Skip to main content

The Product Guides the Process: Discovering Disease Mechanisms

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Building Theories

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 41))

Abstract

The nature of the product to be discovered guides the reasoning to discover it. Biologists and medical researchers often search for mechanisms. The “new mechanistic philosophy of science” provides resources about the nature of biological mechanisms that aid the discovery of mechanisms. Here, we apply these resources to the discovery of mechanisms in medicine. A new diagrammatic representation of a disease mechanism chain indicates both what is known and, most significantly, what is not known at a given time, thereby guiding the researcher and collaborators in discovery. Mechanisms of genetic diseases provide the examples.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Abrahamsen, A. A., & Bechtel, W. (2015). Diagrams as tools for scientific reasoning. Review of Psychology and Philosophy, 6, 117–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abrahamsen, A., Benjamin, S., & William, B. (2017). Explaining visually: Mechanism diagrams. In S. Glennan & P. Illari (Eds.), The routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy (pp. 238–254).  New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, H. (2012). Mechanisms: What are they evidence for in evidence-based medicine? Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice, 18(5), 992–999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arp, R., Smith, B., & Spear, A. D. (2015). Building ontologies with basic formal ontology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. In C. F. Craver & L. Darden (Eds.), Special issue: Mechanisms in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences (vol. 36, pp. 421–441).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. A. (2013). Thinking dynamically about biological mechanisms: Networks of coupled oscillators. Foundations of Science, 18, 707–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1993). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2008). Physical law and mechanistic explanation in the Hodgkin and Huxley model of the action potential. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 1022–1033.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F., & Darden, L. (2013). In search of mechanisms: Discoveries across the life sciences. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2002). Strategies for discovering mechanisms: Schema instantiation, modular subassembly, forward/backward chaining. Philosophy of Science, 69(Proceedings), S354–S365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries: Mechanisms, interfield relations, and anomaly resolution. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2013). Mechanisms versus causes in biology and medicine. In H. K. Chao, S. T. Chen, & R. L. Millstein (Eds.), Mechanism and causality in biology and economics (pp. 19–34). The Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2002). Strategies in the interfield discovery of the mechanism of protein synthesis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33, 1–28. Reprinted with corrections in Darden (2006, Chap. 3).

    Google Scholar 

  • de Lange, K. M., et al. (2017). Genome-wide association study implicates immune activation of multiple integrin genes in inflammatory bowel disease. Nature Genetics, 49, 256–261. https://doi.org/10.1038/ng.3760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gebharter, A., & Kaiser, M. I. (2014). Causal graphs and biological mechanisms. In M. I. Kaiser, O. R. Scholz, D. Plenge, & A. Hüttemann (Eds.), Explanation in the special sciences (Vol. 367, pp. 55–85). Dordrecht: Synthese Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gene Ontology Consortium. (2015). The gene ontology consortium: Going forward. Nucleic Acids Research, 43(database issue), D1049–D1056.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S., & Illari, P. (Eds.). (2017). Routledge handbook of mechanisms and mechanical philosophy. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorlatova, N., Chao, K., Pal, L. R., Araj, R. H., Galkin, A., Turko, I., et al. (2011). Protein characterization of a candidate mechanism SNP for Crohn’s disease: The macrophage stimulating protein R689C substitution. PLOS ONE (open access). http://dx.doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0027269.

  • Howick, J. (2011). Exposing the vanities—And a qualified defense—Of mechanistic reasoning in health care decision making. Philosophy of Science, 78, 926–940.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jin, L., Xiao-Yu, Z., Wei-Yang, S., Xiao-Lei, Z., Man-Qiong, Y., Li-Zhen, H., et al. (2014). Pathway-based analysis tools for complex diseases: A review. Genomics, Proteomics & Bioinformatics, 12(5), 210–220. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gpb.2014.10.002.

  • Kanehisa, M., Furumichi, M., Tanabe, M., Sata, Y., & Norishima, K. (2017). KEGG: New perspectives on genomes, pathways, diseases and drugs. Nucleic Acids Research, 45(D1), D353–D361. https://doi.org/10.1093/nar/gkw1092.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser, M. I. (2016). On the limits of causal modeling: Spatially-structured complex biological phenomena. Philosophy of Science, 83(5), 921–933.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Li, G. M. (2008). Mechanisms and functions of DNA mismatch repair. Cell Research, 18, 85–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindee, S., & Mueller, R. (2011). Is cystic fibrosis genetic medicine’s canary? Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, 54(3), 316–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plutynski, A. (2013). Cancer and the goals of integration. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 4, 466–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plutynski, A. (forthcoming). Explaining Cancer: Finding Order in Disorder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russo, F., & Williamson, J. (2007). Interpreting causality in the health sciences. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 21(2), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheredos, B., Burston, D., Abrahamsen, A., & Bechtel, W. (2013). Why do biologists use so many diagrams? Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 931–944.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2015). Making medical knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1998). Explaining disease: Causes, correlations, and mechanisms. Minds and Machines, 8, 61–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1999). How scientists explain disease. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2003). Pathways to biomedical discovery. Philosophy of Science, 70, 235–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2016). On the incompatibility of dynamical biological mechanisms and causal graphs. Philosophy of Science, 83(5), 959–971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. (2013). Understanding as representation manipulability. Synthese, 190, 997–1016. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-0055-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

LD thanks Emiliano Ippoliti and his colleagues at Sapienza University in Rome for the invitation to the Building Theories Workshop, and to them and all the participants for lively discussions of discovery heuristics. For helpful suggestions on earlier drafts, she thanks Carl Craver, Giamila Fantuzzi, Nancy Hall, and an anonymous reviewer, as well as Kal Kalewold and the other students in her graduate seminar on mechanisms and ontology. This work was supported in part by NIH (US National Institutes of Health) grants R01GM102810 and R01GM104436 to JM.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lindley Darden .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Darden, L., Pal, L.R., Kundu, K., Moult, J. (2018). The Product Guides the Process: Discovering Disease Mechanisms. In: Danks, D., Ippoliti, E. (eds) Building Theories. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 41. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72787-5_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics