average at 71.1%. Unfortunately, comparable data are not available for non-OECD countries, although their average is likely to be larger. Without significant loss of generality, I will assume that the per capita consumption is measured by the per capita income (i.e. GDP in USD, based on purchasing power parity [PPP]). Indeed, postponed consumption (as saving or investment) affects the welfare of future generations, but this welfare increase contributes to the current generation’s utility (i.e. both UN and US depend on UF). Moreover, consumption of imported goods (typically, in OECD countries) increases welfare where they are consumed, but their production might increase the use of the environment and so reduce welfare where they are produced and then exported (typically, in non-OECD countries). However, this welfare decrease in non-OECD countries contributes to the utility for OECD countries (i.e. UN depends on US). Finally, net exports equal net imports at the world level. Thus, the per capita consumption levels in OECD and non-OECD countries, based on world development indicators data for 2012, are US$36 727 GDP PPP and US$8216 GDP PPP, respectively. The current OECD generation’s aversion to inequality for the current non-OECD generation (ε) and the current generation’s aversion to inequality for future generations (ζ) are both in the range [0.01, 0.99].

Some parameters of the model developed in Sect. 3 require additional assumptions or manipulations. In particular, the future population was normalised to 1. In other words, I compare representative individuals for the current and future world, with a change in the future population depicted by a change in the sustainable per-capita EF. Future consumption preferences are assumed to converge towards the preferences of the current OECD generation (i.e. αF = αN). This assumption seems to be consistent with the observed aspiration of the current non-OECD generation, whereas a future preference for consumption at a level that equals the average of current preferences seems to be more plausible in the case of a specified group of countries at similar levels of development. See Appendix 2 for formalisation of this analysis in the case of a shared common environment.

The future generation achieves sustainability by relying on the environmental technology currently being applied by the OECD countries (i.e. θF = θN). In other words, complete technology transfer between developed and developing nations is optimistically assumed to be implemented in the future. Indeed, some technological convergence is likely to occur, although it is impossible to quantify the degree of this convergence. Moreover, a future technology that represents an average of the capabilities of current technologies seems to be more plausible in the case of a specified group of countries at similar levels of development. See Appendix 2 for formalisation of this analysis in the case of a shared common environment. Finally, this assumption does not affect the solutions for the a-growth and strong sustainability paradigms, but makes the solutions for the weak sustainability and de-growth paradigms less feasible.

The remaining parameters of the model developed in Sect. 3 can be indirectly estimated. In particular, the benchmark scenario is characterised by OECD countries attaching the same importance (i.e. the same budget share) to consumption level, environmental preservation, the welfare of future generations, and the welfare of people in non-OECD countries; in this analysis, the budget share for consumption represents the parameter with the maximum budget share (i.e. the preference for consumption is realistically assumed not to be smaller than the concerns for the other issues), with the budget shares for all parameters summing up to 1. On this basis, I have fixed αN at 0.25, and have normalised all other parameters with respect to this value (i.e. the observed budget shares are multiplied by 0.25). The OECD concern about the use of the environment (βN) is based on the assumption that 6.8% of GDP is devoted to the environment in OECD countries. This value was calculated by multiplying the observed average government expenditure on environmental protection as a percentage of GDP in OECD countries (i.e. 1.7% in the OECD data; http://www.oecd-ilibrary.org) by 4, to account for both public and private expenditures as well as for both direct and indirect expenditures. That is, this assumes equal expenditures for each of these four categories of expenditure. Similarly, the current OECD generation’s concern for future generations (γN) is based on the average value of 4.8% of GDP devoted to green R&D and patents in OECD countries. This percentage was calculated by multiplying the average observed expenditure on environmental R&D and patents as a percentage of GDP observed in OECD countries (i.e. 2.4% in OECD data; http://www.oecd-ilibrary.org) by 2, to take into account both direct and indirect expenditures. That is, this assumes equal expenditures for public and private expenditures. Similarly, the current OECD generation’s concern for the current non-OECD generation (δN) is based on the assumption that 1.2% of GDP in OECD countries is devoted to providing development assistance. This is calculated by multiplying the average observed official government expenditure on development assistance as a percentage of GDP in OECD countries (i.e. 0.3% in OECD data; http://www.oecd-ilibrary.org) by 4 to account for both public and private expenditures as well as both direct and indirect expenditures. That is, this assumes equal expenditures for each of these four categories of expenditure.

To facilitate comparisons between the numerical simulations, without significant loss of generality, I will normalise βN = γN = δN = 0.01 to represent an average share of GDP of 4% (i.e. [0.01/0.25] × 100%). Unfortunately, comparable data are not available for non-OECD countries. Without significant loss of generality, I will assume that αS = αN (i.e. since only three parameters are inputs for US, this implies a greater importance attached to consumption for people in non-OECD countries) and βS = γS = 0.005 (i.e. the current non-OECD generation’s concern over use of Earth resources and concern for future generations is assumed to be half of what is estimated for the current OECD generation). Indeed, all these figures are likely to be tiny but positive.

5 Results

This section, for the sustainability paradigms described using the model developed in Sect. 3, will provide analytical solutions for cases based on extreme parameter values, and identify numerical solutions for cases based on the data and normalisations described in Sect. 4. Appendix 3 presents statistical analyses to check for the significance and size of the five main secular environmental ethics for sustainability (i.e. β, γ, δ, ε, and ζ), by relying on the same dataset discussed in Sect. 4 and the formulas introduced in Sect. 3. I will do this by relying on graphs that represent the relevant conditions within the whole problem domain for the OECD consumption level and use of the environment: XN in [0, 36.727] and EN in [0, 5.74], where 36.727 and 5.74 are the current values. These solutions are then characterised in terms of the alternative efficiency and equity approaches by referring to the following current (i.e. status quo) values: XF = 10.876, EF = 1.7, UF = 1.81, XC = 13.348, EC = 2.79, and UC = 1.82.

Some methodological remarks are noteworthy here. The purpose of the analysis is not to explain many (past) observations of the same phenomenon and to predict its (future) dynamics, but rather to estimate the relative effectiveness of the (future) actions (here, value changes) required to achieve sustainability in a real context identified by a single (present) observation (here, the sustainability status of the economies of OECD and non-OECD countries). Consequently, the usual processes of validation and testing must be reinterpreted or rephrased.

The usual validation procedures for choosing a model are to identify a sub-sample of the observations; endogenously parameterise the model (e.g. by choosing parameter values to minimise the distance between the observed or empirical values and the simulated or theoretical values); and evaluate the estimation error of the model (i.e. measure the extent to which the model explains the data in the sub-sample once it has been parameterised). This approach cannot be applied in the present context because the sample is too small and unbalanced (i.e. 145 countries including both 33 OECD and 112 non-OECD countries) for a statistical analysis based on two sub-samples (i.e. for both OECD and non-OECD countries) to produce a reliable estimation of 9 parameters (i.e. αN, βN, γN, δN, αS, βS, γS, ε, and ζ) in a nonlinear model. Instead, the model explains a single observation with no error, since the parameters are exogenously calculated to depict this observation. Note that the logic of the algorithms and their self-consistency is corroborated, since both the analytical and the numerical solutions are obtained using the same software (i.e. Mathematica).

Next, the usual procedures for testing a model (i.e. identify an out-of-sample dataset and compare it with the predictions of the previously parameterised model) cannot be applied here. Indeed, there are no future observations of variables (i.e. X and E) with changed values (i.e. ΔβN, ΔγN, ΔδN, ΔβS, ΔγS, Δε, and Δζ) that could be used to perform any statistical analysis. Instead, the model predicts the future sustainability scenarios with no error, since calculations are presented over the whole variable space to ensure the absence of alternative solutions. Note that the reliability of the presented solutions is confirmed, since the accuracy and precision goals of Mathematica were set at 10 in this analysis (i.e. the calculation algorithm stops searching for solutions only if the relative distance from the root is smaller than 10−10; in other words, the error tolerances for the presented solutions are smaller than 10−10).

In other words, although the estimated parameters can be compared in terms of significance and plausibility (e.g. from the statistical analysis presented in Appendix 3, αN and αS are plausible and significant; βN and βS are significant, but implausibly large; γN, γS, and δN are plausible, but non-significant; ε is plausible, but non-significant; and ζ is significant, but implausibly large), a statistical analysis cannot produce reliable parameter values to be used in numerical simulations; thus, a dimensional analysis is performed instead. In particular, since the focus is on the relative effectiveness (ability to achieve sustainability) of value changes such as responsibility towards the environment (β), towards future generations (γ), towards the current generation in developing countries (δ), aversion to inequality within the current generation (ε), and aversion to inequality between current and future generations (ζ), all items associated with these parameters (i.e. ES or EN, UF, UN, and US) are one-digit numbers (i.e. a consistent set of units is applied). Note that XS is also a one-digit number, whereas XN is a two-digit number, although it is often around 10 and always smaller than 12.68 in feasible solutions. However, this irregularity is non-significant, since the associated parameter (α) is normalised to 0.25.

5.1 Corner solutions

In this section, I search for feasible solutions arising from changes in a single preference parameter to determine whether a single change can achieve sustainability. To do so, I measure feasibility in terms of acceptable welfare losses in OECD and non-OECD countries.

For a situation in which there is no concern for nature, future generations, and non-OECD countries (i.e. βN = γN = δN = 0) in OECD countries, and in which there is no concern for nature and future generations (i.e. βS = γS = 0) in non-OECD countries, and for which the current generation’s aversion to inequality for the current non-OECD generation and the current generation’s aversion to inequality for future generations are both at their minimum (i.e. ε = ζ = 0), the analytical solutions for the four sustainability paradigms are as follows:

For weak sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and UF ≥ UC),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{{\eta \alpha_{{\rm N}} }}{{\theta_{{\rm N}} \left( {p_{{\rm N}} \alpha_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \alpha_{{\rm S}} } \right)}}\quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm N}} \le {\text{exp}}^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}}$$

For a-growth (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{{\eta \alpha_{{\rm N}} }}{{\theta_{{\rm N}} \left( {p_{{\rm N}} \alpha_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \alpha_{{\rm S}} } \right)}}\quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta$$

For de-growth (i.e. UF ≥ UC and XC ≤ XF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} \le {\text{exp}}^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le X_{{\rm F}}$$

For strong sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max W and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm N}} }} \quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm S}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm S}} }} \quad {\text{and}} \quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta .$$

Figure 1 illustrates the numerical solutions for these equations based on empirical data.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on current preferences: αN = αS = 0.25, βN = γN = δN = 0.01, βS = γS = 0.005, ε = ζ = 0.01. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve to the right of this cluster represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

For a situation in which there is no concern for future generations and non-OECD countries (i.e. γN = δN = 0) in OECD countries, and for which there is no concern for future generations (i.e. γS = 0) in non-OECD countries, and for which the current generation’s aversion to inequality for the current non-OECD generation and the current generation’s aversion to inequality for future generations are both at their minimum (i.e. ε = ζ = 0), the analytical solutions for the four sustainability paradigms are as follows:

For weak sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and UF ≥ UC),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{{\eta \left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right)}}{{\theta_{{\rm N}} \left[ {p_{{\rm N}} \left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) + p_{{\rm S}} \left( {\alpha_{{\rm S}} - \beta_{{\rm S}} } \right)} \right]}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm N}} \le {\text{exp }}^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) p_{{\rm N}}}}}} \left( {p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} } \right)^{{\frac{{\beta_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) p_{{\rm N}}}}}} \left( {p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} } \right)^{{\frac{{\beta_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm S}} - \beta_{{\rm S}} } \right) p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) p_{{\rm N}} }}}}$$

For a-growth (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{{\eta \left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right)}}{{\theta_{{\rm N}} \left[ {p_{{\rm N}} \left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) + p_{{\rm S}} \left( {\alpha_{{\rm S}} - \beta_{{\rm S}} } \right)} \right]}} \quad {\text{and}} \quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta$$

For de-growth (i.e. UF ≥ UC and XC ≤ XF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} \le {\text{exp }}^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \left( {p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} } \right)^{{\frac{{\beta_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \left( {p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} } \right)^{{\frac{{\beta_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm S}} - \beta_{{\rm S}} } \right) p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\left( {\alpha_{{\rm N}} - \beta_{{\rm N}} } \right) p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}} \quad p_{{\rm N}} X_{N} + p_{S} X_{S} \le X_{{\rm F}}$$

For strong sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max W and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm N}} }} \quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm S}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm S}} }} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta .$$

Figure 2 illustrates the numerical solutions based on empirical data.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on the perceived responsibility for nature: αN = αS = 0.25, βN = βS = 0.73, γN = δN = 0.01, γS = 0.005, ε = ζ = 0.01. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from top to bottom. The thick decreasing curve represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

For a situation in which there is no concern for nature and for non-OECD countries (i.e. βN = δN = 0) in OECD countries, and in which there is no concern for nature (i.e. γS = 0) in non-OECD countries, and in which the current generation’s aversion to inequality for the current non-OECD generation and the current generation’s aversion to inequality for future generations are both at their minimum (i.e. ε = ζ = 0), the analytical solutions for the four sustainability paradigms are as follows:

For weak sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and UF ≥ UC),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{{\eta \alpha_{{\rm N}} }}{{\theta_{{\rm N}} \left( {p_{{\rm N}} \alpha_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \alpha_{{\rm S}} } \right)}} \quad {\text{and}} \quad X_{{\rm N}} \le {\text{exp}}^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}}$$

For a-growth (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{{\eta \alpha_{{\rm N}} }}{{\theta_{{\rm N}} \left( {p_{{\rm N}} \alpha_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \alpha_{{\rm S}} } \right)}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta$$

For de-growth (i.e. UF ≥ UC and XC ≤ XF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = { \exp }^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} U_{{\rm F}}^{{ - \frac{{\gamma_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} + \gamma_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le X_{{\rm F}}$$

For strong sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max W and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm N}} }}\quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm S}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm S}} }} \quad {\text{and}} \quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta .$$

Figure 3 illustrates the numerical solutions based on empirical data.

Fig. 3
figure 3

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on a concern for future generations: αN = αS = 0.25, γN = γS = 0.73, βN = δN = 0.01, βS = 0.005, ε = ζ = 0.01. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve to the right of this cluster represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

For a situation in which there is no concern for nature and future generations (i.e. βN = γN = 0) in OECD countries, and in which there is no concern for nature and future generations (i.e. βS = γS = 0) in non-OECD countries, and in which the current generation’s aversion to inequality for the current non-OECD generation and the current generation’s aversion to inequality for future generations are both at their minimum (i.e. ε = ζ = 0), the analytical solutions for the four sustainability paradigms are as follows:

For weak sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and UF ≥ UC),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} \eta {\text{ln}}\left[ {X_{{\rm S}} } \right]}}{{\theta_{{\rm N}} \left( {p_{{\rm N}} \delta_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm N}} \alpha_{{\rm N}} { \ln }\left[ {X_{{\rm S}} } \right] + p_{{\rm S}} \alpha_{{\rm S}} { \ln }\left[ {X_{{\rm S}} } \right]} \right)}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm N}} \le \alpha_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\delta_{{\rm N}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} }}}} { \exp }^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} { \ln }\left[ {X_{{\rm S}} } \right]^{{ - \frac{{\delta_{{\rm N}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} }}}}$$

For a-growth (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} \eta \,{ \ln }\left[ {X_{{\rm S}} } \right]}}{{\theta_{{\rm N}} \left( {p_{{\rm N}} \delta_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm N}} \alpha_{{\rm N}} { \ln }\left[ {X_{{\rm S}} } \right] + p_{{\rm S}} \alpha_{{\rm S}} { \ln }\left[ {X_{{\rm S}} } \right]} \right)}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta$$

For de-growth (i.e. UF ≥ UC and XC ≤ XF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \alpha_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\delta_{{\rm N}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} }}}} { \exp }^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} { \ln }\left[ {X_{{\rm S}} } \right]^{{ - \frac{{\delta_{{\rm N}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}} \quad p_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le X_{{\rm F}}$$

For strong sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max W and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm N}} }} \quad {\text{and}} \quad X_{{\rm S}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm S}} }} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta .$$

Figure 4 illustrates the numerical solutions based on empirical data.

Fig. 4
figure 4

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on a concern for non-OECD countries: αN = αS = 0.25, δN = 0.73, βN = γN = 0.01, βS = γS = 0.005, ε = ζ = 0.01. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve to the right of this cluster represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

For a situation in which there is no concern for nature, future generations, and non-OECD countries (i.e. βN = γN = δN = 0) in OECD countries, and in which there is no concern for nature and future generations (i.e. βS = γS = 0) in non-OECD countries, and in which the current generation’s aversion to inequality for the current non-OECD generation and the current generation’s aversion to inequality for future generations are at their maximum (i.e. ε = 1 so pNUN = pSUS) and at their minimum (i.e. ζ = 0), respectively, the analytical solutions for the four sustainability paradigms are as follows:

For weak sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and UF ≥ UC),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = X_{{\rm S}}^{{\frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm N}} \le { \exp }^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}}$$

For a-growth (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = X_{{\rm S}}^{{\frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta$$

For de-growth (i.e. UF ≥ UC and XC ≤ XF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = { \exp }^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le X_{{\rm F}}$$

For strong sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max W and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm N}} }}\quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm S}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm S}} }} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta .$$

Figure 5 illustrates the numerical solutions based on empirical data.

Fig. 5
figure 5

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on aversion to inequality for non-OECD countries: αN = αS = 0.25, βN = γN = δN = 0.01, βS = γS = 0.005, ε = 0.99, ζ = 0.01. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve to the right of this cluster represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

For a situation in which there is no concern for nature, future generations, and non-OECD countries (i.e. βN = γN = δN = 0) in OECD countries, and in which there is no concern for nature and future generations (i.e. βS = γS = 0) in non-OECD countries, and in which the current generation’s aversion to inequality for the current non-OECD generation and the current generation’s aversion to inequality for future generations are at their minimum (i.e. ε = 0) and at their maximum (i.e. ζ = 1 so UC = UF), respectively, the analytical solutions for the four sustainability paradigms are as follows:

For weak sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and UF ≥ UC),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = { \exp }^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm N}} \le { \exp }^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}}$$

For a-growth (i.e. first-order conditions for Max U and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = { \exp }^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta$$

For de-growth (i.e. UF ≥ UC and XC ≤ XF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = { \exp }^{{\frac{{U_{{\rm F}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} X_{{\rm S}}^{{ - \frac{{\alpha_{{\rm S}} p_{{\rm S}} }}{{\alpha_{{\rm N}} p_{{\rm N}} }}}} \quad {\text{and}} \quad p_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le X_{{\rm F}}$$

For strong sustainability (i.e. first-order conditions for Max W and EC ≤ EF),

$$X_{{\rm N}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm N}} }} \quad {\text{and}}\quad X_{{\rm S}} = \frac{\eta }{{\theta_{{\rm S}} }}\quad {\text{and}}\quad p_{{\rm N}} \theta_{{\rm N}} X_{{\rm N}} + p_{{\rm S}} \theta_{{\rm S}} X_{{\rm S}} \le \eta .$$

Figure 6 illustrates the numerical solutions based on empirical data.

Fig. 6
figure 6

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on aversion to inequality for future generations: αN = αS = 0.25, βN = γN = δN = 0.01, βS = γS = 0.005, ε = 0.01, ζ = 0.99. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve to the right of this cluster represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

Figures 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 and 6 show that there are no solutions for weak sustainability, apart from the case with (extreme) responsibility for nature, whereas the other three sustainability paradigms always have solutions. Table 2 suggests that, with current preferences, a-growth and strong sustainability are slightly feasible, although these solutions are Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare. Responsibility for nature makes all paradigms unfeasible. As expected, concern for future generations makes a-growth and strong sustainability feasible, and solutions are also MaxMin-equitable for welfare; Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare; and Pareto-efficient. Surprisingly, a concern for non-OECD countries makes a-growth and strong sustainability moderately feasible, and solutions are Kaldor–Hicks efficient and Gini-equitable for consumption and environment use. Aversion to inequality for non-OECD countries makes a-growth and strong sustainability moderately and slightly feasible, respectively, with a reduction of welfare by 5 and 16% for OECD and non-OECD countries, respectively, for a-growth, and by 25 and 5% for strong sustainability, respectively. In addition, all strong sustainability solutions are Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare, whereas a-growth is Kaldor–Hicks efficient. Aversion to inequality for future generations makes a-growth and strong sustainability slightly feasible, with a reduction of welfare by 23 and 6% for OECD and non-OECD countries, respectively, for a-growth, and by 25 and 5% for strong sustainability, respectively. In addition, all solutions are Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare.

Table 2 Feasibility (green = feasible, yellow = moderately feasible, red = slightly feasible, white = unfeasible), and levels and percent changes in consumption (X), environment use (E), and welfare (U) for developed OECD countries (subscript N) and developing non-OECD countries (subscript S)

5.2 Interior solutions

In this section, I search for feasible solutions arising from changes in all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility, for alternative values of the aversion to inequality parameters, by measuring feasibility in terms of acceptable welfare losses in OECD and non-OECD countries.

Figures 7, 8 and 9 show that there are no solutions for de-growth, whereas the other three sustainability paradigms have some solutions. Table 3 shows that weak sustainability is slightly feasible with small (and moderate) aversion to inequality: solutions are Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare and Kaldor–Hicks efficient and Gini-equitable for consumption and welfare. A-growth is slightly feasible with all levels of aversion to inequality, although the sustainability burden is larger for people of the non-OECD countries at larger values of ε and ζ; solutions are Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare with small and moderate ε and ζ, and Kaldor–Hicks efficient with moderate and large ε and ζ. Strong sustainability is always slightly feasible, regardless of ε and ζ; all solutions are Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare.

Fig. 7
figure 7

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility and small aversion to inequality: αN = βN = γN = δN = 0.25, αS = βS = γS = 0. 25, ε = ζ = 0.01. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

Fig. 8
figure 8

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility and medium aversion to inequality: αN = βN = γN = δN = 0.25, αS = βS = γS = 0. 25, ε = ζ = 0.50. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

Fig. 9
figure 9

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility and large aversion to inequality: αN = βN = γN = δN = 0.25, αS = βS = γS = 0. 25, ε = ζ = 0.99. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

Table 3 Feasibility levels (yellow = moderately feasible, red = slightly feasible, white = unfeasible) and percent changes in consumption (X), environment use (E) and welfare (U) for developed OECD countries (subscript N) and developing non-OECD countries (subscript S)

5.3 Sensitivity analyses

In this section, I search for feasible solutions at current preferences of OECD and non-OECD countries but in three different contexts: improved technology, decreased population, and modified consumption. Since the welfare of future generations is affected by all three context changes, I have modified the reference values accordingly: UF = 1.81 becomes UF = 1.95, 1.92, and 1.56 in contexts with changes in technology (θ), population (η), and consumption (α), respectively, whereas XF = 10.876 becomes XF = 14.502 and 13.595 in contexts with changes in θ and η, respectively.

Figures 10, 11 and 12 show that there are no solutions for weak sustainability, whereas the other three sustainability paradigms always have solutions. Table 4 shows that improved technology makes a-growth, de-growth, and strong sustainability slightly feasible. In addition, the solutions are Kaldor–Hicks efficient; Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare; and MaxMin-equitable for consumption and welfare. Decreased population makes a-growth, de-growth, and strong sustainability slightly feasible. In addition, the solutions are Kaldor–Hicks efficient and Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare. Modified consumption makes a-growth slightly feasible and de-growth and strong sustainability moderately feasible. In addition, all solutions are Gini-equitable for consumption, environment use, and welfare.

Fig. 10
figure 10

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on improved technology (i.e. increased environmental efficiency, θ): αN = αS = 0.25, βN = γN = δN = 0.01, βS = γS = 0.005, ε = ζ = 0.01, η = 1.7, θN = 0.1172, θS = 0.1957. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

Fig. 11
figure 11

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on reduced world population (η): αN = αS = 0.25, βN = γN = δN = 0.01, βS = γS = 0.005, ε = ζ = 0.01, η = 2.125, θN = 0.1563, θS = 0.2610. Numerical values on each curve represent (UF − UC)/UF. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

Fig. 12
figure 12

Solutions for use of the environment (EN) as a function of per capita consumption (XN) for OECD countries based on changed consumption preferences (α): αN = αS = 0.1875, βN = γN = δN = 0.01, βS = γS = 0.005, ε = ζ = 0.01, η = 1.7, θN = 0.1563, θS = 0.2610. The cluster of curves represents the relationship between EN and XN for four values of (UF − UC)/UF, with the value decreasing from left to right. The thick decreasing curve represents the first-order conditions for Max U. The increasing straight line represents the border condition for EF ≤ EC. The horizontal straight line represents the first-order conditions for Max W. The highest, middle, and lowest dots are the representative OECD, world, and non-OECD individuals, respectively

Table 4 Feasibility levels (green = feasible, yellow = moderately feasible, red = slightly feasible, white = unfeasible), and percent changes in consumption (X), environment use (E) and welfare (U) for developed OECD countries (subscript N) and developing non-OECD countries (subscript S)

In addition, feasible solutions can be found at current preferences and technology levels that characterise some representative OECD and non-OECD countries. I will refer to three highly populated countries in each group (i.e. Japan, Mexico, and the USA for OECD countries; Brazil, India, and Russia for non-OECD countries). Table 5 shows that there are no solutions for WS, whereas the other three sustainability paradigms always have solutions. In particular, OECD countries could increase their welfare by 32, 18, and 15% if they all apply AG by using current preferences and technology levels that characterise the USA, Mexico and Japan, respectively. These results can be explained by comparing these OECD countries with the average representative OECD country in Sect. 5.2. Specifically, compared with the values for the representative OECD country, γ is larger and ζ is smaller in the USA; ε is smaller in Mexico; and θ is smaller, γ is larger, and ζ is smaller in Japan. However, non-OECD countries would be worse-off by 16, 15, and 15%, respectively. Note that DG and SS would decrease welfare for both the OECD and the non-OECD countries, although to different extents.

Table 5 Alternative feasible solutions if OECD and non-OECD countries use the preferences and technology levels that characterise Japan, Mexico, and the USA (JAP, MEX, and USA, respectively) for OECD countries, and Brazil, India, and Russia (BRA, IND, and RUS, respectively) for non-OECD countries

In contrast, the non-OECD countries could increase their welfare by 9% if they all apply AG based on the preferences and technology levels that characterise Brazil; they could instead increase their welfare by 15 and 6% if they all apply DG by using to the preferences and technology levels that characterise Brazil and India, respectively, and by 13 and 4% if they all apply SS based on the preferences and technology levels that characterise Brazil and India, respectively. These results can be explained by comparing these non-OECD countries with the average representative non-OECD country used in Sect. 5.2. Specifically, compared with the values for that representative non-OECD country, γ is larger and θ is smaller in Brazil, and ε is larger in India. However, OECD countries would be worse-off, with welfare decreasing by between 11 and 33%.

Note that the aversion to intra-generation inequality ε refers to comparisons between OECD versus non-OECD countries. Consequently, a smaller ε increases welfare in OECD countries, whereas a larger ε increases welfare in non-OECD countries. Moreover, the average strategies turned out to be less effective than country-specific strategies in 3 and 5 out of 9 scenarios for the OECD and non-OECD countries, respectively. Finally, the aversion to inter-generation inequality ζ refers to comparisons between current versus future generations. Consequently, a smaller ζ increases welfare in countries that are currently better-off than future generations, whereas a larger ζ increases welfare in countries that are currently worse-off than future generations.

Thus, R&D should be increased and technology levels should be improved (i.e. γ and θ) in both OECD countries (like Japan) and non-OECD countries (like Brazil). Unfortunately, all the countries I considered, including both OECD and non-OECD countries, were characterised by too small expenditures for environmental protection and foreign aid (i.e. β and δ) as a percentage of GDP to deduce any policy suggestion.

6 Discussion

From a positive perspective, the insights about sustainability paradigms and value changes can be summarised as follows (Table 6). By considering the effects of modified consumption, decreased population and improved technology, the ordering of sustainability paradigms is a-growth > strong sustainability > de-growth > weak sustainability. Note that de-growth is unfeasible if we disregard these effects. A sense of responsibility for nature β never produced a feasible solution, whereas the ordering of the other value changes was γ > δ > ε > ζ. Note that all senses of responsibility combined with medium inequality aversions were ranked II, like the effect of improved technology θ; all senses of responsibility combined with small or large inequality aversions were ranked III, like the effects of modified consumption α and decreased population η. Thus, γ > δ = (β, γ, δ) if medium (ε,ζ) = θ > ε = α = η = (β, γ, δ) if small (ε,ζ) = (β, γ, δ) if large (ε, ζ) > current preferences = ζ.

Table 6 Feasibility of the sustainability paradigms

From a normative perspective, in terms of internal consistency, the insights about sustainability paradigms and value changes can be summarised as follows (Table 7). A case consistent with weak sustainability (i.e. Kaldor–Hicks efficient with small ε and ζ) has no solutions. A case consistent with a-growth (i.e. Gini-equitable for welfare with small ε and ζ) allows a choice between γ, δ, all senses of responsibility combined, and all context changes, although γ is more feasible. A case consistent with de-growth (i.e. MaxMin-equitable for welfare for any ε and ζ) must rely on context changes. A case consistent with strong sustainability (i.e. Gini-equitable for consumption and environment use for any ε and ζ) allows a choice between γ, ε, and ζ, all senses of responsibility combined, and all context changes, although γ is more feasible. In summary, by considering the effects of modified consumption, decreased population, and improved technology, the ordering of sustainability paradigms is strong sustainability > a-growth > de-growth, whereas weak sustainability was never internally consistent. Note that de-growth is internally inconsistent if we disregard these effects. Although modified consumption, decreased population, and improved technology are ranked better than a sense of responsibility for future generations (i.e. α = η = θ > γ), the ordering of the value changes is γ = (β, γ, δ) with all (ε, ζ) > δ = ε = ζ.

Table 7 Internal consistency

From a normative perspective, in terms of consistency with equity approaches, the insights about sustainability paradigms and value changes can be summarised as follows (Table 8). A case consistent with the utilitarian approach (here, Harsanyi; Kaldor–Hicks efficient with small ε and ζ) could be a-growth with a change in γ or δ, or strong sustainability with a change in γ or δ.

Table 8 Consistency with the equity approaches

With a focus on consumption or environment (here, Dworkin; Gini-equitable for consumption or environment use), a case consistent with the egalitarian approach could be weak sustainability with all senses of responsibility combined and small or medium aversion to inequality; it could be a-growth with current preferences, a change in γ, δ, or ζ, all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility with small or medium aversion to inequality, and all context changes; it could be de-growth with all context changes; or it could be strong sustainability with current preferences, a change in γ, δ, ε, or ζ, all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility with all aversion to inequality, and all context changes.

With a focus on welfare (here, Arneson; Gini-equitable in welfare), a case consistent with the egalitarian approach could be weak sustainability with all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility and small or medium aversion to inequality; it could be a-growth with current preferences, a change in γ or ζ, all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility with all levels of aversion, and all context changes; it could be de-growth with context changes; it could be strong sustainability with current preferences, a change in γ, ε, or ζ, all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility with all levels of aversion, and all context changes.

With a focus on consumption and environment (here, Sen; Gini-equitable in consumption and environment use), a case consistent with the egalitarian approach could be weak sustainability with all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility and small aversion to inequality; could be a-growth with current preferences, a change in γ, δ, or ζ, all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility with small or medium aversion, and all context changes; could be de-growth with context changes; or could be strong sustainability with current preferences, a change in γ, δ, ε, or ζ, and all preference parameters related to a sense of concern or responsibility, with all levels of aversion, for all context changes.

A case consistent with the contractarian approach (here, Rawls; MaxMin-equitable in consumption, environment use, or welfare) could be a-growth with a change in γ, improved technology, and modified consumption; could be de-growth with improved technology and modified consumption; or could be strong sustainability with a change in γ, improved technology, and modified consumption. In summary, by considering the effects of modified consumption, decreased population, and improved technology, the ordering of sustainability paradigms is strong sustainability > a-growth > de-growth > weak sustainability. Note that de-growth is inconsistent with any equity approach if we disregard these effects. Although modified consumption and improved technology are ranked better than a sense of responsibility for future generations (i.e. α = θ > γ > (β, γ, δ) with all (ε, ζ) = η > δ = ζ = current preferences > ε), the ordering of value changes is γ > δ = ζ > ε.

The approach developed in this paper confirms several expected (i.e. intuitive) insights:

  1. 1.

    An inter-generational sense of responsibility (γ) is the most important feature, although a concern for non-OECD countries (δ) also leads to sustainability with a-growth and strong sustainability.

  2. 2.

    A population reduction makes de-growth feasible.

  3. 3.

    Improved technology makes a-growth more feasible, and to a greater extent than with a population reduction.

  4. 4.

    Modified consumption makes de-growth more feasible.

  5. 5.

    Strong sustainability reduces inequality in consumption, environment use, and welfare in all scenarios, apart from welfare in a case with a concern for non-OECD countries (δ).

The approach developed in this paper provides several unexpected (i.e. counterintuitive) insights:

  1. 1.

    Aversion to inequality for non-OECD countries (ε) is more important than aversion to inequality for future generations (ζ), although people of non-OECD countries pay more with larger ε than with larger ζ, whereas the opposite holds for people in OECD countries.

  2. 2.

    An increase in aversion to inequality for either non-OECD countries (ε) or for future generations (ζ) makes a-growth more feasible in cases with a sense of responsibility for nature (β) and current (δ) and future (γ) generations.

  3. 3.

    Modified consumption makes strong sustainability more feasible.

  4. 4.

    In a case with a sense of responsibility for both nature (β) and current (δ) and future (γ) generations, a-growth and strong sustainability lead to feasible sustainability conditions that provide similar welfare for OECD and non-OECD countries, despite differences in the representative individuals, if aversion to inequality both for non-OECD countries (ε) and for future generations (ζ) is small.

  5. 5.

    A large sense of responsibility for nature (β) provides no feasible solutions for all sustainability paradigms.

Weaknesses of the present study include:

  • Environmental free-riding (i.e. some individuals pay for the consequences of the environmental use by other individuals) is not modelled (e.g. in Appendix 2, EN and ES are replaced by EC = ∑ piEi). However, welfare in OECD countries depends on welfare in non-OECD countries, which in turn depends on their environmental use (i.e. UN depends on US, which depends on ES = 2 η − EN and ES = η/pS − (pN/pS) EN for non-weighted and weighted sustainability conditions, respectively).

  • The institutionalisation of sustainability (i.e. implementation of technical, legal, and moral systems; development of organisations, boards, and offices to implement sustainability strategies; Ott 2014) is not discussed. However, most operational conditions that would lead towards sustainability are identified (e.g. δ should be preferred to γ).

  • Feasibility was defined based on arbitrary thresholds (i.e. a welfare reduction larger than 25% was defined as unfeasible). However, comparisons between value changes and the four sustainability paradigms are independent of these thresholds (e.g. a-growth and strong sustainability should be preferred to weak sustainability, which should be preferred to de-growth).

Strengths of the present study include:

  • The framework combines sustainability paradigms and equity approaches to find a theoretically coherent solution that can lead to sustainability or an operationally implementable policy that will lead to sustainability.

  • The results confirm insights in the literature on context changes such as modified consumption and improved technology (Zagonari 2015), but they also expand these insights to include value changes by distinguishing among four sustainability paradigms and by considering proportions of the global population in OECD and non-OECD countries and the dynamics of these populations.

  • Neither a top-down nor a bottom-up approach to preference changes is suggested; instead, the most important features linked to each sustainability paradigm and equity approach are identified.

Therefore, in normative terms, if the a priori commitment is a consistent sustainability paradigm, this study suggests a focus on γ (if a-growth or strong sustainability is adopted), δ (if a-growth is adopted), ε (if strong sustainability is adopted), ζ (if strong sustainability is adopted), all senses of concern or responsibility combined (if a-growth or strong sustainability is adopted), and all context changes (if a-growth, de-growth, or strong sustainability is adopted). Moreover, in normative terms, if the a priori commitment is a consistent equity approach, this paper suggests a focus on γ (in the case of utilitarian, egalitarian, or contractarian approaches), δ (in the case of utilitarian or egalitarian approaches), ε (in the case of an egalitarian approach), and ζ (in the case of an egalitarian approach). Finally, in positive terms, the most effective sustainability conditions, regardless of consistency of the adopted paradigm or approach, appear to be γ > δ > ε > ζ for value changes and a-growth > strong sustainability > de-growth > weak sustainability for sustainability paradigms.

7 Conclusions

Three main novel findings were obtained in this study. First, weak sustainability and de-growth, which include the constraint UF ≥ UC, are both theoretically problematic to sustain and empirically difficult to implement, since the happiness or needs of future generations, which depend on spatial and temporal variations in culture, cannot be easily defined or measured. Second, sustainability conditions cannot be achieved by relying only on a sense of responsibility for nature, but instead must rely on a concern for both future generations and non-OECD countries. In other words, relying on a sense of responsibility for nature, which only indirectly affects future generations, is theoretically ineffective; indeed, welfare losses in the absence of concern for future generations and non-OECD countries are large under all paradigms, although sustainability conditions differ among the paradigms. Relying on a sense of responsibility for nature is also operationally difficult; for example, agreements between religions are difficult to achieve, since their philosophies have evolved from different cultural backgrounds and histories. Third, the perspectives of a single individual (i.e. the focus is on individual sustainability) and of a representative individual (i.e. the focus is on overall sustainability) that are assumed by a-growth and strong sustainability, respectively, lead to sustainability at similar levels of per capita consumption and use of the environment by both OECD and non-OECD countries.

The main theoretical good news from this study is that the ecological debt (i.e. the current average ecological footprint of 2.79 ha is larger than the long-run equilibrium value of 1.7 ha) can be paid in full by the current generation if there is significant concern for future generations and non-OECD countries, although the welfare burden depends on the possible preference changes and the distribution of this burden depends on the adopted sustainability paradigms.

The main operational good news is threefold. First, sustainability can be achieved at current preferences with reasonable burdens for the current generations in OECD and non-OECD countries if a-growth or strong sustainability is adopted. Second, improved technology and modified consumption could increase welfare for the current non-OECD generation compared with the status quo. Third, whenever a feasible solution exists, the sustainability burden on current OECD generations is proportionally larger than that on current non-OECD generations.

The main theoretical bad news is that two of the four sustainability paradigms are not internally consistent: weak sustainability was never Kaldor–Hicks efficient (with and without context changes), whereas de-growth was never MaxMin-equitable (without context changes).

The main operational bad news is threefold. First, achieving sustainability implies an increase in inter-generational inequality: the current unsustainable representative individual for the world is closer to the future sustainable representative individual than to the current sustainable representative individual in terms of both consumption and environment use in all sustainability paradigms. Second, reducing the world’s population, as endorsed by the de-growth paradigm, is not enough to achieve sustainability, although the current non-OECD generation would not decrease its status quo welfare if strong sustainability or de-growth were adopted. Third, if the suggested changes in preferences related to a sense of concern or responsibility are interpreted as changes in the budget share, sustainability conditions appear difficult to achieve.

Three main developments from this paper seem to be particularly promising. First, it should be possible to move from aggregated data to more detailed data on consumption levels. This would allow the inclusion of expenditures for additional factors such as health and education, possibly at a national level. Second, it should be possible to enhance the current one-shot model to produce a dynamic model, which would allow an investigation of issues related to overlapping generations. Third, moving from aggregated data to more detailed data on the direct and indirect use of Earth’s resources would allow the framework to account for both pollution production and resource use, possibly at a national level.