Keywords

These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

1 Introduction

The struggle to give legal form and content to ‘terrorism’ has preoccupied states, international organisations, and lawyers for more than 80 years, since the League of Nations first considered terrorism as a transnational legal problem.Footnote 1 Originally confronted within the framework of domestic extradition law, the powerful terminology of ‘terrorism’ soon took on an international life of its own, with calls for its more deliberate regulation. The subsequent great difficulties in defining terrorism are typically portrayed as an unfortunate failure of the international community to confront a virulent species of transnational crime.

In one sense, that dominant critique is understandable because the failure to reach agreement has hindered the highest possible level of international cooperation against terrorism. Countries cannot fully cooperate against ‘terrorism’ without knowing the scope of the phenomenon against which they would be required to impose legal sanctions. Some of the disagreement between states has stemmed from negotiating positions which have sought to confer unprincipled impunity on certain preferred political actors. Attempts to carve out exceptions for one’s own side of international politics have damaged inter-state confidence.

In a different sense, however, the failure to define terrorism can also been viewed as a kind of messy success. Some states have resisted efforts to define terrorism for more principled reasons – for instance, because defining terrorism in a certain way would jeopardize other international public policy interests such as political freedom, asylum, or human rights. That some states have held out against pressures to conform to particular definitional proposals is an achievement of sorts, for it has stalled the destructive slide towards overly-punitive responses to terrorism which has tempted many states. Having no definition of terrorism is better than having a definition which criminalises legitimate politics or dissolves freedoms. Meanwhile, practical cooperation against particular forms of terrorism has not only been possible but effective, through various means including transnational crime treaties.

Given the protracted and often acrimonious disagreements among states about defining terrorism, it surprised many to learn that the United Nations Special Tribunal for Lebanon identified a customary international crime of transnational terrorism in February 2011.Footnote 2 By recognising a definition of terrorism in customary law, the Special Tribunal neatly side-stepped almost a century of legal deadlocks in (ongoing) treaty negotiations and debates in bodies such as the UN General Assembly and Security Council. The first part of this chapter assesses whether there is now an accepted definition of terrorism in general international law. Concluding that there is no such consensus, the second part of the chapter examines the relative advantages and costs of defining terrorism in particular ways.

2 Is There a Definition of Terrorism in International Law?

The definition of terrorism identified by the UN Special Tribunal for Lebanon is a useful starting point for considering whether there is a general definition in international law. The Special Tribunal identified a customary law crime of terrorism consisting of three elements:

(i) the perpetration of a criminal act (such as murder, kidnapping, hostage-taking, arson, and so on), or threatening such an act; (ii) the intent to spread fear among the population (which would generally entail the creation of public danger) or directly or indirectly coerce a national or international authority to take some action, or to refrain from taking it; (iii) when the act involves a transnational element.Footnote 3

The requirement of a transnational elementFootnote 4 rules out purely domestic terrorism. While the Tribunal recognised only peace-time terrorism as a crime, it indicated that ‘a broader norm that would outlaw terrorist acts during times of armed conflict may also be emerging’.Footnote 5

State practice does not, however, support the conclusion reached by the Tribunal. A close analysis of relevant treaties, United Nations resolutions, national laws and national judicial decisionsFootnote 6 confirms the near-universal scholarly consensus that there does not yet exist a customary law crime of terrorism as defined by the Tribunal.

As regards treaties, a decisive point is that numerous efforts by the international community since the 1920s have not produced agreement on a general international crime of terrorism in a treaty.Footnote 7 While there are numerous ‘sector’-specific treaties which address particular criminal means or methods used by terrorists,Footnote 8 none of those treaties – individually or collectively – contains a comprehensive definition of terrorismFootnote 9 or establishes a general international crime of transnational ‘terrorism’. At most, specific offences in some treaties may have entered into customary law, such as aircraft hijacking or hostage taking.Footnote 10

In the absence of a general crime of terrorism in treaty law, no parallel customary rule can arise out of those treaties. The sectoral approach was adopted precisely because states could not reach agreement on ‘terrorism’ as such. The decades of deadlock – continuing in the negotiations for a UN Draft Comprehensive Terrorism Convention since 2000 – demonstrate a lack of global consensus on defining terrorism. Even the 1999 Terrorist Financing Convention – sometimes pointed to as a generic definition of terrorism – only defines and criminalises terrorist financing, not terrorism per se, and there is no wider practice suggesting that states have extrapolated wider general crimes of terrorism from its definition.

The treaties of regional organisations also do not support the existence of an agreed definition of terrorism. An accurate reading of those conventions establishes exactly the opposite: enormous variation in regional conceptions of terrorism.Footnote 11 Some regional treaties focus on specific terrorist methods, without defining terrorismFootnote 12; others contain (often wide or conflicting) generic definitions,Footnote 13 or define terrorism only to criminalize ancillary conductFootnote 14; and yet others do not create offences at all, but serve other purposes (such as extradition or law enforcement cooperation).Footnote 15 Some of the treaties do not enjoy wide participation by members of the regional organisation,Footnote 16 and even where states are parties, the treaty may not have influenced national practice much at all.Footnote 17

The General Assembly resolutions have repeatedly condemned terrorism as ‘[c]riminal acts intended or calculated to provoke a state of terror in the general public, a group of persons or particular persons for political purposes’.Footnote 18 The value of such resolutions as evidence of a customary law agreement on the definition of terrorism must be cautiously appraised. The key normative resolution which sets out a definition, the 1994 Declaration on Measures against International Terrorism, itself emphasizes the need to progressively develop and codify the law on terrorismFootnote 19 – far from reflecting existing rules. In supporting it, many States argued that there was still a need to define terrorism and/or to adopt a comprehensive treaty criminalizing it,Footnote 20 and to distinguish self-determination strugglesFootnote 21 – including the 118 States of the Non-Aligned Movement and 56 OIC states.Footnote 22 At most the Declaration reflects a political agreement on the wrongfulness of terrorism which falls short of evidencing a customary definition of terrorism, particularly against a background of continuing, inconclusive UN treaty negotiations on a definition since 2000.

Moreover, the Declaration’s definition of terrorism (requiring a political purpose) is, in any case, different to that in the UN Draft Comprehensive Convention (which does not require a political motive). It is different again from the definition in Security Council resolution 1566 (which is limited to underlying sectoral offences, and does not catch all forms of terrorism). It is also different from the definitions in the 1999 Terrorist Financing Convention, where the emphasis is on intimidating a population or coercing a government, for whatever purpose. As shown below, it is also different from those many different definitions in national laws and, as shown above, in regional treaties. All of this suggests that the legal definition of terrorism, and such criminal liability as may attach to it, remains deeply contested.

National laws also do not evidence a customary law definition of terrorism.Footnote 23 Not all countries have even defined or criminalised terrorism generally in their legal systems, and still prosecute terrorism as ordinary crime or deal with it according to pre-existing legal categories (such as general security or emergency laws). Some countries thus resist the idea that the factual phenomenon of terrorism should be legally conceptualised as ‘terrorism’.

While there are now a great many national laws giving legal life to ‘terrorism’, the picture is highly fragmented and variable. First, some national laws address domestic terrorism, others concern international terrorism, and some states deal with both. The many national laws which address domestic terrorism are irrelevant in evidencing a customary international crime of transnational terrorism (which the UN Special Tribunal claims exists).

Secondly, countries sometimes deploy different definitions of terrorism for different legal purposes (whether in criminal law, civil or administrative law), further fracturing any consensus on a core definition across most legal systems. More particularly, only national criminal law definitions of terrorism can usefully evidence any customary international law criminal definition of terrorism.

Thirdly, where national laws do define terrorism (for whatever purpose), they reveal fundamental disagreements between states as to what legally constitutes terrorism.Footnote 24 Examination of state reports to the UN’s Counter-Terrorism Committee clearly evidences such wide variations in approach.Footnote 25

Fourthly, even where national laws converge on the definition of terrorism, they may be inappropriate models for an international definition. Various national definitions have been criticised for violating international human rights law, such as by being too vague to satisfy the principle of legality and freedom from retroactive criminal punishment.Footnote 26 Such unlawful acts are not accompanied by opinio juris to the effect that rights-violating definitions are permissible or required under international law: they remain simply unlawful.

While certain national judicial decisions have also been invoked to support the existence of a customary definition of terrorism,Footnote 27 analysis of national decisions does not sustain such a claim. At worst, some national decisions expressly doubt the customary law status of terrorismFootnote 28; do not concern terrorism at allFootnote 29; mention terrorism incidentally but not dispositivelyFootnote 30; or refrain from ruling on the issue.Footnote 31 At most, some national decisions accept that certain forms of terrorism may have attracted international consensusFootnote 32 (for instance, hijacking or hostage taking), but that falls short of support for the existence of a comprehensive, universal definition of terrorism per se.

In those few cases which mention customary law, the methodology of analysing custom formation is minimal to say the least and ‘rest[s] upon a very inadequate use of the sources’.Footnote 33 The position on customary law is ambiguous in a few cases. One matter was a civil case and did not involve criminal liability,Footnote 34 while others concerned national law contexts such as extraditionFootnote 35 or exclusion from refugee status.Footnote 36 One decision identifies ‘the essence’ of terrorism for the limited purpose of interpreting a domestic immigration law statute, but acknowledges that ‘there is no single definition that is accepted internationally’ and that ‘[o]ne searches in vain for an authoritative definition’.Footnote 37

While one Italian decision appears to squarely identify a customary crime of terrorism,Footnote 38 it then defines such crime quite differently from the notion suggested by the UN Special Tribunal – specifically, by requiring a political, religious or ideological motivation. This is not a trivial or marginal difference of opinion. On the view of the Italian court, terrorism is simply not terrorism unless it is defined to include such a motive. Indeed one of the central disagreements in defining terrorism in national and international law is whether a publicly-oriented motive should be an element of the definition.Footnote 39

Such divergence amongst national laws has not been cured by the UN Security Council’s edict in Resolution 1373 (2001) requiring states to criminalise terrorism.Footnote 40 That resolution failed to define terrorism, and in practice the Security Council’s Counter-Terrorism Committee tolerated a wide variety of national approaches to defining terrorism. The Council’s subsequent ‘working definition’ of terrorism in Resolution 1566 (2004) does not require States to conform their anti-terrorism laws to it. Nonetheless, that resolution is understood by States as establishing ‘soft’ guide-posts in the implementation of earlier Resolution 1373. Over time, sufficient State practice in conformity with the resolution – that is, an actual common national law approach to defining terrorism – may provide evidence of a customary law definition. There is, however, a long way to go.

Any emerging global consensus around the definition in Resolution 1566 would reflect a fairly narrow and rights-respecting concept of terrorism, and would not be a bad result. The cumulative elements set out in that resolution define conduct as terrorism only: (a) when it is committed to harm people, (b) with the purpose to provoke a state of terror, or to intimidate a population, or to compel a government or an international organization, and (c) and where such conduct also constitutes an offence under the existing sectoral anti-terrorism treaties.

In other words, Resolution 1566 does not criminalize any conduct which is not already criminal under existing transnational crime treaties; rather, it reclassifies as ‘terrorism’ certain existing criminal wrongs where they are designed to terrorize, intimidate or compel. There is no further ‘special intent’ or motive requirement of a political, religious or ideological purpose behind the conduct. The relatively narrow scope of that definition complements efforts by the UN human rights bodies and mechanismsFootnote 41 to identify and wind-back excessive national anti-terrorism laws which adversely affect human rights.

3 Defining Terrorism to Civilize Legal Exceptionalism

If terrorism is not presently defined under general international law, the twin questions arise whether it is worth the effort, and what kind of definition is worth the effort. As briefly noted earlier, numerous ‘sectoral’ treaties on transnational criminal cooperation, adopted since the 1960s, targeted the common methods of violence used by terrorists (such as hijacking, hostage taking, endangering maritime facilities and so on), but did not create or define a new international crime of terrorism.Footnote 42 Such treaties typically required States parties to criminalise certain conduct, to establish extraterritorial jurisdiction over it, and to cooperate by prosecuting or extraditing suspected offenders.

This pragmatic approach enabled the repression of terrorism while side-stepping the irreconcilable problem of defining it, at a time when States were unable to agree on the legitimacy of violence committed by self-determination movements or by State forces. The result has been a functional transnational cooperation against terrorism, even if there remain regulatory gaps because of the reactive, ad hoc nature of treaty making (for example, terrorist attacks by small arms, as in Mumbai in 2008, are not prohibited by treaty law).

Despite the wide range of terrorist conduct criminalised by the sectoral treaties and the law of armed conduct, the international community has continued to feel compelled to pursue a more general international anti-terrorism treaty framework. Since 2000, efforts have been underway to negotiate a Comprehensive Anti-Terrorism Convention under the auspices of the United Nations. Draft article 2(1) proposes an offence if a person ‘unlawfully and intentionally’ causes: ‘[d]eath or serious bodily injury to any person’; ‘[s]erious damage to public or private property’; or ‘[d]amage to property, places, facilities, or systems… resulting or likely to result in major economic loss’.Footnote 43 The purpose of any such conduct, ‘by its nature or context’, must be ‘to intimidate a population, or to compel a Government or an international organization to do or abstain from doing any act’.Footnote 44 Possible exceptions to the Draft Convention remain contentious, particularly as regards violence by non-State groups and State military forces.

The ongoing effort to define a general international crime of terrorism suggests that the international community places some importance on that effort. At a normative level, defining terrorism as a distinct category of legal harm also symbolically expresses the international community’s desire to condemn and stigmatize ‘terrorism’, as such, beyond its ordinary physical or criminal characteristics. Doing so normatively recognizes and protects certain international community values, and sets legal limits on the acceptable means and methods of political action. At a practical level, the patchy regulation of terrorism in many domestic legal systems can give rise to impunity, as a result of jurisdictional lacunae, differences in the definition of offences, gaps the coverage of the sectoral treaties, and limits on the extradition of political offenders. International agreement on defining terrorism and cooperative measures to deal with it is capable of narrowing those gaps. It would also bring greater precision and certainty in the definition of terrorist offences pursuant to UN Security Council measures, and thus strengthen the rule of law in responding to terrorism.

In the practice of the international community over many decades, concentrated through the United Nations organs and regional organizations, broad consensus has emerged that transnational terrorism is internationally wrongful because it: (1) seriously threatens or destroys basic human rights and freedom; (2) jeopardizes the state and the stability of political life; and (3) threatens international peace and security.Footnote 45 While those explanations are not entirely coherent or without criticism,Footnote 46 the collective identification of what is wrongful about terrorism aids in explaining both why it is insufficient to leave its regulation to domestic law alone, and how terrorism can be best defined to reflect the underlying international interests and protected values at stake.

This in turn raises important questions about who is entitled to use violence and for what purposes. Depending on the scope of the definition of terrorism and the acceptability of any exceptions to it, the criminalisation of terrorism risks empowering the State – including autocratic ones – at the expense of other (potentially legitimate) political claims to the use of violence. Terrorism may often jeopardize the human rights of civilians; but if terrorism is defined more widely as any violence against the State, then the criminalisation of terrorism itself strips away the human freedom to resist oppressive or authoritarian regimes. Criminalising terrorism may serve to safeguard the stability of the State and its political order; but those political orders which systematically violate human rights may warrant destabilisation and subversion. Protecting democracy from terrorism is one thing, but protecting all States is different matter – hence the understandable political difficulty of reaching international agreement on an acceptable universal definition of terrorism.

One important means of legally distinguishing terrorism is by reference to the motivation of offenders. A compelling reason for including a motive element in an international or domestic definition of terrorist offences is that it helps to differentiate terrorism from other kinds of serious violence which may also generate fear (such as common assault, armed robbery, rape, or murder), while also according with commonplace public understanding of what constitutes terrorism. The core premise is that political violence, or violence done for some other public-oriented reason (such as religion, ideology, or race/ethnicity) is conceptually and morally different than violence perpetrated for private ends (such as profit, greed, jealousy, animosity, hatred, revenge, personal or family disputes and so on).

As such, international law should recognise this distinction in defining terrorism, so as to more accurately express what is considered by the international and national communities to be distinctively wrongful about terrorism. This distinction does not necessarily imply that terrorism is always morally worse than organised crime (a mafia hit may cause as much fear as a terrorist act), but it does suggest that it is morally different, not least because it aims to disrupt and coerce peaceful political processes through violence.

Until recently, the international community’s legal response to terrorism did not focus on motive. From the early 1960s, the ‘sectoral’ anti-terrorism treaties avoided any general definition of terrorism, including reference to motive. Instead, most of the treaties require States to prohibit and punish in domestic law certain physical or objective acts—such as hijacking, hostage taking, misuse of nuclear material, or bombings—regardless of whether such acts are motivated by private or political ends. Proof of the motive(s) behind the act (as distinct from the intention to commit the act) is not required as an element of the offences.Footnote 47

At best, some of the treaties define their offences by inclusion of special intent requirements, but which fall short of requiring a political or other motive as such. For instance, the 1999 Terrorist Financing Convention prohibits the financing of certain acts where their purpose ‘is to intimidate a population or to compel a government… to do or abstain from doing any act’.Footnote 48 While this definition partly signals a focus on repressing public-oriented violence – by targeting acts directed at the community or a government– it still does not accurately capture what is most wrongful about terrorism.Footnote 49 For it is still possible to intimidate a population or compel a government for a host of private, non-political reasons, including simple extortion.

As a result of their failure to include motive elements, many of the existing anti-terrorism treaties reach considerably beyond common understandings of terrorism, since violence for public and private motives alike is equally criminalized. Thus hostage taking or hijacking for profit or to obtain custody of a child in a family dispute is treated no differently than identical acts committed in pursuit of a political cause. The lack of differentiation arguably fails to capture what it distinctively wrongful about terrorism, which is not inherent in a physical act of violence alone.Footnote 50 As Levitt writes:

Not all hijackings, sabotages, attacks on diplomats, or even hostage-takings are ‘terrorist’; such acts may be done for personal or pecuniary reasons or simply out of insanity. The international instruments that address these acts are thus ‘overbroad’…Footnote 51

Overreach undermines ‘the moral and political force of these instruments as a counter-terrorism measure’Footnote 52 and dilutes the special character of terrorism as a crime against non-violent politics and social life. As Habermas suggests, terrorism ‘differs from a private incident in that it deserves public interest and requires a different kind of analysis than murder out of jealousy’.Footnote 53 Prosecuting an individual for politically motivated ‘terrorism’, rather than for common crimes like murder or sectoral offences like hijacking, may help satisfy public indignation at terrorist acts, better express community condemnation, and placate popular (but reasonable) demands for justice.

In international practice, there is increasing support for the view that terrorism is political or other publicly motivated violence, which is distinguishable, and should be distinguished, from private violence. In its influential and widely supported 1994 Declaration mentioned earlier, the UN General Assembly distinguished terrorism from other violence because of its motivation ‘for political purposes’.Footnote 54 In the European Union’s 2002 Framework Decision on Combating Terrorism,Footnote 55 terrorism is considered a distinctive form of violence precisely because ‘the motivation of the offender is different’.Footnote 56

The definitions of terrorism in Britain, Canada, Australia, New Zealand and South Africa similarly reflect a political judgment by those democratic communities that the motives of terrorists set them apart from other criminals. According to the Australian Parliamentary Joint Committee on Intelligence and Security in 2006, ‘terrorism is qualitatively different from other types of serious crime’ and is perceived as so distinct by the public.Footnote 57 For Australia’s Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Commission, the aim of terrorists to undermine the political system and institutions ‘makes the differentiation between “terrorist” and “non-terrorist” offences meaningful’.Footnote 58 As the Canadian government suggests, removing the motive element would thus make terrorism offences indistinguishable from the general law.Footnote 59 In a review of British terrorism laws in 1996, Lord Lloyd of Berwick observed that labelling what would otherwise be ordinary crime as terrorism reflects that terrorism attacks society and democratic institutions.Footnote 60

At the same time, the international community has equally recognised the distinctiveness of non-political crime. For instance, the oldest international crime, piracy, is defined as violence on the high seas for ‘private ends’, indicating that core notion of piracy as common robbery which takes place beyond the reach of national criminal law enforcement. More recently, the 2000 UN Convention against Transnational Organized Crime defines transnational organised crime as serious crime that is motivated by ‘financial or other material benefit’,Footnote 61 with indications during the drafting that proposals for an international treaty definition of terrorism should take into account what is already covered by this Convention.Footnote 62

In sum, the expressive function of international law cannot be overstated; a conviction for political or religious violence sends a symbolic message that ­certain kinds of violence, as such, cannot be tolerated against states, which are duty bound to ensure the safety of their peoples and to legitimately suppress those who wish to influence politics, and interfere in the autonomy of others in peaceful societies, by resorting to violence. Here international law has a role in reinforcing the ethical values of democratic political communities, which are constructed on a shared commitment to peaceful deliberation and participatory dialogue – rather than using the unilateral force of arms against one’s fellow citizens or the ­community at large.

4 The Elements of Definition

It is possible to sketch the contours of a rational definition of terrorism based on the policy reasons for definition revealed in state practice and discussed above, to reflect existing agreement on the wrongfulness of terrorism. To fully reflect the consensus on what is wrong with terrorism, each of the elements outlined below is necessarily conjunctive, thus increasing the specificity of terrorist offences.

First, if terrorism is thought to seriously violate human rights, a definition must contain elements reflecting this judgment. In particular, if terrorism infringes the right to life and security of person, a definition should prohibit serious violence intended to cause death or serious bodily injury to a person. The prohibition should also extend to attacks on public or private property where intended or likely to physically endanger people, including acts against essential utilities and public infrastructure.Footnote 63

To increase certainty, the element of ‘serious violence’ could be qualified by enumerating prohibited violent acts, such as by listing the offences in existing sectoral terrorism treaties, and specifying additional acts not covered by those treaties (such as murder or physical assault by any means and in any context). At the same time, the element of ‘serious violence’ could remain as an open-ended ‘catch-all’ category to ensure that offenders do not evade liability by perpetrating violence by new or unanticipated methods.

Certainty could also be increased by qualifying ‘serious violence’ as that which is already ‘criminal’ under international or national law, thus excluding violence which is lawfully justified or excused by legal defences. The seriousness of criminal violence could remain a matter of appreciation in individual cases, just as ‘serious non-political crime’ in exclusion cases under international refugee law is interpreted by reference to comparative national law. This approach may, however, be challengeable for lack of specificity under human rights law and a definition may be more predictable if it particularizes all prohibited physical acts.

Secondly, there are a number of possibilities for framing a definitional element to reflect the normative consensus that terrorism undermines the State and the political process. A narrow approach would be to criminalize only violence directed at State officials, institutions, or interests. This approach would fail to cover acts directed at individuals, groups or populations unconnected to State interests and would thus omit to address a significant proportion of acts commonly understood as terrorism.

To meet this problem, a number of recent international definitions of terrorism have supported protecting both the State and the broader population, by requiring that the purpose of an act, ‘by its nature or context’, must be ‘to intimidate a population, or to compel a government or an international organization to do or to abstain from doing any act’.Footnote 64 One difficulty is that mere intimidation of a population, or compulsion of a government, seems to fall short of the severe impact implied by the term ‘terrorism’.Footnote 65 This problem is arguably cured by the European Union’s solution of requiring an aim to seriously intimidate a population or unduly compel a government or international organization.Footnote 66 Alternatively, New Zealand modifies this approach by replacing the ‘intimidation’ of a population with a graver intention ‘to induce terror in a civilian population’.Footnote 67

The language of ‘terrorism’ itself implies that the intention to inflict terror, as opposed to mere intimidation, ought to be required. There has been considerable support for including such an element in an international definition of ­terrorism, commonly formulated in proposals as either an intention ‘to create a state of terror’,Footnote 68 or ‘to provoke a state of terror’,Footnote 69 in particular persons, groups of persons, or the general public. The serious social stigma which attaches to labelling an offender a ‘terrorist’ should be reserved only for those people who cause the grave psychological harm which is signified by the term terrorism. That label should not be deployed too easily to describe violent offenders who generate other harms.

Still, it remains the case that intimidation of a population or compulsion of a government may be motivated by private concerns such as blackmail, extortion, criminal profit or even personal disputes. Consequently, if a definition of terrorism is to reflect the real nature of the harm that terrorism inflicts on the political process, it must differentiate publicly-oriented violence from private violence. As mentioned earlier, a terrorist act is committed not only where there it has a political purpose,Footnote 70 but wherever there is a public motive, aim, objective or purpose broadly defined: political, ideological, religious, ethnic or philosophical. The presence of a public motive distinguishes terrorism from private violence which also intimidates a population or compels governments.

Thirdly, if terrorism is thought to threaten international peace or security, an international definition must be limited to acts capable of that result—for instance, because of its cross-border or multi-national preparation or effects, the involvement of State authorities, or injury to other vital international community values or interests. This need not preclude a definition from covering domestic terrorism, where such conduct is thought to injure international values of sufficient gravity and attract international concern.

Historically, the weight of international opinion has only supported the definition and criminalization of international terrorism. The offences in the sectoral anti-terrorism treaties adopted since 1963 typically do not apply to purely domestic terrorism.Footnote 71 The most recent sectoral treaties have followed a common formula, building on that in the 1979 Hostages Convention. The 1997 Terrorist Bombings Convention, the 1999 Terrorist Financing Convention and the 2005 Nuclear Terrorism Convention all do not apply where an offence is committed in a single State, the offender and victims are nationals of that State, the offender is found in the State’s territory and no other State has jurisdiction under those treaties.Footnote 72 Article 3 of the UN Draft Comprehensive Convention follows the same formula and is a reasonable approach.

Accordingly, based on the international community’s identification of the underlying wrongfulness of international terrorism, terrorism can be deductively defined as follows:

  1. 1.

    Any serious, violent, criminal act intended to cause death or serious bodily injury, or to endanger life, including by acts against property;

  2. 2.

    Committed for a political, ideological, religious or ethnic purpose; and

  3. 3.

    Where intended to:

    1. (a)

      Create extreme fear in [or seriously intimidate] a person, group, or the general public; or

    2. (b)

      Unduly compel a government or an international organization to do or to abstain from doing any act.

The cumulative elements of this definition ensure that the stigma of the terrorist label is reserved for only the most serious kinds of unjustifiable political violence. Its limited application also prevents the symbolic power of the term from being diluted or eroded.

5 Exceptions to Definition: Democratic Protests, Armed Conflicts

The question remains whether any exceptions to the general definition should be recognised by international law. Agreement on exceptions to any definition of terrorism has proved more difficult than agreement on the definition itself. In particular, two controversies have plagued the debate: whether national liberation or self-determination movements should be exempt, and whether State violence causing terror should be covered. The wider the definition of terrorism, the more likely a broader range of exceptions or defences should be available. If international law is to avoid criminalizing legitimate violent resistance to political oppression, agreement on the lawful boundaries of political violence is an essential first step before agreement on definition can be properly reached. The variety of possible exceptions and defences to, and justifications and excuses for, terrorism under international law has been considered fully elsewhere.Footnote 73

In the first place, it is justified to include an exception acts of advocacy, protest, dissent or industrial action which are not intended to cause death, serious bodily harm, or serious risk to public health or safety – as exists already in some national laws.Footnote 74 Such exclusions are useful devices to prevent criminalizing as ‘terrorism’ comparatively minor harm (limited to property damage), such as when protestors at a union demonstration smashed the foyer of the Australian Parliament House in 1996; when anti-Iraq war protesters painted ‘No War’ on the shell of the Sydney Opera House in 2003 (requiring expensive repairs)Footnote 75; or when urban rioters cause extensive property damage, as at G8 anti-globalization protests, or in the Paris suburbs in late 2005. While such destruction to property may exceed the limits of freedom of expression and amount to public order offences, they should fall short of being labelled as terrorism. This is particularly important in the construction of an international crime of terrorism, since States that are not democratic or generally rights-respecting are far less likely to exercise prosecutorial restraint in selecting appropriate criminal charges.

Secondly, violence committed in the context of an armed conflict (international or non-international) should be excluded from a general definition of terrorism, and instead dealt with under the specialised regime of international humanitarian law (IHL). In armed conflict, where ‘terrorists’ commit unlawful violence under IHL or international criminal law, they may be prosecuted for war crimes or crimes against humanity, either in national courts or (where available) in international tribunals. Most terrorist-type conduct committed in connection with an armed conflict is already criminalized as war crimes,Footnote 76 including as a special war crime of spreading terror amongst a civilian population.Footnote 77 Where terrorism is not connected the conflict, it could be prosecuted under general terrorism offences.

Lawful violent acts committed by State or non-State forces should be excluded from the scope of any general international crime of terrorism, to prevent such a crime interfering in the carefully constructed parameters of permissible violence in IHL. IHL is also the appropriate legal framework for dealing with self-determination conflicts, and for internal rebellions rising to an armed conflict. Those who target military objectives in accordance with the laws of war would thus not be liable to prosecution as international ‘terrorists’.

By contrast, if non-State parties to an armed conflict find themselves branded and delegitimized internationally as criminal terrorist groups, the incentive to comply with IHL by those groups evaporates. For it then makes sense to such groups to fight as dirtily and for as long as possible to avoid defeat, since defeat and capture brings severe criminal penalties rather than amnesties, demobilization and social reintegration. The brutal last months of the internal armed conflict in Sri Lanka is a telling case, where international legitimation of the government’s cause in rooting out Tamil Tiger (LTTE) ‘terrorists’ encouraged an escalation of government violence into systematic war crimes or crimes against humanity; while the LTTE used civilian hostages as human shields and executed civilians attempting to flee.Footnote 78

In contrast, if non-State groups are not criminalized as terrorists, but treated as belligerents in an armed conflict, there is greater reason to comply with humanitarian principles, both to enhance the group’s own legitimacy and to stake a claim to more dignified treatment as belligerents upon capture. Of course, there may be some extreme organisations which are not, and will never be, interested in playing by any rules; but the broad definitions of terrorism currently in play sweep up many more organisations than only the most extreme or asocial.

Where terrorism is committed in peace-time (or in situations not covered by IHL), in order to maintain moral symmetryFootnote 79 and broaden its legitimacy, a definition should cover acts of both State officials and non-State actors. Thus extrajudicial assassinations of political opponents by State officials,Footnote 80 or collusion in such killings,Footnote 81 might gainfully be qualified as terrorism, as might suicide bombings by non-State actors outside armed conflict. As Primoratz argues, acts which exhibit the ‘the same morally relevant traits’ should be similarly morally understood.Footnote 82

In other cases not covered by any of the forgoing exceptions—such as in internal rebellions beneath an armed conflict—the international community may still regard some terrorist-type violence as ‘illegal but justifiable’. In such cases, consideration might be given to excusing such conduct, and mitigating penalties for it, where it was committed in the ‘collective defence of human rights’. Concrete examples might include the assassination of a military dictator, or politicians who forcibly refuse to cede power following defeat in a democratic election. Political amnesties and pardons, as well as ordinary criminal law defences, may also play a role in more sensitively responding to particular instances of terrorism in context.

6 Conclusion

The application of international law to terrorism rapidly developed in the 10 year period from 2001–2011, and certainly more rapidly than in the previous 70 odd years. Security Council law-making, sanctions regimes, national law reform and transnational legal borrowing, judicial decisions, and ‘soft law’ standard-setting by a range of bodies have all increasingly shaped international counter-terrorism practice. Despite these rapid developments, there remains basic conceptual confusion about defining the problem of terrorism which is subject to such deepening regulation. No doubt certain effective measures can be taken to counter-terrorism even whilst the concept remains ambiguous. But quite apart from considerations of effectiveness, there are other costs which should properly concern the international community. Ambiguity of legal concepts allows both states to unilaterally shape their counter-terrorism responses in ways which undermine human rights and other international social interests and values; and terrorists too can take advantage of the gaps.