Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 40))

Abstract

Until recently, pragmatics — the study of language in relation to the users of language — has been the neglected member of the traditional three-part division of the study of signs: syntax, semantics, pragmatics. The problems of pragmatics have been treated informally by philosophers in the ordinary language tradition, and by some linguists, but logicians and philosophers of a formalistic frame of mind have generally ignored pragmatic problems, or else pushed them into semantics and syntax. My project in this paper is to carve out a subject matter that might plausibly be called pragmatics and which is in the tradition of recent work in formal semantics. The discussion will be programmatic. My aim is not to solve the problems I shall touch on, but to persuade you that the theory I sketch has promise. Although this paper gives an informal presentation, the subject can be developed in a relatively straightforward way as a formal pragmatics no less rigorous than present day logical syntax and semantics. The subject is worth developing, I think, first to provide a framework for treating some philosophical problems that cannot be adequately handled within traditional formal semantics, and second to clarify the relation between logic and formal semantics and the study of natural language.

The research for and preparation of this paper was supported by the National Science Foundation, grant number GS-2574. I would like to thank Professors David Shwayder and Richmond Thomason for their helpful comments on a draft of this paper.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Charles W. Morris, Foundations of the Theory of Signs, Chicago 1938, pp. 4–5.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Rudolf Carnap, Foundations of Logic and Mathematics, Chicago 1939, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Dana Scott, ‘Advice on Modal Logic’ in Philosophical Problems in Logic. Recent Developments (ed. by Karel Lambert), D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht 1970, pp. 143–173.

    Google Scholar 

  4. This is not an inevitable strategy. Instead of taking individuals and possible worlds as primitive, defining properties and relations as functions from one to the other, one might take individuals, properties and relations as primitive and define possible worlds in terms of these.

    Google Scholar 

  5. A theory of possible worlds and propositions defined in terms of them is not committed to any absolute notion of synonymy or analyticity. Since propositions are functions taking possible worlds as arguments, a domain of possible worlds must be specified as the domain of the function. But the domain need not be all possible worlds in any absolute or metaphysical sense. We may leave open the possibility that the domain may be extended as our imaginations develop, or as discoveries are made, or as our interests change. Propositional identity is, of course, relative to the specification of a domain of possible worlds.

    Google Scholar 

  6. This is not necessarily so, however. Since speech act types can be any way of picking out a class of particular speech acts, one might define one in such a way that the context was irrelevant, and the problem of analysis reduced to a problem of syntax or semantics, as for example the speech act of uttering a grammatical sentence of English, or the speech act of expressing the proposition X.

    Google Scholar 

  7. R. Montague, ‘Pragmatics’ in Contemporary PhilosophyLa philosophie contemporaine (ed. by R. Klibansky), La Nuova Italia Editrice, Florence 1968, Vol. I, pp. 102–122. Montague uses the phrase ‘point of reference’ as does Dana Scott in the paper mentioned in note 3.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Tenses and times, for example, are an interesting case. Does a tensed sentence determine a proposition which is sometimes true, sometimes false, or does it express different timeless propositions at different times? I doubt that a single general answer can be given, but I suspect that one’s philosophical views about time may be colored by his tendency to think in one of these ways or the other.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Bas C. van Fraassen, ‘Singular Terms, Truth Value Gaps, and Free Logic’, Journal of Philosophy 63 (1966) 481–495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. and van Fraassen, ‘Presupposition, Implication, and Self Reference’, Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968) 136–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Keith Donnellan, ‘Reference and Definite Descriptions’, Philosophical Review 75 (1966) 281–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. See R. Thomason and R. Stalnaker, ‘Modality and Reference’, Noûs 2 (1968) 359–372

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. and R. Stalnaker and R. Thomason, ‘Abstraction in First Order Modal Logic’, Theoria 34 (1968) 203–207.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See R. Stalnaker, ‘A Theory of Conditionals’ in Studies in Logical Theory (ed. by Nicholas Rescher), Oxford 1968, pp. 98–112 for a semantical theory of conditional propositions. Nuel Belnap has developed a theory of conditional assertion in ‘Conditional Assertion and Restricted Quantification’, Noûs 4 (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  15. J. O. Urmson, ‘Parenthetical Verbs’, Mind 61 (1952) 192–212.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1972 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Stalnaker, R.C. (1972). Pragmatics. In: Davidson, D., Harman, G. (eds) Semantics of Natural Language. Synthese Library, vol 40. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2557-7_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2557-7_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-0310-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-2557-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics