The Quest for ‘Decolonised’ Knowledge

One of the core demands of the #FeesMustFall student protest movement in South Africa over the last 2 years (2015–2016) has been for ‘decolonised’ education. This concern is not unique to (South) Africa and expresses a global concern about ‘colonial’ knowledge. For example, the Center of Study and Investigation for Decolonial Dialogue from Barcelona (Spain) explains its decolonising effort as follows: ‘A basic assumption of the project takes knowledge-making, since the European Renaissance, as a fundamental aspect of coloniality—the process of domination and exploitation of the Capitalist/Patriarchal/Imperial Western Metropolis over the rest of the world’. This coloniality ‘denies the epistemic diversity of the world and pretends to be mono-epistemic’. The Western tradition of thought ‘is the hegemonic perspective within the world system with the epistemic privilege to define for the rest of the world, as part of an imperial universal design, concepts such as democracy, human rights, economy, feminism, politics, history, etc. Non-WesternFootnote 1 traditions of thought are concomitantly inferiorized and subalternized. … There is no modernity without coloniality’.Footnote 2

The same sentiments are expressed in the very interesting paper by Achille Mbembe, titled ‘Decolonising knowledge and the question of the archive’.Footnote 3 He asks the question what a Eurocentric canon is and then responds: ‘A Eurocentric canon is a canon that attributes truth only to the Western way of knowledge production. It is a canon that disregards other knowledge traditions’ (Mbembe 2015, p. 9). He proceeds: ‘The problem—because there is a problem indeed—with this tradition is that has become hegemonic’ (Mbembe 2015, p. 10).

Mbembe concludes that the decolonising project has two sides: A critique of the dominant Western models of knowledge and the development of alternative models. ‘This is where a lot remains to be done’ (Mbembe 2015, p. 18).

Indeed, a lot remains to be done. One could summarise the concerns of knowledge decolonisation as follows: Western knowledge traditions have become the norm for all knowledge; the methodologies underlying these traditions are seen as the only forms of true knowledge, which has led to a reduction in epistemic diversity; because of the institutional and epistemic power that Western traditions hold, they constitute the centre of knowledge so that other forms of knowledge are suppressed and are seen as inferior—a situation described as ‘coloniality’. Decolonisation has specific relevance to Africa, as this continent finds itself in a post-colonial era, but its knowledge and university curricula still reflect the dominance of Western knowledge forms.

This essay speaks to some of the salient issues raised in the decolonisation of knowledge debate via the case study of an African (business) ethic. The focus is therefore not on the material content of African ethics as such, but to use key aspects of attempts to construct an African ethics as illustration of the cultural and epistemological claims underlying coloniality. The concern of centre-periphery power asymmetry so eloquently expressed by decolonisation academics will be confirmed. As Mbembe intimates, this is the easy part. The constructive effort to build an alternative is the difficult task. This essay therefore embarks on a discussion of different ways in which one can talk about ‘African’ ethics, taking the ubuntu debates as main example of the potential and constraints of such an ‘African’ ethic. The paper ends with a short evaluation of whether ubuntu ethics holds potential to rescue African intellectuals from coloniality.

As a precursor to the discussion, it is important to raise the concern that to talk about ‘African’ ethics rests on the questionable assumption that it is indeed possible to speak about ‘an African’ approach abstracted from the complex histories, cultures and geographies of Africa.Footnote 4 This is a familiar paradox where one attempts to build a model based on generalisations while knowing that such generalisations are distortions of the particularities from which they are abstracted. Where these generalisations are mostly filtered through the lenses of colonial and post-colonial views, the task for abstracting an ‘indigenous’ or ‘traditional’ African view becomes even more complex.

It would therefore technically be more appropriate to speak of African knowledges or ethics or value traditions in the plural form. This is, however, rarely done, as we have grown accustomed to explaining particular complexities with a singular and a universal approach. Models gain their explanatory value exactly from such generalisations, and this essay therefore ventures to speak about ‘African ethics’ in the singular, though concerns about the empirical validity of the very general value claims made in the name of ‘sub-Saharan African people’ will be raised below.

Advocates for decolonisation are right that by adding the adjective ‘African’ (or Chinese,Footnote 5 or Japanese)Footnote 6 to ethics, the marginal intellectual and geo-ethical position of Africa may be reinforced. In the ‘centre’ there is (an assumed) ‘universal’ ethics derived from the dominance of Western philosophy, which is taken as the norm and point of reference, but rarely described as ‘Western’.Footnote 7 And on the margins are the adjective ethics with curiosity value and an overt contextuality.Footnote 8

The reality facing a scholar from Africa (or other marginal sites) is that there is no way to escape the already well-developed traditions in ethics with the accompanying technical terms and canonical/classical texts. This is in fact the very way in which African-based scholars are introduced to ‘ethics’. There is no tabula rasa or Archimedes starting point ‘in Africa’ from where one can subsequently approach the established canons of ethics built over a 2,400-year reflective, written tradition in the West.

The intellectual journey to Africa always starts in Europe: An African scholar travels an arduous intellectual journey to first understand the rich and complex traditions of ‘ethics’. We learn the names of the great thinkers such as Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Schopenhauer, Marx and Nietzsche. We hear about the established models of ethics explained in terms such as virtue, deontology and utility. Once this tradition is understood, our hermeneutical lenses have already been shaped. So when we ‘return’ our gaze to Africa to reflect upon ‘traditional values’ or ‘indigenous knowledge systems’, the only categories and intellectual apparatus at our disposal are the Western ones. Whatever we seek and might find locally will have to be explained in English and in terms of the established academic tradition, otherwise it simply does not ‘make sense’ to outsiders. The local voice, if heard at all, will only be taken seriously if judged and legitimised in terms of the accepted standards already established. The homogenising power of academic globalisation renders ‘local’ ethics as an interesting variation on the normative tradition with which it is always compared.

Models of ‘African’ Business Ethics

Let us—for argument’s sake—accept this centre–periphery configuration as the reality of doing ethics, but take on the challenge to develop (business) ethics from an ‘African’ perspective. Three broad options for an ‘African’ business ethics emerge in ascending order of localisation: a direct transfer of Western ethics to Africa (transfer model); different attempts to translate Western ethics into the context of Africa (translation model); and the development of a uniquely African position via the so-called ubuntu principle (substantive model). The first two options are enumerated with minimal description, after which the potential of a substantive, alternative ubuntu ethics is explored in more depth.

The Transfer Model

In this model, Western ethics is taken as the norm and held up as the ideal approach to ethics. This dominant tradition is then read and simply transferred to the context of Africa. There is very little ‘translation’, no contextual adaptation and rarely any critical reception. This can happen with any standard Western textbook. When, for example, James Rachel’s fine collection, The right thing to do (1989), with its readings in moral philosophy drawn inter alia from Aquinas, Kant, Mill, Kant and Hobbes, is used as lecturing material in an African classroom, those names are simply held up by lecturers as ‘basic readings’ that everyone interested in moral philosophy should know.

The consequence is that the adjective ‘Africa’ in this case, if used at all, describes nothing more than a geographical reading location. Whether one reads Aristotle and Kant in Lagos, Cairo, Nairobi or Berlin, it makes no difference. This is the way in which most African students (like myself) are taught ethics and philosophy. We neither realise that we are introduced to a ‘Western’ tradition, nor that there are ‘Africans’ (such as Augustine and the Alexandrian School) who made significant contributions to this tradition. The question of an ‘African’ approach to ethics always comes later, if at all—and then it is impossible to jump over our own European shadows.

The Translation Model

There are at least three possible forms of translation that one may discern from a reading of business ethics literature. In each case, the normative position of Western ethics is accepted, but there is an interaction with the African context that goes further than a mere transfer of knowledge.

First, there is an elucidation of Western ethics from an African perspective. In this case, there is an (uneven) reciprocal relationFootnote 9 between Western ethics and African contexts: The Western insights are taken as basis from which to interpret local contexts with the consequence that these contexts themselves are made sense of, or are critically appraised, in terms of the accepted Western perspective with an illuminating effect on the Western idea itself.

In a paper ‘In defence of partisan justice: What can African business ethics learn from John Rawls?’ (Naudé 2007), the insight of structuring society behind a veil of ignorance with the least advantaged representative person as reference point is translated into the African context with specific implications for business ethics.

Second, a popular way to make a contextual, African contribution to ethics is the translation of local case studies into the frameworks of Western theories or ideas. One of the tasks to indigenise business school curricula is exactly by providing local case studies instead of dominant examples from the North.Footnote 10 Typical questions could be the following: What does the Walmart takeover or SAB Miller merger teach us about stakeholder theory? How can a utilitarian approach be used to argue for/against implementation of a minimum wage in South Africa? In what way does Islamic finance in Africa illustrate the potential of a deontological ethics?

A third way of translation occurs when context-specific African ethical problems are addressed with recourse to insights from the Western tradition. In this case, African ethics focuses on moral dilemmas that are particular to our context and seeks resolution of these questions by making use of Western theories. For example: Can corrupt business practices in Africa be explained by recourse to Kohlberg’s stages of moral formation?Footnote 11 How can extensive management–labour conflicts be resolved by using the creating shared value notion developed by Porter and Kramer (2011)?

It is clear that the translation model does achieve a significant gain over a mere transfer, but as an example of decolonising knowledge, its contribution is minimal, as it relies on the Western insights and theories for its construction. In other words: There are local languages with some interesting variations, but the language from which and into which the translation takes place is predominantly ‘English’ (as a metaphor for the Western traditions).

The Substantive Model: Ubuntu Ethics

In this model, Western ethics is taken as a valuable tradition, but there is an endeavour to develop a distinct ethics that could be called ‘African’. The claim is that ubuntu ethics constitutes an additional, competing and alternative theoretical framework to those received via the Western tradition, hence the calling of this model ‘substantive’.

There has been a considerable growth in the literature to design an ‘ubuntu ethics’ deriving from the African continent. This essay does not give a literature overview, but engages with some of the most important representatives in furthering the argument about the possibility of an African ethic. The most advanced analytical work in this field has over recent years been done by Thaddeus Metz, who, in a seminal essay ‘Toward an African moral theory’ (Metz 2007b), outlines at least six senses in which ubuntu is used. He comes to the conclusion that there is indeed an indigenous African ethics that expresses the communitarian approach of Africans in distinction to the individualism of Europe. This qualifies his work as a substantive approach to African ethics. According to him, this ubuntu ethic may be summarised in the following principle of right action: ‘An action is right just insofar as it promotes shared identity among people grounded on goodwill; an act is wrong to the extent that it fails to do so and tends to encourage the opposites of division and ill-will’ (Metz 2007b, p. 338; read also Metz 2012).

To assist in the advancement of this important debate, my contribution—framed in the quest for decolonised knowledge—is to argue that the ubuntu project is based on a number of questionable claims:

First, the claim is that ubuntu derives from a universal respect for being-through-the-other, but it will be shown that its origin and social setting are tribal kinship relations.

Second, the claim is that ubuntu is a uniquely African phenomenon, but it will be argued that the values associated with ubuntu are based on generalisations that are not empirically proven and, even if accepted, are prevalent in most pre-modern and small-scale communities.

Third, the claim is that ubuntu expresses African communitarian views in contrast to Western individualism and rationalism. It will be argued that personhood and autonomy are inherent in all societies, including those in Africa, and sociality or being-through-the-other is indeed integral to Western philosophy as well.

The classical academic discussion of what became known as the ubuntu idea derives from John Mbiti in his book African religions and philosophy (1969).Footnote 12 I will use this work as primary reference point to develop a critical assessment of ubuntu.

According to Mbiti (1969, p. 108–109), ‘[w]hatever happens to the individual happens to the whole group, and whatever happens to the whole group happens to the individual. The individual can only say: “I am, because we are; and since we are, therefore I am”. This is a cardinal point in the understanding of the African view of man’.

First Argument

One should carefully note that the quotation above is set in Mbiti’s discussion of ethnic groups, kinship, (extended) family life and the individual. Mbiti wishes to avoid the negative connotation of the word ‘tribe’ and prefers to speak of ‘people’ or ‘peoples’. He emphasises that African peoples are to be differentiated on a number of factors: language, geographical boundaries (however fluid), a common culture expressed via a history with particular national figures and common ancestors, as well as common customs. He further mentions that ‘each people has its own distinct social and political organisation’ with tribal chiefs, extended families and persons with special status. Each people also has its own religious system: ‘Traditional religions are not universal: they are tribal or national’ (Mbiti 1969, p. 4). It therefore warrants to speak of African religions in the plural (Mbiti 1969, p. 1), while ‘a person cannot be converted from one tribal religion to another’, just as it is impossible to change tribal membership that is based on birth (Mbiti 1969, p. 103–104).

When proceeding to discuss kinship, Mbiti points out that the ‘deep sense of kinship, with all it implies, has been one of the strongest forces in traditional African life’. He immediately explains: ‘Kinship is reckoned through blood and betrothal (engagement and marriage).Footnote 13 It is kinship which controls social relations between people in a given community: it governs marital customs and regulations, it determines the behaviour of one individual toward another’ (Mbiti 1969, p. 104, my emphasis). This kinship is extended to the living dead (ancestors) and even covers animals and non-living objects through the totemic system. For Mbiti ‘almost all the concepts connected with human relationship can be understood and interpreted through the kinship system. This is what largely governs the behaviour, thinking and whole life of the individual in the society of which he [sic] is a member’ (Mbiti 1969, p. 104, my emphasis).

Although Mbiti points out that cultural exchange occurs among African peoples and that ideas found in one people may be found in a different form in another people (Mbiti 1969, p. 103), his discussion of the ‘ubuntu’ idea is fundamentally situated within the social boundaries of a particular people.

One can obviously abstract the idea of ubuntu from its social embeddedness in a particular people and then develop a kind of universal goodwill idea with some moral force. This is what African (and other) ethicists do. But to claim that traditional Africans in general upheld a universal notion of ubuntu that includes ‘all others’Footnote 14 is simply not supported by Mbiti’s discussion or by empirical research.Footnote 15 If it is said that ‘I am, because we are’, the ‘we’ that shapes the ‘I’ has a particular ethnic and kinship character, and not a universal (‘I am through all others’) connotation.Footnote 16 Translated into current contexts, ubuntu could consequently mean that I use my power in society to benefit those who are ‘of my own’. I am a person through the ones close to me, and they benefit from my patronage to the exclusion of others who are not from my nation, tribe, family or political party. This tribal notion of ubuntu lies at the heart of factionalism in Africa.

Second Argument

It is claimed that ubuntu is a uniquely African phenomenon, but it will be argued that the values associated with it are not proven empirically and are prevalent in most pre-modern and small-scale communities.

Mbiti points out that he is discussing African philosophy in its ‘traditional’ sense: traditional religions, traditional beliefs, traditional attitudes and traditional philosophies. He is aware of ‘modern’ influences such as education, urbanisation and industrialisation ‘by which individuals become detached from their traditional environments’. He is also keenly aware of the global power of modernity: ‘The man [sic] of Africa must get up and dance, for better and for worse, on the arena or world drama. His image of himself and of the universe is disrupted and must make room for the changing ‘universal’ and not simply “tribal” man’ (Mbiti 1969, p. 216). Some Africans are less affected by the changes (rural and illiterate people), but even where outward change to a ‘modern’ life takes place, many still hold on to some traditional beliefs.

The first problem is that the list of values associated with ‘traditional’ African society and therefore seen as expressions of ubuntu is as varied as there are authors on the topic: empathy, care for others, dignity, harmony, inclusivity, respect, reciprocity, forgiveness, community orientation, and so forth. The consequence is ‘that Ubuntu comes to mean no more than what is good or virtuous’ in a very vague sense (West 2014, p. 49), without enough particularity to be of ethical use.Footnote 17

The second problem is that the claims made in academic literature about these purported ‘African’ values have thus far not been supported by credible and reliable empirical research. Almost all ubuntu writers make the general claim that Africans (at least traditional ones) are ‘communal’ (with the kind of value list as above), while Westerners are ‘individualistic’. Two prominent authors serve as example of this:

Ramose bases his argument of ubuntu as ‘the root of African philosophy’ on a fine etymological analysis of ubuntu. This linguistic base for ubuntu is prevalent among what Ramose calls ‘the Bantu-speaking people’ of Africa,Footnote 18 and it is on this analysis that he builds the philosophy and ethics of ubuntu. But nowhere does Ramose empirically verify the transition from a linguistic feature to a moral world.Footnote 19 He takes his cue for this linguistic analysis from Heidegger, but Heidegger does not make general claims about purported moral convictions held by ‘German-speaking people’ as derived from his existentialist philosophy or language ontology. In other words, ubuntu and its associated values—insofar as they are derived from a linguistic feature—are not entirely convincing.

Thaddeus Metz is at pains to state that his effort to build a theory of right action on the basis of ubuntu ‘is a constructive project not an empirical one’ (Metz 2007a, p. 333). This is a fair admission. But he then proceeds on the same page to say that he attempts to build a theory that is different from Western ones. The ‘evidence’ (his word) that he gathered for this ‘African’ claim is from reading books on moral beliefs of Africans, engaging in conferences on the theme, listening to his students from Africa, and speaking to colleagues (Metz 2007a, p. 333, footnotes 3 and 4). He then proceeds: ‘So far as I can tell,Footnote 20it is a fact that there are several judgments and practicesFootnote 21 that are spatio-temporally extensive in Africa, but not in the West’ (Metz 2007a, p. 333, my emphasis).

As Andrew West rightly points out, empirical claims (such as claiming as a fact that sub-Sahara Africans hold distinctive communal values) that are only based on personal experience, anecdotes and impressions are not ‘evidence’ in the academic sense of the word. Empirical claims must flow from valid questionnaires, administered to an acceptable proportion of participants via random sampling followed by credible statistical inferences. West discusses a number of empirical cross-cultural studies on the collectivism–individualism divide by authors such as Hofstede, Thomas and Bedixen, Bernstein, and others,Footnote 22 and he convincingly (West 2014, p. 53) demonstrates their inconclusive results:

The mixed results and methodological limitations of all these studies preclude any simple generalisations regarding the values of sub-Saharan Africans being justified. It is premature to conclude, on the basis of existing evidence, that sub-Saharan Africans … do or do not maintain the values of Ubuntu. At present, we can only conclude, that such generalisations are unjustified.

What happened in the ubuntu literature is that claims of ‘ubuntu values’ (as proliferated as they are) as ‘typical of sub-Saharan Africans’ (as diverse as they are) became part of the canon and were then transmitted via academic cross-references from author to author, creating the impression of an undeniable ‘fact’.

What is ‘African’ about a set of ubuntu values is that it is an abstraction developed mostly by Africa-based or African-associated scholars. In this sense it is an etic, elite reinterpretation of residues of what used to be ‘traditional African’, devoid of the social practices and everyday realities of Africans subject to political, social and economic brutalities in sub-Saharan Africa. In this guise, it may function in two ways: As a utopian vision of society, it may inspire and give (false?) hope, like a kind of empty clarion call. And as a ‘narrative of return’Footnote 23 it may provide Africans, subject to rapid modernisation and identity renegotiation,Footnote 24 some sense of anchorage in an idealised pre-colonial past.Footnote 25

But it fails as a project of decolonisation, because it ‘essentialises’ Africans (exactly what a colonial mind does) and as an elite abstraction it mirrors colonial power structures that exactly inhibit the move to release Africans from their oppression under coloniality.

The third problem relates specifically to the ‘uniqueness’Footnote 26 claim of ubuntu. I concur with the few ubuntu authors that point out that ubuntu is not uniqueFootnote 27 and actually expresses a universal senseFootnote 28 of humanity.

If we, for the moment, accept the value description of Mbiti’s ‘traditional’ African societies, the question arises whether what is termed ‘ubuntu’ is not in fact a description of most pre-modern, ‘traditional’ or ‘small-scale’ societies, irrespective of their geographical location? This question can be answered in the affirmative when one reads studies on personhood in ancient Egypt;Footnote 29 concepts of autonomy in early rabbinical societies,Footnote 30 the effect of monetisation on interpersonal relations in sixth-century BCE Greece,Footnote 31 the shifting concept of trust from ‘traditional’ to contemporary Chinese communities,Footnote 32 as well as descriptions of early faith communities in the New Testament with the values embedded in, for example, the body metaphor.Footnote 33

It is clear that in most ‘traditional’ societies a person is established as person when he/she is embedded in social relations and that there is an ontological reciprocity between individual and society. This applies to Europe as well where, for example, Ferdinand TönniesFootnote 34 makes a distinction between Gemeinschaft (community) based on affectual loyalty so typical of pre-modern relations (ubuntu-type communities) and Gesellschaft (society), which is marked by impersonal, functional relations, for example the rational agreements contained in commercial contracts prevalent in modern, industrial contexts.

The idea that ‘I am a person through other persons’ in a close-knit community of reciprocity is therefore not a uniquely African phenomenon. The only ‘uniquely African’ part is the depiction thereof via the concept of umuntu ngumuntu ngabantu.Footnote 35

Third Argument

Ubuntu expresses African communitarian views in contrast to Western individualism and rationalism. It will be argued that personhood and autonomy are inherent in all societies, including Africa, and sociality or being-through-the-other is indeed integral to Western philosophy as well.

The ‘Individualist’ Dimension of African Personhood

Let us turn to the complex notion of ‘making a person’ and the relation between an individual and the community in which he/she lives.

On the one hand, Mbiti argues what one would call a ‘communitarian’ perspective: ‘In traditional life, the individual does not and cannot exist alone except corporately. He owes his existence to other people … He is simply part of the whole. The community must therefore make, create or produce the individual; for the individual depends on the corporate group’ (Mbiti 1969, p. 108, my emphasis).

On the other hand, Mbiti holds on to what one could call an ‘individualist’ perspective: ‘Just as God made the first man, as God’s man, so now man himself makes the individual who becomes a corporate or social man’ (Mbiti 1969, p. 108, my emphasis). An example of this is polygamy, which must, according to Mbiti, ultimately be viewed in the context of enhancing immortality: The greater the number of offspring, the greater the opportunity to be reborn in the multitude of descendants and to be remembered by and through them. A man who enters into a polygamous marriage is ‘making’ both himself and the community. ‘Such a man has the attitude that “the more we are, the bigger I am”’ (Mbiti 1969, p. 142, emphasis original).

Mbiti also qualifies his references to corporate descriptions to ensure that the element of individuation is not lost: ‘Therefore, when we say in this book that such and such a society “believes” or “narrates” or “performs” such and such, we do not by any means imply that everybody in that society subscribes to that belief or performs that ritual … Individuals hold differences of opinion on various subjects’ (Mbiti 1969, p. 3, my emphasis)—a further testimony to the active presence of individuals and individuality in a given social context (though constrained by patriarchy and other social allocations of power).

This important dimension of ‘self-making’ or autopoiesis is lost in the crude contrast that African ethicists set up between ‘Western individualism’ and relational ‘African communalism’ (Comaroff and Comaroff 2002). In no society, neither Western nor African, can an individual create him- or herself ex nihilo or outside of social relations (Keller 2002, pp. 200–201) because the idea that a person can exist as an unmediated sociological reality is simply that—an abstraction, an idea (Comaroff and Comaroff 2002, p. 67).

Based on their careful anthropological studies in Africa, the Comaroffs make a number of important observations:

There is no generic view of the African conception of personhood. ‘There is no such thing’ (Comaroff and Comaroff 2002, p. 68). Personhood is indeed a social construction, and ‘the person’ is a dynamic negotiated entity, a constant work-in-progress that plays itself out in a social context that is at once highly communal and individuated (Comaroff and Comaroff 2002, p. 69, 72) and subject to the resistance of countervailing forces (Comaroff and Comaroff 2002, p. 76). The ‘foundational notion of being-as-becoming, of the sentient self as active agent in the world, was so taken for granted that it went largely unsaid’ (Comaroff and Comaroff 2002, p. 73).

The conclusion is clear:

Nowhere in Africa were ideas of individuality ever absent. Individualism, another creature entirely, might not have been at home here before the postcolonial age … But, each in its own way, African societies did, in times past, have a place for individuality, personal agency, property, privacy, biography, signature, and authored action upon the world … All of which ought to underscore, yet again, why crude contrasts between European and African selfhood make little sense … (Comaroff and Comaroff 2002, p. 78, original emphasis).

This notion of personhood is confirmed by African scholar Kwama Gyekye. According to him, the first post-colonial leaders in Africa (such as Senghor and Kenyatta) overemphasised the communitarian or communalist nature of traditional African societies to provide a basis for experiments in African socialism (Gyekye 2002, pp. 298–299). This communitarian conception, reinforced by African philosophers such as Ifeanyi Menkiti,Footnote 36 upholds the ontological primacy and independence of the community over against the individual with the implication that ‘the person is wholly constituted by social relationships’ (Gyekye 2002, p. 298, original emphasis). On the basis of moral agency (individuals are held responsible for their actions) and autonomy ‘that enables one to determine at least some of one’s own goals and to pursue them’ (Gyekye 2002, p. 306), Gyekye rejects as ‘misguided’ the simple contrast between African and Western notions of the person (2002, p. 303). Gyekye holds a restricted or moderate communitarian view (2002, p. 306), because ‘it cannot be persuasively argued that personhood is fully defined by the communal structure or social relationships’ (Gyekye 2002, p. 305, original emphasis).

The dynamic nature of African humanness (not humanism) implies for Mogobe Ramose, inter alia, that one’s humanity is confirmed by recognising the humanity of others. This in turn implies that human subjectivity is an essential part of ubuntu. ‘If this were no so, it would be senseless to base the affirmation of one’s humanness on the recognition of the same in other’ (Ramose 2002a, p. 644). The group is neither primary to nor does it supersede the individual. ‘The crucial point here is that motho is a never finished entity in the sense that the relational context reveals and conceals the potentialities of the individual’ (Ramose 2002a, p. 644).

This ‘individualist’ dimension of African personhood implied by ubuntu is mostly ignored by African ethicists. Although there is no interest in the individual solely as an ontological construct but always in a normative relation to others, it does not deny a focus in Africa on personal signature and relative autonomy.

Let us now turn our gaze in the other direction: Is it correct to assume that the Western tradition operates with a rational, autonomous and individualist notion of personhood and that it is therefore different from Africa, which purportedly upholds a ‘relational’ orientation?

An Expanded View on Western Notions of Personhood

One could start by pointing to the deep paradox in the very notion of an ‘autonomous individual’, because ‘a non-contextual autonomy—autonomy in and of the self, rather than in relation to another—does not exist’. The reason is that ‘autonomy always arises within a context, relative to those from which it claims its independence’ (Keller 2002, p. 194). There is always only, paradoxically speaking, a relational autonomy.

Acknowledging the context dependence of any claim to ‘autonomy’, Keller suggests that we need a social ontology wherein we recognise ‘the self always and only emergent from its matrix of relations—and therefore never strictly speaking autonomous, however free the agency of that emergence’ (Keller 2002, p. 199). This would hold true for the ‘thinking I’ suggested by Descartes as well as the Enlightened person who is an autonomous rational being according to Kant. Yes, we indeed find in Descartes and Kant powerful expressions of ‘the turn to the subject’ (see below), but to suggest that this subject is to be equated with a purely decontextualised self-referential individualism is to overlook the fundamental ambiguity of relational autonomy in principle.

Rene Descartes

It has become the custom by some African ethicists to build a contrast between cogito ergo sum (Western thinking) and the African umuntu ngumuntu ngabantu (Mbigi 2005, pp. 69–70). This interpretation is a misreading of Descartes, as it assumes that his view of the human person is fully expressed in the cogito ergo sum dictum. The confusion arises because Descartes’ epistemology is isolated from and simply conflated with this anthropology. African ethicists therefore make a category mistake by comparing Cartesian apples (how do I know?) with African pears (how do I relate to others?).

As is well known, Descartes’ aim was to establish an irrefutable basis for knowledge.Footnote 37 Via a process of methodical doubt he came to the conclusion that the only certainty is in fact doubting all existing knowledge. But to doubt means that I, the doubting individual, must exist. He wrote in his Meditations II: ‘So that after having reflected well and carefully examined all things, we must come to the definite conclusion that this proposition: I am, I exist, is necessarily true each time that I pronounce it, or that I mentally conceive it’ (Descartes 1952, p. 78).Footnote 38 Descartes’ further conclusion, after positing that thought is a vital attribute belonging to him, is that he is a real thing and really exists. ‘But what thing? I have answered: a thing which thinks’ (Descartes 1952, p. 79).Footnote 39

This summary of himself as ‘a thinking thing’ early in the Meditations reflects his search for an irrefutable basis for true knowledge, but does not exhaust his view of himself as a human person. As Descartes addressed the difficult question of sense perceptions such as feeling pain and hunger and thirst, he asserted that nature teaches him …

… that I am not only lodged in my body as a pilot in a vessel, but that I am very closely united to it, and so to speak so intermingled with it that I seem to compose with it one whole … For all these sensations of hunger, thirst, pain, etc. are in truth none other than certain confused modes of thought which are produced by the union and apparent intermingling of mind and body (Meditation VI, Descartes, 1952, p. 99).Footnote 40

In his last published work, Passions de l’ame (Passions of the soul) (1649), Descartes (as the title suggests) turned his attention to discuss the feelings and experiences that arise from the interaction between body and spirit. The six basic passions are wonder, love, hatred, desire, joy and sadness, which are seen as physiological phenomena to be studied from a natural scientific perspective to ensure that they are beneficial to humans because they are understood and controlled. The freedom of the human person lies in the ability to reflect on and steer the reciprocal interaction between mind and body, constituting the person as a ‘master of his experiences’ (see Perler 2002, p. 161).

While Descartes maintained his dualism as well as the primacy of the thinking soul, it would be inappropriate to reduce his richly developed view of the human person to a mere ‘thinking I’ and then build upon this reductionist basis a perception of ‘the Western tradition’.

Immanual Kant

It is, further, a misreading of Kant to claim that he was only promoting a self-confident, rational being who has the courage to seek knowledge with hisFootnote 41 own mind, without recourse to assistance from other people. Kant, in his essay ‘Was ist Aufklärung?’, indeed famously described the enlightened person in these terms,Footnote 42 and said that it is very difficult to escape from immaturity and to use our own mind, because the immature state (relying for knowledge and truth on the insights of tradition or others in authority) has become a natural part of who we are. But this essay and the epistemology contained in Critique of pure reason (Kant 1998) should always be read in conjunction with his ethics in the Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (Kant 1964).

In this latter work Kant explains that the free will that practises the categorical imperative is not merely subject to the law, but is so subject that it must be considered as also making the law for itself. This co-construction of the law with its sensitivity to all human beings as ends in themselves comes to pass because it is ‘in no way based on feelings, impulses, and inclinations, but only on the relation of rational beings to one another’ (Kant 1964, p. 102, my emphasis; see Keller 2002, p. 197).

Via his ethics, Kant herewith demonstrated the importance of relationality: not only does the imperative of treating people as ends and not merely as means points towards a striving precisely beyond ‘individualism’, but its very formulation depends on the relation of rational beings to one another in the kingdom of ends.

Karl Marx

It is, further, a selective reading and distortion to portray ‘the Western tradition’Footnote 43 as not being open to the purported ubuntu idea of being a person through others. In his famous theses on Feuerbach (1845, published 1888) Marx states unambiguously in the sixth thesis that Feuerbach dissolves the religious essence into the human essence. The problem is that Feuerbach presupposes ‘…an abstract—isolated—human being’ whereas ‘the human essence is no abstraction inherent in each single individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of the social relations’ (my emphasis).Footnote 44 This must be understood from Marx’s theory of social classes, steering him sociologically speaking towards an explanation of individuals from their embeddedness in material, historical social relations, exactly against strands of individualism that view the single, autonomous person as unit of social analysis.

The intention for constructing relational personhood by the philosophers referred to above is not to merely make an abstract ontological point about the human person, but to infuse a moral dimension into their philosophy. This is apparent from Descartes’ notion of moral perfection, Kant’s communal law-making, and Marx’s class struggle towards a more just society.

In their efforts to create an African ethic, most ubuntu scholars work with false generalisations of both Africa and the West, as well as with assumed dichotomies between them. This is a well-known rhetorical strategy: One creates space for one’s own view by building an exaggerated contrast position of the other. In terms of a decolonising project, it would, however, be a deep irony and a sign of a colonised hermeneutic if African ethicists call on a decontextualised and selective interpretation of Western philosophy to argue for their own uniqueness and contextuality.

With the discussions above as background, the question posed in the title of this paper may now be addressed with greater focus: Does ubuntu ethics save us from coloniality, and, if so, in what sense?

Does Ubuntu Ethics Provide an Escape from Coloniality?

The background to this paper is the debate whether one could steer between the ‘immovable rock’ of Afrocentric and ‘the bad place’ of Eurocentric knowledges (Cooper and Morell 2014, p. 2). On the assumption of an agreement that the current situation requires acts of ‘decolonisation’, a possible option is to enter into a process of decentring the West and replace it with Africa. In other words, Eurocentrism is replaced by Afro-centrism. Mbembe (with reference to Ngugi) explains decolonisation exactly as such a process of decentring. ‘It is about rejecting the assumption that the modern West is the central root of Africa’s consciousness and cultural heritage. It is about rejecting the notion that Africa is merely an extension of the West’ (Mbembe 2015, p. 16). A new centre should be created: ‘With Africa at the centre of things, not existing as an appendix or a satellite of other countries and literatures, things must be seen from the African perspective’ (Mbembe 2015, p. 17, my emphasis).

Apart from the question how this should happen in practice, it seems unethical to in the end mimic the coloniality from which we try to escape in creating a new power asymmetry where Africans exercise power over others.Footnote 45

A variation of this idea and a ‘softer’ version of Afro-centrism is the proposal for ‘Africa-centred knowledges’. This implies that ‘knowledge can become Africa-centred regardless of where they originate. But they do so only when they get entangled in African realities, lexicons and matrices and are shaped by these contexts’ (Cooper and Morell 2014, pp. 4–5). Africa is then not so much a new centre, but a legitimate context which is taken seriously in the pursuit of multiple knowledges in an intermediate space between the West and Africa.Footnote 46

It is fairly straightforward to see that the transfer model of business ethics (see “The Transfer Model” section) does not qualify to fit into either an African- or Africa-centred paradigm, and in fact prolongs a colonial mindset. Insofar as the three forms of the translation model (see “The Translation Model” section) are each in its own way a contextualising of Western knowledge in Africa, they do weaken the dominant Eurocentric or Western view and indeed provide a minimal level of recourse from coloniality. But because the assumption of Western theories remain, this effort at decolonisation only functions at the level of de- and re-contextualisation with minimal, if any, epistemological challenge to prevailing Western moral philosophies.

The question then remains: Do the efforts to build a substantive, alternative ubuntu ethics (as set out in 2.3 above) transcend decolonisation-as-contextualisation towards a genuine escape from epistemological coloniality? The critical exposition above already points to just how difficult it is to escape from coloniality:

The dominant languages expressing ubuntu ideas are colonial English and French, and the means of knowledge production and distribution are via mainline universities, conferences, journals and publishers. Even ubuntu requires the very infrastructure and means seen as oppressive colonial power structures. The reason is simple: Ubuntu scholars also wish to be taken seriously. And they know that ‘acceptance’ and ‘validation’ of ubuntu scholarship are still subject to the hegemony of the North. The rule is clear: so-called indigenous knowledge is only ‘knowledge’ once endorsed by the centre.

For ubuntu to be taken seriously as alternative rival ethical theory (see Metz above), it must be contrasted with dominant and standard Western traditions.Footnote 47 Its own particularity is premised upon that which it tries to undermine, escape or complement.Footnote 48 The post-colonial thinker is forever bound to the colony and the thought patterns underlying Western paradigms. The methods and interpretative categories are borrowed from the West. Ramose premises his linguistic analysis of ubuntu on Heraclitus’ view of motion (Ramose 2002a, p. 645) and Heidegger’s etymological discussion of aletheia (Ramose 2007, p. 354). And in his development of an African philosophy he uses standard Western categories such as epistemology, ontology, ethicsFootnote 49 and metaphysics. He, and others, cannot jump over the shadow of the European tradition.

Why is an Escape from Epistemic Coloniality So Difficult?

To understand why the task of epistemological liberation from Western models is so difficult and not particular to (business) ethics, two explanatory factors need to be taken into account:

First. Efforts at constructing an African ethic like ubuntu, is a theoretical task. It therefore represents second-order knowledge. This is to be distinguished from first-order or tacit knowledge.

Tacit knowledges—including moral knowledge—are assumed by people in their everyday lives and are expressed in many forms: stories, anecdotes, beliefs, customs, songs, feasts. All social contexts, not only ‘indigenous’ or ‘African’ ones, are rich with a multiplicity of moral knowledges. These moral knowledges imply cosmologies and sustain worldviews taken for granted, and their validity is not usually called into question. Life simply goes on.

But the moment it is asked: ‘What is scientific or (in this essay) ethical knowledge?’, a different epistemic realm with much stricter rules of validity comes into play. Not everything counts as ‘evidence’ and not anyone is a valid ‘source’. The modern Western tradition has, for now, definitively shaped the nature of what we call scientific, academic knowledge—including ethics and moral philosophy—and therefore dominates the content and paradigms of our theorising efforts.

The challenge, as was demonstrated in the ethics discussion above, is that the moment indigenous moral knowledge of ‘sub-Saharan bantu-speaking peoples’ is made into an object of study beyond its lived reality,Footnote 50 the shadow of the Western canon with its particular thought forms looms large. Look, for example, at this quotation from Hoppers and Richards (2011) who argue strongly for the epistemic deconstruction of Western science:

Whenever we look deeply at African society, or indeed most indigenous societies, the empirical fact that stares back at us is a reality of life lived differently, lives constituted around different metaphysics of economic, of law, of science, of healing … The problem before us is that the academy has not adopted to its natural context, or has resisted epistemologically, cosmologically and culturally—with immense ensuing cognitive injustice to boot! (2012, p. 10).

However, the construction of an ‘empirical fact’ and the description of indigenous cultures in etic, theoretical categories like ‘cosmology’, ‘metaphysics’, ‘epistemology’, and so forth (including ‘ethics’!) are clearly inferred from the Western academic tradition and constitute acts of colonisation and epistemic injustice—the exact opposite of what the authors intended.

The second factor that complicates an escape from paradigmatic or theoretical coloniality has to do with the global nature of ‘Western’ science:

What is described as ‘modern scientific thinking’ is indeed a fairly recent phenomenon in human history. If we take David Wootton’s magisterial history of the scientific revolution as reference point (Wootton 2015), this ‘new science’ only finds its foothold in the period between 1492 and 1750. It introduced a new understanding of knowledge with a new language in which terms such as ‘discovery’, ‘hypotheses’, ‘experiments’, ‘theories’ and ‘laws’ of nature assumed a new meaning. Decolonisers are therefore right that this kind of knowledge is relative to the longer preceding history of knowledges; it is further relative to current indigenous knowledges as well as to the specific geography in which it first emerged, namely Western Europe. This particular scientific way of thinking therefore in principle qualifies for the description of a ‘local’ knowledge.

However, this ‘locality’ has in the meantime been ‘universalised’ in at least two ways:

First, the successful translation of Western scientific knowledge into all sorts of technologies has and will continue to shape the global world. Science constitutes the inescapable basis of our everyday lives, no matter our location. If some decolonisers call for the suspension of well-established knowledges that underlie the many positive fruits of these valid knowledges (such as flying in an aeroplane, using antiretroviral medicine, halting the spread of cholera and malaria, and talking on our mobile phones), they will not be taken seriously. Each of these technologies is the product of stable modern knowledges that are, for now, accepted as valid. Translated into technology their trusted and stable validity, as measured in scientific terms, is indeed useful to all people. We, inescapably, live in and benefit from a ‘scientific’ world, shaped by modernity and the Enlightenment.

Second, the idea that ‘science’ is a ‘local’ form of ‘Western’ knowledge has been superseded by both academic and economic globalisation. If one takes into account the spread of scientific knowledge in its ‘Western’ form across the globe via the international university system, and if one, for example, looks at manufactured products with a global supply chain, it has almost become superfluous to speak of ‘Western’ knowledge. At this point in human history, the matrix of knowledge as scientific knowledge knows no geographical boundaries and is being advanced by scientists and being bought in consumer goods all over the globe, including Africa.Footnote 51

The same globality holds for the development and advancement of ethical theories. Although ethics in the Western tradition pre-dates the Enlightenment, all theoretical models from Ancient Greek to late twentieth-century moral philosophers are now embedded in this global knowledge system that forms the inescapable matrix against which all ethical knowledge that claims to be valid, theoretical knowledge, is both framed and measured. That is why the good efforts at a substantive ubuntu ethics not only expresses itself via Western terminology, but as second-order knowledge also conforms to the validity standards of Western science—citing reliable and authoritative sources, making non-contradictory statements, building rational arguments, and so forth—against which decolonisation in its epistemic form exactly rebels.

Is There—In Principle—A Way Out?

Have we therefore reached a cul de sac in our efforts to overcome coloniality beyond contextualisation? I wish to argue to the contrary, on condition that a blind spot in the search for epistemic diversityFootnote 52 in the decolonisation project is avoided:

If decolonisation critique is against scientism or positivistic knowledge where empirical observation and repeatable experiments are seen as the only form of valid knowledge, decolonisers are in fact in good company. Philosophically this critique is well established in various forms of post-positivist thinking from Popper’s falsification and Kuhn’s paradigm theories to different strands of social constructivism. This is not a new idea.

The blind spot of some proponents of decolonisation in seeking greater room for other forms of knowledge than ‘scientific’ knowledge is that they focus chiefly on the natural sciences. They consequently miss the point that ‘knowledge’ in any modern university includes a rich variety of perspectives that do not conform to a narrow definition of experimental validity or the requirement of quantitative exactitude that works so well in mathematics, physics or engineering.

Western science itself has developed a rich diversity of epistemologies in fields of enquiry such as economics, history, philosophy, literature, psychology, theology, art, or what one could bundle together as the humanities and social sciences. Ethics and moral philosophy form an integral part of these knowledge forms, and they challenge the narrow empiricist scientific tradition. The key consequence is that this epistemic diversity beyond empiricism opens these disciplines up to embrace what has become known as ‘indigenous’ knowledgesFootnote 53: Historians recognise that oral histories are crucial for access to an oral past; local music and song are important sources of anthropological understanding; archaeological artefacts open doors on the lifestyle of past communities; traditional healers already assist in a richer definition of health, and—in the context of this essay—forms of tacit moral knowledge about personhood-in-community, expressed via ubuntu, have the potential to eventually disrupt and enhance our existing ethical theories and move from mere (de)-contextualisation to a transcendence of epistemic coloniality.

This disruptive and complementary potential is enhanced by the fact that the very nature of post-positivist knowledge invites falsification and paradigm revolutions. As African intellectuals we should exploit this inherent trait of Western knowledge and actively create space for dissenting views, especially those from the so-called margins.Footnote 54 This will undermine current privileges and weaken current academic power nestled in conferences, universities and journals. This will expose and deconstruct the social and epistemic violence accompanying the modern Western scientific tradition. Such dissent and critique are ‘rational’ things to do, as they increase the likelihood of growth in scientific knowledge as so eloquently described by Popper and Kuhn.Footnote 55 As Mbembe said (with reference to Enrique Dussel), for knowledge to be universal, it must also be pluriversal. We must therefore transform the university into a pluriversity (Mbembe 2015, p. 19)Footnote 56 by continuing to pursue decolonisation via ‘local’ knowledge forms, and by being more radical in our search for genuine alternative thought forms.

Conclusion

The conclusion of this essay is that the substantive effort to construct an alternative moral theory via ubuntu represents the strongest form of de- and re-contextualisation of Western knowledge if compared with transfer and translation models of business ethics and hence qualifies as a decolonised form of Africa-centred knowledge. In this limited sense, then, ubuntu does provide a decentring of Eurocentric views and consequently a tempering of coloniality.

But on the stronger claim of actual epistemic decolonisation, it is apparent that the ubuntu project—like all forms of theoretical-scientific knowledge—is invariably steeped in Western knowledge forms and rules of validation. From this perspective, and judged by the more fundamental epistemic demands of decolonisation, ubuntu is in fact a perpetuation and further reinforcement of a colonial mindset.

Because post-positivist, ‘Western’ scientific knowledge is by definition and in principle open to falsification, efforts at decolonisation of moral philosophy may yet yield ethical theories with superior problem-solving and alternative expressive abilities, leading to new knowledge paradigms. In light of the current state of African business ethics scholarship, and the fact that relieve cannot readily be expected from ‘Western’ ethicists, the prospect of success does not look good, unless we radically reconceptualise what is counted as moral ‘problems’, moral ‘solutions’ and—ultimately—moral ‘theory’.