Skip to main content

The Analytico-Dialectical Theory of Justice: A Sketch of an Action-Theoretical and Non-Cognitivist Theory of Justice

  • Chapter
An Institutional Theory of Law

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 3))

Abstract

In this chapter I should like to discuss some assumptions and to establish some theses which seem to me to characterise a specific conception of justice. I call this conception the ‘analytico-dialectical theory of justice’ or ‘dialectical theory of justice’ for short. The term ‘dialectical’ is here to be understood in a non-Hegelian sense, which will in due course be explained. The discussion is divided into the following ten sections:

  1. Section 1

    Theories of justice are concerned to provide objective criteria as to what is just (and thus as to how the concept of justice should be defined). They present these principles of justice either as formal criteria or as substantive criteria which are intuitively evident and a priori or as anthropological facts or as articles of religious faith. Utilitarian theories and Rawlsian contract theory also offer objective determinants of what is just and what is unjust. By contrast, legal positivism in its strong version says that it is only relative to some given system of positive norms that questions of justice can arise at all.

  2. Section 2

    Precepts of justice must be understood as justifying grounds of decision and action, that is, as elements of practical reasoning.

  3. Section 3

    My starting point is a non-cognitivist conception of practical reasoning. There is such a thing as practical thought and practical argumentation, but no such thing as practical cognition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 229.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 299.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 299.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes to Chapter VII

  1. What is intended here is, of course, the first formulation of the categorical imperative (“Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same time will that it should become a universal law”, I. Kant, Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Ethics, trans. by T. K. Abbot, 10th ed., London, 1962, p. 46), not the by no means equivalent second formulation (“So act as to treat humanity whether in thirie own person or in that of any other, in every case as an end withal, never as means only” (ibid., p. 56)). The second formulation is a substantive rule which postulates a teleological commitment of a kind which can only be valid given some prior moral commitment.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ch. Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (trans. by J. Petrie, London, 1963), p. 29 : “Formal justice has been defined as the principle of action according to which the persons who belong to one and the same essential category ought to be treated in the same way”.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. R. M. Hare, Freedom and Reason (Oxford, 1963).

    Google Scholar 

  4. R. M. Hare, The Language of Morals (Oxford, 1952), pp. 191ff;

    Google Scholar 

  5. R. M. Hare, Freedom and Reason, p. 90 et passim; Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method and Point (Oxford, 1981).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass., 1971); on the problem of this sort of fictitious consensus, see O. Weinberger, Die Rolle des Konsensus in der Wissenschaft’, Rechtstheorie (1981), Beiheft 2, pp. 147–165.

    Google Scholar 

  7. I have elsewhere rejected as illusory the purported justification of principles of justice through the ‘original position’ and the ‘hypothetical contract’. See O. Weinberger, ‘Begründung oder Illusion. Erkenntniskritische Gedanken zu John Rawls’ Theorie der Gerechtigkeit’, Zeitschrift für philosophische Forschung (1977), Bd. 31, Heft 2, pp. 195–216, republished in my Logische Analysen in der Jurisprudenz (Berlin, 1979), pp. 195–216.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Notwithstanding my critical attitude towards Rawls, I by no means undervalue the importance of his work, in particular his idea about the ‘veil of ignorance’, his reflections on ‘reflective equilibrium’ and his allusions to the importance of procedural justice.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. O. Weinbeger, ‘Rationales und irrationales Handeln’, in Recht und Gesellschaft: Festschrift für Helmut Schelsky zum 65. Geburtstag (ed. by F. Kaulbach and W. Krawietz, Berlin, 1978), pp. 721–44;

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf. O. Weinbeger, ‘Handeln und Schließen. Überlegung zum Begriff der Praktischen Inferenz’, in F. van Dun (ed), The Law between Morality and Politics, Philosophica 23 (1979), pp. 5–36;

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ch. Weinberger and O. Weinberger, Logik, Semantik, Hermeneutik (Munich, 1979), Chapter 8;

    Google Scholar 

  12. O. Weinberger, ‘Studien zur formalfinalistischen Handlungstheorie’, Beiträge zur Allgemeinen Rechts- und Staatslehre 5 (Berne and Frankfurt/Main, 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  13. The restriction of the principle of non-derivability to informative conclusions seems necessary for the following reason: analytically valid declarative propositions can be derived as conclusions from premises of either type. The same holds good for normative sentences which are devoid of information, such as, for example, an oughtsentence with the structure ‘If p ⋀p, then q ought to be’. For more details of my view on norm-logical inferences, see Ch. Weinberger and O. Weinberger, Logik, Semantik, Hermeneutik (Munich, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  14. J. Jørgensen, ‘Imperatives and Logic’, Erkenntnis 7 (1937–38), 288–96;

    Google Scholar 

  15. K., Engliš Die Lehre von der Denkordnung (Vienna, 1961) and Die Norm ist kein Urteil’, ARSP 50 (1964), 305–16;

    Google Scholar 

  16. H. Kelsen, Allgemeine Theorie der Normen (ed. by K. Ringhofer and R. Walter, Vienna, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cf. also O. Weinberger, Normentheorie als Grundlage der Jurisprudenz und Ethik. Eine Auseinandensetzung mit Hans Kelsens Theorie der Normen (Berlin, 1981); ‘Kelsens These von der Unanwendbarkeit logischer Regeln auf Normen’ [‘Kelsen’s Thesis as to the Nonderivability of Logical Rules from Norms’], in Die Reine Rechtslehre in wissenschaftlicher Diskussion (Vienna, 1982), pp. 108–21.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. on this and the next following point, Weinberger, ‘Rationales und irrationeles Handeln’.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cf. Ch. Weinberger and O. Weinberger ‘Teleonomie und formal Teleologie’, in Logik, Ethik und Sprache, Festschrift für Rudolf Freundlich (Vienna, 1981), pp. 108–21.

    Google Scholar 

  20. How exactly this is to be accomplished I cannot say.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. Rawls, Theory of Justice, pp. 38f, 68ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. O. Weinberger Wahrheit, Recht und Moral. Eine Analyse auf kommunikationstheoretischer Grundlage’, Rechtstheorie 1 (1970), 129–46.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Common goals are, for example, pursued by spouses in the rearing of their children or in safeguarding the economic basis of their household. Complementary goals are, for example, pursued by teacher and pupil or by opponents in a game. When people in their several roles are in competition with each other, the goals they pursue are often mutually opposed; yet for all that, both parties can aspire to playing their own role. Consider for instance the relationship between seller and buyer: with respect to the price, they have mutually opposed goals, yet they have each a similar interest in the trading relationship.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. on this point Kant’s idea of the highest good. For Kant, the interconnection of morality and happiness is an article of faith and of hope. To me, it seems more reasonable to champion an analogous postulate concerning just conduct, and to propose it as a goal for a just organisation of society. It is to be wished that just and moral conduct should at least have a certain probability of being more conducive to a prosperous way of life than evil-doing.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. O. Weinberger, Dialektik und philosophische Analyse’, in Logik der Sozialwissenschaften (ed. by E. Topitsch assisted by P. Payer, 10th edition, Cologne and Berlin, 1980), pp. 278–309.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1986 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Weinberger, O. (1986). The Analytico-Dialectical Theory of Justice: A Sketch of an Action-Theoretical and Non-Cognitivist Theory of Justice. In: An Institutional Theory of Law. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 3. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7727-4_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7727-4_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8419-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7727-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics