1 Introduction

This paper examines the views of Mill, Hayek, and Buchanan on the role of discussion in the constitutional order. We link Hayek’s criticism of Mill with Buchanan’s criticism of Hayek, arguing that both disagreements turn on the role for discussion within the economic and political sphere. For Mill and Buchanan, the constitutional order itself may be subjected to discussion (and change). By contrast, Hayek made the case that the constitutional order is best left unarticulated, outside the realm of public debate and discussion. The question as Hayek posed it is whether there is a role for discussion in “choice of law” the way there is a role for discussion in the “choice of legislation.” For Mill and Buchanan, the answer is yes; but for Hayek, the answer is no.Footnote 1

Having emphasized the role of discussion in the constitutional order, we then turn to the idea of law in greater detail. Supposing, with Hayek, that law evolves as a recognized pattern, we inquire about whether the pattern is unique. If multiple sets of experiences or patterns co-exist in society, then any one pattern is an incomplete description of experience and the question arises of whether there is now a role for the recognition and then discussion of other patterns or laws? We follow this thinking up in Sect. 4, where we sketch out how a norm of generosity might eventually be brought into a constitutional order as justice, through a process of discussion. We show how the analysis can be applied to the example Buchanan developed in response to Hayek, that of the messy beach. Finally, we suggest that Hayek’s appeal to government to remedy institutional incompleteness (Whitman 1998) or “degeneration” actually takes him quite close to Mill’s position, that discussion can serve to beneficently direct institutional change.

Throughout our analysis, we focus on Hayek’s views on the evolution of institutions, while acknowledging that Darwinism is most often considered in terms of the evolution of human beings.Footnote 2 Institutional evolution was, Hayek maintained, a matter of the application of ideas that pre-dated Darwin to the realm of institutions:

A nineteenth-century social theorist who needed Darwin to teach him the idea of evolution was not worth his salt. Unfortunately, some did, and produced views which under the name of ‘Social Darwinism’ have since been responsible for the distrust with which the concept of evolution has been regarded by social scientists. ... The error of ‘Social Darwinism’ was that it concentrated on the selection of individuals rather than on institutions ... (Hayek 1973, p. 23).Footnote 3

As noted above, a key to Hayek’s disagreements with both Mill and Buchanan is the role of discussion in the context of constitution making. For Hayek, discussion may derail the evolutionary process with all the nice properties that entails. Discussion of law can do very little good and a great deal of harm. By contrast, neither Mill nor Buchanan is predisposed to find that institutions evolve optimally. Consequently, both Mill and Buchanan allow that discussion may in fact do some good and not do a great deal of harm. We suggest that Mill and Buchanan reside squarely in a Smithian framework (and they depart from Hume) in which “generosity” fills in gaps in the development of “law” or contracts. Discussion is one means by which this is accomplished.

Our reconstruction of the differences between Mill and Buchanan on the one hand, and Hayek on the other, focuses on foundations. With Buchanan, we see Hayek as a “sophisticated” rather than a naive “cultural” evolutionist (1977, p. 327). In our reading of the evidence, Mill and Buchanan allow for the possibility of systematic differences in experience, so that there is no clear-cut favored evolutionary path; while Hayek does not.Footnote 4 When experience differs systematically, proverbial wisdom—whereby the experiences of the polity are summarized in a central tendency—may provide a starting point for discussion and institution-making.Footnote 5 Starting from a summary of experience, discussion of systematically different experiences might be used to overturn, revise, or update the polity’s understanding of what’s “best”, and institutional change may be effected.

2 Law, patterns, and discussion

In Hayek’s account, law is the result of observation and pattern recognition, something that evolves and is in some sense beyond articulation or discussion:Footnote 6

The first of these attributes which most rules of conduct originally possessed is that they are observed in action without being explicitly known to the acting person in articulated (‘verbalized’ or explicit) form. They will manifest themselves in a regularity of action which can be explicitly described, but this regularity of action is not the result of the acting persons being capable of thus stating them (1973, p. 19)

As is well known, Hayek stresses the efficiency property of rule following as agents come to treat each other impartially. Footnote 7 But he takes a step beyond this to suggest that, in fact, rules function well “especially so long as” they remain outside the realm of discussion:

every man growing up in a given culture will find in himself rules, or may discover that he acts in accordance with the rules–and will similarly recognize that he acts in accordance with rules–and will similarly recognize the actions of others as conforming or not conforming to various rules. This is, of course, not proof that they are a permanent or unalterable part of ‘human nature’ or that they are innate, but proof only that they are part of a cultural heritage which is likely to be fairly constant, especially so long as they are not articulated in words and therefore also are not discussed or consciously examined. (Hayek 1973, p. 19)Footnote 8

Indeed, Hayek goes so far as to suggest that discussion is “counter-productive”. This was, he held, especially true of the discussions of “social justice” that arose following the loosening of moral obligations in the transition to a market economy.Footnote 9

To consider our case in some detail, we need a better account of the content of what Hayek refers to as “law.”Footnote 10 In a sequence of articles and books beginning with the 1945 lecture “Individualism: True and False” and stretching beyond the three volume Law, Legislation and Liberty of the 1970s, Hayek distinguished between liberal thinkers who gave priority to spontaneously occurring “law” and those for whom legislation enacted by majority rule was all one need worry about. He called the former, “Continental liberals”, and the latter, “English liberals.” Continental liberals, he argued, identified law with legislation; they are said to be “constructive rationalists”. The latter believe that law is the foundation of legislation in an evolutionary sense; they are adherents of “spontaneous order.” The “Continental liberal,” the “rationalist” of greatest concern to Hayek, was the great British empiricist, Mill.Footnote 11

Hayek’s criticism of Mill turned on his perception that Mill was responsible for much of the collectivist policy making of the 20th century, policy making that in Hayek’s view had resulted from unfruitful “discussion” of the constitutional order. In his conversation with Buchanan, Hayek attributed the “delusion” that democratic politics is sufficient to limit government authority to the British utilitarians, including Mill (Hayek and Buchanan 1978). Earlier, Hayek wrote that Mill’s was a “false liberalism” that “always” tended towards “socialism or collectivism”: “design theories necessarily lead to the conclusion that social processes can be made to serve human ends only if they are subjected to the control of individual human reason, and thus lead directly to socialism” (1946, p. 4).

The implication is that it would be far better simply to submit to the constitutional order, to law. Indeed the efficiency properties of rule following were stressed early on by Hayek. In the 1944 Road to Serfdom he asserted that one needed to “submit” to prices; these were unfit for discussion.Footnote 12 Beginning in the 1960s, he sketched an account of the inarticulate institution that underlies science itself.

Until we have definite questions to ask we cannot employ our intellect; and questions presupposed that we have formed some provisional hypothesis or theory about the agents.

Questions will arise at first only after our senses have discerned some recurring pattern or order in the events. It is a re-cognition of some regularity (or recurring pattern, or order), of some similar feature in otherwise different circumstances, which makes us wonder and ask ‘why’? ... To such curiosity we owe the beginning of science. (1967, pp. 22–23)

So, patterns of behavior underlie the law that is so critical to society. These patterns need not be articulated by those who follows the precepts of law:

In the instances so far quoted it will probably be readily granted that the “know how” consists in the capacity to act according to rules which we may be able to discover but which we need not be able to state in order to obey them. The problem is, however, of much wider significance than will perhaps be readily conceded. If what is called the Sprachgefühl consists in our capacity to follow yet unformulated rules, there is no reason why, for example, the sense of justice (the Rechtsgefühl) should not also consist in such a capacity to follow rules which we do not know in the sense that we can state them. (1967, p. 45)

From this argument, follows Hayek’s distinction between law and legislation in a liberal society. The conclusion he draws from the distinction between inarticulate law and articulate legislation is that the discussion of law can do very little good and a great deal of harm. Most famously and controversially, Hayek made this case in the oft-reprinted 1949 “Intellectuals and Socialism.”

Here, the difference between Mill and Hayek becomes most pronounced. One of the points Mill made in On Liberty was that the discussion of poorly understood norms (Hayek’s inarticulate law) would make them more effective.Footnote 13 For many liberals, regardless of what might divide them, law which is not articulated violates the deepest constitutional constraint. It is the hallmark of totalitarian systems that one can be charged with and convicted of violations of secret legislation.Footnote 14 So, for instance, Mill was the greatest speaker of his era for the cause of widespread access to contraceptive information. Such “discussion” became legal in Britain only once the conviction of Mill’s disciples, Besant and Bradlaugh, for the crime of publishing an “obscene” tract on birth control, was reversed on appeal because the prosecution had failed to articulate what constituted the obscenity in the case. (Peart–Levy 2005b, 2008).

The difference between Hayek and Mill may of course be a result of different historical moments from which they surveyed their worlds. Outlook and emphasis obviously changed. Mill was optimistic about the outcome of discussion—seeing room for the improvement of the existing constitutional order and fearing that, if law and institutions are left alone, beyond the pale of discussion, little improvement will occur. By the mid 20th century, however, a great deal of the sort of constitutional change favored by Mill had obviously already been implemented. Perhaps, then, it is not so surprising that Hayek’s outlook was less optimistic about prospects for additional improvements in the constitutional order. At any rate, he seems to have concluded that additional discussion of law (though not of legislation) now had the potential to derail the good properties of institutional evolution and he allowed a role for discussion only when evolutionary gaps and institutional “degeneration” demonstrated to his satisfaction that evolution had failed.

This “context” explanation, however, fails to explain all. For Buchanan’s historical moment of survey overlapped that of Hayek and yet Buchanan’s position on this is closer to that of Mill than Hayek. It was precisely the issue of law without discussion, law as it evolves, which provoked Buchanan’s criticism of Hayek; and in the process of answering Hayek, Buchanan came to a solution very much like that of Mill in On Liberty.

3 Law as proverb

Supposing, with Hayek, that law evolves as a recognized pattern, the question that emerges from the foregoing is whether the pattern is unique? If it is, then perhaps the issue of discussion is moot: there seems little point in discussing a pattern to which we are all subject. But if multiple sets of experiences or patterns co-exist in society, then any one pattern is an incomplete description of experience. So the question arises of whether law reflects the experience of the majority and whether there is now a role for the discussion of other patterns or laws? We now turn our attention to this step in the argument.

We begin by developing a more precise means to consider what Hayek meant by “pattern” or law. In previous work (Peart–Levy 2005c) we have argued that people rely on proverbial wisdom because proverbs carry information in addition to the “theories” of scientific experts. Here, we suggest that we might consider Hayek’s “pattern” or “law” as a summary of experience akin to our “proverbial wisdom”.

Consider Fig. 1 in which we locate three points, a, b, c, in XY space. They do not lie on a straight line. An expert might explain the XY relationship by computing a regression line which touches no point but summarizes all points. This would be OLS in Fig. 1. How can a non-expert make a rule out of observed behavior without such devices? Suppose there are a great many ordinary people each of whom might see different and unrelated behavior. We define what Hayek calls “patterns,” and we call “anecdotal evidence,” as the lines containing [a,b], [b,c], [a,c]. Which one of these patterns might become law?

Fig. 1
figure 1

Fitting a regression

Here is where Hayek is a little vague; however, there are suggestions that he believes that law results from the majority of observations.Footnote 15 This ties into our formulation quite neatly, as we have argued that selecting the median slope of the anecdotal evidence [MAE] would be akin to computing a regression by voting. Passing between majority rule and sample medians is a result which goes as far back as Galton in 1907 (Peart–Levy 2005c).

Corresponding to Hayek’s concern about the vanity of the expert,Footnote 16 the assumption which keeps such devices as the MAE from being considered in the textbooks is that the expert’s model has probability one status. When this is not so, and we allow for both random regime shifts and influential observations, then it is possible to construct cases where the median of anecdotal evidence provides a superior estimate to the textbook estimate of least squares or least absolute deviations regressions.

We have argued (Peart–Levy 2005c) that such technical devices as MAE are instantiated in the real world as “proverbs.” This is consistent with Hayek’s defense of superstition found in the last appendix of Fatal Conceit (Hayek 1988). It is also consistent with Hayek’s larger program of upholding the wisdom of regular people as opposed to experts that anecdotes were a tool of resistance in the Stalinist era.Footnote 17

If Hayek’s “law” is similar to our “MAE” then we can use this tool to work through the differences between Hayek on the one hand, and Buchanan and Mill on the other. In particular, while the MAE may have superior properties to the expert’s models, there may be contenders for which line is “law,” for the relevant proverbial wisdom.Footnote 18 In addition to majority experience, there may be systematic minority experience. Hayek’s analysis suggests that law is unique in each society; he leaves little room for competing systematic experience. This is, perhaps, where Hayek diverges most radically from Smith (and from Mill and Buchanan), who all point to differences in majority and minority experience.Footnote 19 Without uniqueness of law in society, the survival of a society does not necessarily imply the law is best.

4 Just and generous acts

Supposing that laws or patterns of experiences are not unique, the next question is how to choose among them? In Sect. 2 above we emphasized the importance of discussion without disclosing what, exactly, might be achieved through discussion. Here, we explore how a norm of generosity might eventually be brought into a constitutional order as justice (as law) through a process of discussion.

Following Hume’s argument, Hayek focused on one evolved convention, “justice.” For Hume, justice is co-extensive with property and contract.Footnote 20 Smith also focused on justice, an exact duty that follows from the details of the contract. But what if the contract has gaps? Smith described an additional norm of generosity, which is motivationally close to justice. Where Hume had asserted that it was not irrational to save one’s finger instead of sacrificing the finger in order to save the world,Footnote 21 Smith famously argued that such a trade would be so ungenerous as to be practically impossible. One does not, of course, have a well-defined contract to save the world; one acts as if one did.Footnote 22 Giving alms to the poor is not a just act for either Hume or Smith, but for Smith it is a generous one. In Wealth of Nations such poor people support themselves only by the beneficence of the well-disposed and generous.

If justice and thus contracts have gaps—contracts are incomplete—which are closed by generosity, then there is no reason to believe that a proposal to amend justice to include a generous act would involve “constructive rationalism.” Instead, the discussion would entail the suggestion that what has evolved as a generous act be made into a just act. With incomplete contracts that follow from the gaps in justice there may well be Pareto improvements in the reformulation of justice to encompass more generous acts.

With this distinction between justice and generosity in mind, we can now show how Smith’s generosity relates to Buchanan’s beach example developed in response to Hayek. Buchanan’s response relies on his long-standing doctrine (Buchanan 1959) that the role of the economist is to employ his knowledge to suggest Pareto-improving reforms.Footnote 23

Hayek properly stresses than many institutions that have emerged without conscious design are, nonetheless, efficient in the sense defined. But he fails to note that they must be subjected to the same tests as those which are to be classified as inefficient. There are surely many elements in the legal structure that may be provisionally classified as inefficient in the Pareto sense. For these, explicit and deliberately designed proposals for reform can be, and should be, advanced by those whose competence offers them an understanding of the principle of spontaneous coordination. Framework proposals for change can be, and should be ‘constructed’ and then presented for possible approval or disapproval by the members of the relevant public, the participants in the interaction. The economist can, and should, suggest the enactment of a rule, a law, that would impose fines on persons who litter the beach, a rule that is deliberately constructed for the attaining of an end result, the cleanliness of the beach. Buchanan (1977, p. 104)

Suppose we have a two sector economic model. There is a purely private household economy in which all decisions are made by parents who instruct their children about how to behave. The private households have customary rights to lunch on a beach. There are two goods. A view of the beach while lunching, and leisure. The production technology is simple. People lunch on the beach and enjoy the view. A canned lunch is provided by Heaven but, consistent with Hume’s view of the matter, the junior Deity who creates lunches forgets to make the cans self-destruct. The view deteriorates as the cans accumulate. Picking up cans costs leisure.

With Buchanan, we start with a position of commons and we observe that many people do not pick up after themselves. Why not? All the leisure cost is borne by them, the deterioration of the view is borne by others. Unfortunately, not only did the junior Deity fail to create ecologically sensitive cans, He also failed to produce an economist who might suggest Pareto improvements.

Suppose we apply Smithian machinery to the problem. There evolves a moral judgment that children ought to pick up their own room as well as not to leave their jeans on the household commons. The spectator projects what is observed in the household to what is observed in the commons and forms a judgment about what is observed. The people who do not pick up their cans on the beach are judged to be “pigs.” The generous behavior of picking up not only one’s own cans but also the cans of others brings applause. This motivates a suggestion for change.

Here we jump to Mill. As Mill suggests, we cannot change the laws of production.Footnote 24 The decay of cans is fixed; the tradeoff between cans and leisure is fixed. Prayer has proven ineffective. What to do? We think about changes in distribution by changing the assignment of rights in the community.Footnote 25 Who gets to enjoy the view; who has to give up leisure to pick up the cans?

It is not clear that Buchanan’s fines would be chosen. Perhaps only an economist watching the situation from the outside would see this neat solution. If the community were divided between adherents of Mill’s philosophy and those advocating the doctrine of his one-time friend and long-time debating partner, Thomas Carlyle, perhaps they might agree that the “gospel of labor” fallen into disuse with the abolition of slavery, could be brought back into service on an egalitarian basis. Householders could be randomly chosen to toil on the beach.

How this might fall out, each proposed system of rights, each possible system of justice, would have consequences, including production consequences, that need to be considered and discussed. And of course, as Mill wrote in his Principles, there is no reason to believe that the consequences of the change in distributional rights would be understood when it was effected.Footnote 26 The point, however, is that discussion may indeed bring about institutional change that makes the community better off.

5 “Degeneration”

Despite Hayek’s position outlined above, that law lies outside the scope of discussion, debate or reform, the final volume of Law, Legislation and Liberty reads as if there is nothing worthy of respect in existing institutions.Footnote 27 Hayek’s writing here could hardly be described as “panglossian.” (Whitman 1998) “Progress” has reversed and he worried about the end of civilization itself:

What I have been trying to sketch in these volumes (and the separate study of the role of money in a free society) has been a guide out of the process of degeneration of the existing form of government, and to construct an intellectual emergency equipment which will be available when we have no choice but to replace the tottering structure by some better edifice rather than resort in despair to some sort of dictatorial regime. (1979, p. 152)

To solve this government failure we need government, and government presupposes design.

Government is of necessity the product of intellectual design. If we can give it a shape in which it provides a beneficial framework for the free growth of society, without giving to any one power to control this growth in the particular, we may well hope to see the growth of civilization continue. (1979, p. 152).

The closing paragraph of Law, Legislation and Liberty brings us back to the “Abuse of Reason” project in which the quarrel with Mill began:

We ought to have learnt enough to avoid destroying our civilization by smothering the spontaneous process of the interaction of the individuals by placing its direction in the hands of any authority. But to avoid this we must shed the illusion that we can deliberately ‘create the future of mankind’, as the characteristic hubris of a socialist sociologist has recently expressed it. This is the final conclusion of the forty years which I have now devoted to the study of these problems since I became aware of the process of the Abuse and Decline of Reason which has continued throughout that period. (1979, p. 152).

Society needs to begin discussion of a new institutional design. On what basis shall the discussion proceed? Mill’s answer would be the perceived happiness of individuals. This of course is precluded by Hayek.Footnote 28 And although Hayek is an unabashed adherent of Karl Popper’s “piecemeal social engineering” when one worries about dictatorship, in this case of degeneracy it is not clear that mere “tinkering” suffices.Footnote 29

If we renounce utilitarian guidance, how might we proceed? Here is how the argument might be reconstructed using the machinery of Smith and Mill. From time t = 1 to T − 1 morals and institutions evolved together in such a way that institutions are judged to be “good.” At T, something happened to the institutions to cause them to degenerate, but morals continue as before. Thus, at T + 1 the institutions are judged “bad.” This judgment offers the imperative for a discussion of reform. To get out of evolution failures, we require social direction by discussion. This seems consistent with Hayek’s position that “grown law requires correction by legislation.”Footnote 30

The problem of uniqueness returns. If there are multiple evolutionary norms—there is justice and generosity at each moment in time—then at each moment in time acts might be judged as “bad.” Just acts could be disapproved of for being insufficiently generous or generous acts could be criticized for being unjust. We have returned once again to discussion and Mill. When Hayek argues that to fix “degeneration” or an evolutionary “impasse” we need institutional discussion and design, he has in fact come quite close to Mill. Having allowed that undirected evolution might be judged a failure, Hayek now opens the way for discussion.

6 Conclusion

From careless to careful commons, from generosity to justice, all via discussion. This is the means by which the polity evolves for Mill and Buchanan and, nearer the end of his career, for Hayek. It takes what was vague and generous and makes that precise and just. And the political reform is by means of the sort of free political discussion defended by Mill in On Liberty. People observe various actions, form judgments about them, and lament with others when they see the acts too rarely. What a free community might do is start somewhere, take a chance and see what happens. And then talk again. It need not wait until a dictator appears to begin the discussion.