Skip to main content

Why Things Can Hold Rights: Reconceptualizing the Legal Person

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Legal Personhood: Animals, Artificial Intelligence and the Unborn

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 119))

Abstract

The chapter argues that the traditional theories of legal personhood, which associate legal personhood with the holding of rights, are outdated and should be reassessed. Many modern theories of rights come into conflict with our convictions regarding who or what is a legal person. For instance, most jurists would agree that foetuses are not natural persons but new-born children are. However, if we apply the so-called interest theory of rights, we will note that foetuses hold various rights, such as rights against certain forms of abortion. If right-holding entails legal personality, then foetuses are already legal persons. On the other hand, if we apply the will theory, which associates right-holding with the power to control others’ duties, then infants do not hold any rights at all – and are consequently not legal persons.

This is why the chapter outlines an alternative theory of legal personhood. The main tenets of the theory are: (1) legal personality is not binary but rather a matter of degree, and (2) X’s legal personality involves primarily the endowment of X with incidents of legal personhood, much like ownership can be understood as consisting of separate but interconnected incidents. Rather than being a “solved” theoretical issue, the definition of legal personhood should occupy theorists more in the future.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    There are some other formulations of this view as well. I will return to them later.

  2. 2.

    People ex rel. Nonhuman Rights Project, Inc. v. Lavery, No. 518336, 2014 WL 680276 (N.Y. App. Div. Dec. 4, 2014).

  3. 3.

    See also Bartosz Brożek’s article in this volume.

  4. 4.

    Animals were only mentioned as things.

  5. 5.

    The trifurcation is mentioned in Institutes which is the third part of Corpus Iuris Civilis. See (Birks et al. 1987).

  6. 6.

    Doneau was not the first humanist jurist; he was preceded by Franciscus Connanus, who would start systematizing Roman law in a critical manner (Stein 1998, p. 122–123).

  7. 7.

    Der Mensch wird, in so fern er gewisse Rechte in der bürgerlichen Gesellschaft genießt, eine Person genannt. Allgemeines Landrecht für die Preußischen Staaten (01.06.1794), Part I, Chap. 1, Sect. 1. See also (Hattenhauer 2011, p. 52–56).

  8. 8.

    South Africa – a mixed jurisdiction – is an exception among Anglophone countries in that even jurists writing in English do use the phrases “legal subject” and “legal object” synonymously with respectively “person” and “thing”. See (Heaton 2015).

  9. 9.

    For the influence of German, and especially Savigny’s, legal scholarship on English and American jurists, see (Hoeflich 1989); (Riesenfeld 1989); (Reimann 1989) and (Herget and Wallace 1986). Lars Björne has discussed the influence of Savigny’s personhood theory on Scandinavian legal scholarship (Björne 1998, p. 349–365).

  10. 10.

    That Salmond was familiar with Savigny’s work can be seen at 347 f.

  11. 11.

    For the rights theories of the nineteenth century, see (Simmonds 1998).

  12. 12.

    There may be some counterexamples, such as dead creatures whose livers have been removed, but I take the point to be clear.

  13. 13.

    “‘Natural person’ is the term used to refer to human beings’ legal status” (Berg 2007, p. 373).

  14. 14.

    Die Rechtsfähigkeit des Menschen beginnt mit der Vollendung der Geburt. Bürgerliches Gesetzbuch, § 1.

  15. 15.

    Jeder Mensch hat angeborne, schon durch die Vernunft einleuchtende Rechte, und ist daher als eine Person zu betrachten. Austrian Civil Code (Allgemeines bürgerliches Gesetzbuch), § 16.

  16. 16.

    The condition is explicitly recognised in the German Civil Code, as was noted above, as well as in Part 1, Section 1 of the Italian Civil Code. In Spanish law, the neonate must live for at least 24 h outside of the womb in order to be deemed a legal person (de las Heras Ballell 2010, p. 34). Regarding French law, see for example (Malaurie 1999, p. 27): “For natural persons, legal personality appears at birth […] and disappears at death […].“ ([P]our les personnes physiques, la personnalité juridique apparaît avec la naissance […] et disparaît avec la mort […].).

  17. 17.

    An American landmark case, defining foetuses as nonpersons in the context of the 14th Amendment of the Constitution, is Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 158 (1972).

  18. 18.

    This is Neil MacCormick’s translation of the maxim (MacCormick 2007, p. 79).

  19. 19.

    Jörg Neuner analyses anencephalic infants from the point of view of German law and concludes that they are “full legal persons” because the relevant organs – heart, lungs and brain – are still functioning (Neuner 2013, p. 651).

  20. 20.

    This is the terminology used in the UN Disability Convention. See also (Flynn and Arstein-Kerslake 2014) and (Quinn and Arstein-Kerslake 2012).

  21. 21.

    This is somewhat inspired by Neil MacCormick’s terminology in (MacCormick 2007, p. 77–99).

  22. 22.

    Just a few of the scholars classifying slaves as legal nonpersons include (Fede 1992); (Kelsen 2006, p. 95); and (Wise 1996, p. 1). The Scandinavian realist Karl Olivecrona takes himself to be reporting the received opinion when noting that slaves lack legal personality (Olivecrona 1928, p. 38). See also for instance (Cairns 2012).

  23. 23.

    In addition, some animals were prosecuted in criminal courts during the Middle Ages. See (Evans 2010) and (Sykes 2011).

  24. 24.

    Many jurisdictions passed statutes abolishing coverture during the mid-19th century. See (Hoff-Wilson 1987). Married women’s legal status in the 19th-century US is depicted in (Shammas 1994). For a contemporary perspective on the active legal personality of women in a number of Commonwealth countries, see (Freeman 1990). A rather famous case is also In re Lockwood, where the US Supreme Court allowed for state courts to interpret “person” as excluding females. In re Lockwood 154 U.S. 116 (1894)

  25. 25.

    I’ve omitted the “and-duty-bearers” part to improve readability.

  26. 26.

    Some authors distinguish between legal and jural relations; I use the phrases interchangeably.

  27. 27.

    Kramer’s interest theory was first articulated in (Kramer 1998), and subsequently refined in several articles, such as (Kramer 2001). For will theories, see (Hart 1982), (Steiner 1994), and (Simmonds 1998).

  28. 28.

    To be more precise, rights are claims that are accompanied by sundry immunities. I will disregard this detail in the present discussion, as it does not affect my argument in any way.

  29. 29.

    Which entities can hold interest-theory rights is discussed more extensively in (Kramer 2001).

  30. 30.

    This is a crude simplification of Kramer’s interest theory, but it preserves the features of the theory that are relevant for the argument.

  31. 31.

    Kramer has a more extensive conception of interests, as he thinks that interests can be ascribed to, for instance, blades of grass, but the normative protections of sentient beings are according to him the primary group of such protections that can be called rights.

  32. 32.

    See, for example, The Cambridge Declaration on Consciousness, drafted by Philip Low and signed on July 7, 2012 by conference participants of Francis Crick Memorial Conference on Consciousness in Human and non-Human Animals. It is available at http://fcmconference.org/img/CambridgeDeclarationOnConsciousness.pdf (accessed Nov 19, 2016).

  33. 33.

    It is important to note that the sheer fact that a foetus or an animal is sentient does not tell us what kind of legal protections these beings should be accorded. Even if a third-trimester foetus is sentient, there may still be moral justifications for the termination of pregnancy during this phase of gestation.

  34. 34.

    More generally regarding the legal protection of slaves in the antebellum South, see (Morris 1996, p. 182–208).

  35. 35.

    Some adherents of the legal-persons-as-right-holders view recognise this; Richard Tur, for instance, notes that legal personhood is “a matter of degree” (Tur 1988, p. 122).

  36. 36.

    Women have not been legal persons to a full extent at all times, either – for instance, in some jurisdictions, they have lacked the competence to dispose of their property, and in others the legal capacity to own property altogether.

  37. 37.

    An interesting exception in this regard is Arthur Machen, who claims that legal personhood is not about right-holding at all but only about duty-bearing (Machen 1911, p. 263).

  38. 38.

    The claim is also false with regard to rights, but not as glaringly false.

  39. 39.

    It is rather interesting that in Political Liberalism John Rawls endorses the claim that “slaves are not counted as capable of having duties or obligations” (Rawls 2005, p. 33). However, on the same page he makes reference to Patterson’s book, which contains a wholesale rebuttal of that very claim. Hillel Steiner makes a similar claim: “self-enslavement […] cannot be incurred by a self-owner’s transferring (selling or donating) that right [to self-ownership], since such transfers entail that transferrors thereby acquire duties to their transferees, whereas slaves, as things wholly owned by others, must lack duties as well as rights” (Steiner 1994, p. 232f).

  40. 40.

    “Typical” in that the jurisdiction has, for instance, preserved the born-alive rule: only children that are born alive are legal persons.

  41. 41.

    This depends somewhat on the jurisdiction, however. In certain common-law jurisdictions (such as England), children may only be the beneficiaries of trusts. Regardless, this is often considered a form of “beneficial ownership” (see Penner 2014). Even in such jurisdictions where infants are allowed to own property, from a Hohfeldian point of view they only hold ownership-related claim-rights but not the ownership-related powers that require more advanced volitional capacity.

  42. 42.

    For example, Article 16-1 of the French Civil Code states explicitly that the human body, its elements and its products cannot be the objects of economic rights (droit patrimonial). The question of whether human bodies can be property in the context of common-law jurisdictions is discussed extensively in (Davies and Naffine 2001).

  43. 43.

    Even if in some jurisdictions the killing of one’s newborn may lead to a less harsh sentence than a typical homicide. For example, according to Finnish law, “[a] woman who in a state of exhaustion or distress caused by childbirth kills her baby shall be sentenced for infanticide” (Finnish criminal code, chapter 21, section 4).

  44. 44.

    The Oregon Supreme Court has in fact recently delivered two interesting judgments in this regard. In State v. Fessenden/Dicke (355 Or 759 (2014)) the court affirmed a decision by a lower court, according to which “animals were included in the class of ‘persons’ that officers may aid without a warrant” (at 763). State v. Nix (355 Or 777 (2014)) concerned Oregon’s anti-merger statute, according to which a given type of conduct that violates only one statute constitutes as many crimes as there are victims. The court ruled that animals are such victims, which is why the defendant could be convicted of 20 counts of animal neglect rather than only one.

Bibliography

  • Austin, John. 1885. Lectures on Jurisprudence: Or, the Philosophy of Positive Law, vol. I. London: John Murray, Albemarle Street.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg, Jessica. 2007. Of Elephants and Embryos: A Proposed Framework for Legal Personhood. Hastings Law Journal 59: 369–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birks, Peter, Grant McLeod, and Paul Krueger, ed. 1987. Justinian’s Institutes. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Björne, Lars. 1998. Brytningstiden: den nordiska rättsvetenskapens historia. Del II, 1815–1870. Lund: Institutet för rättshistorisk forskning.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cairns, John W. 2012. The Definition of Slavery in Eighteenth-Century Thinking. In The Legal Understanding of Slavery: From the Historical to the Contemporary, ed. Jean Allain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, Margaret Jane, and Ngaire Naffine. 2001. Are Persons Property?: Legal Debates About Property and Personality. Dartmouth: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, P.W. 1938. Personality in Roman Private Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, E.P. 2010. The Criminal Prosecution and Capital Punishment of Animals. Clark, New Jersey: The Lawbook Exchange, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fede, Andrew. 1992. People Without Rights: an Interpretation of the Fundamentals of the Law of Slavery in the U.S. South. New York & London: Garland Publishing, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel. 1974. The Rights of Animals and Unborn Generations. In Philosophy and Environmental Crisis, ed. William T. Blackstone, 43–68. Athens, GA: The University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flynn, Eilionóir, and Anna Arstein-Kerslake. 2014. Legislating personhood: realising the right to support in exercising legal capacity. International Journal of Law in Context 10: 81–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, Marsha A. 1990. Measuring Equality: A Comparative Perspective on Women’s Legal Capacity and Constitutional Rights in Five Commonwealth Countries. Commonwealth Law Bulletin 16: 1418–1443. doi:10.1080/03050718.1990.9986106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funkhouser, Eric. 2014. The Logical Structure of Kinds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, John Chipman. 1997. The Nature and Sources of the Law. Edited by David Campbell and Philip Thomas. Brookfield, USA: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, HLA. 1955. Are There Any Natural Rights? The Philosophical Review 64: 175–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, HLA. 1982. Essays on Bentham. Jurisprudence and Political Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hattenhauer, Christian. 2011. “Der Mensch als Solcher Rechtsfähig” – Von der Person zur Rechtsperson. In Der Mensch als Person und Rechtsperson, ed. Eckart Klein and Christoph Menke, 39–66. Berlin: Berliner Wissenschafts-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heaton, Jacqueline. 2015. The South African Law of Persons. 4thed. Durban: Lexis Nexis South Africa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herget, James E., and Stephen Wallace. 1986. The German Free Law Movement as the Source of American Legal Realism. Virginia Law Review 73: 399–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoeflich, Michael H. 1989. Savigny and His Anglo-American Disciples. American Journal of Comparative Law 37: 17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoff-Wilson, Joan. 1987. The Unfinished Revolution: Changing Legal Status of U.S. Women. Signs 13: 7. doi:10.1086/494384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, Thomas Erskine. 1880. The Elements of Jurisprudence. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holthöfer, Ernst, and Johanna M. Baboukis. 2009. Doneau, Hugues. In The Oxford International Encyclopedia of Legal History, ed. Stanley N. Katz, 359–362. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 2006. General Theory of Law and State. New Brunswick, New Jersey: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, Matthew H. 1998. Rights Without Trimmings. In A Debate over Rights. Philosophical Enquiries, Matthew H. Kramer, N. E. Simmonds, and Hillel Steiner, 7–112. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, Matthew H. 2001. Getting Rights Right. In Rights, Wrongs and Responsibilities, ed. Matthew H. Kramer. Houndmills: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagercrantz, H, and JP Changeux. 2009. The emergence of human consciousness: from fetal to neonatal life. Pediatric research: 255–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larenz, Karl. 1983. Allgemeiner Teil des deutschen Bürgerlichen Rechts. Ein Lehrbuch. München: C.H. Beck’sche Verlagsbuchhandlung.

    Google Scholar 

  • de las Heras Ballell, Teresa Rodríguez. 2010. Introduction to Spanish Private Law. Facing the Social and Economic Challenges. London: Routledge-Cavendish.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann, M. 2007. Der Begriff der Rechtsfähigkeit. Archiv für die civilistische Praxis.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, Neil. 2007. Institutions of Law. An Essay in Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Machen, Arthur W. 1911. Corporate Personality. Harvard Law Review 24: 253–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malaurie, Philippe. 1999. Cours de droit civil. Les personnes, les incapacités. 5th ed. Paris: Éditions Cujas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, Thomas D: 1996. Southern Slavery and the Law, 1619–1860. Chapel Hill and London: The University of North Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neuner, Jörg. 2013. Zur Rechtsfähigkeit des Anencephalus. Medizinrecht 31: 647–651. doi:10.1007/s00350-013-3527-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olivecrona, Karl. 1928. Studier över begreppet juridisk person i romersk och modern rätt. Uppsala: Appelbergs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, Orlando. 1982. Slavery and Social Death. A Comparative Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penner, J.E. 2014. The (True) Nature of a Beneficiary’s Equitable Proprietary Interest under a Trust. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 27: 2014.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, Sir Frederick. 1896. A First Book of Jurisprudence for Students of the Common Law. London: Macmillan and Co., Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylkkänen, Anu. 2009. Trapped in Equality: Women as Legal Persons in the Modernisation of Finnish Law. Helsinki: Suomalaisen Kirjallisuuden Seura/Finnish Literature Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1951. Two Dogmas of Empiricism. The Philosophical Review 60: 20–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quinn, Gerard, and Anna Arstein-Kerslake. 2012. Restoring the “human” in “human rights”: personhood and doctrinal innovation in the UN disability convention. In The Cambridge Companion to Human Rights Law, ed. Conor Gearty and Costas Douzinas, 36–55. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rattigan, W.H. 1888. The Science of Jurisprudence, Chiefly Intended for Indian Students. Lahore: Civil and Military Gazette Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 2005. Political Liberalism. Expanded Edition. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reimann, Mathias. 1989. The Historical School against Codification: Savigny, Carter, and the Defeat of the New York Civil Code. American Journal of Comparative Law 37: 95–119. doi:10.2307/840443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riesenfeld, Stefan. 1989. The Influence of German Legal Theory on American Law: The Heritage of Savigny and His Disciples. American Journal of Comparative Law 37: 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rochfeld, Judith. 2013. Les grandes notions du droit privé. 2nd ed. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmond, John W. 1902. Jurisprudence or the Theory of the Law. London: Stevens & Haynes.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Savigny, Friedrich Carl. 1884. Jural Relations; or, the Roman Law of Persons as Subjects of Jural Relations : Being a Translation of the Second Book of Savigny’s System of Modern Roman Law. Translated by William Henry Rattigan. London: Wildy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seymour, John. 2000. The Legal Status of the Fetus. In Childbirth and the Law, 135–189. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shammas, Carole. 1994. Re-Assessing the Married Women’s Property Acts. Journal of Women’s History 6: 9–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmonds, N. E. 1998. Rights at the Cutting Edge. In A Debate over Rights. Philosophical Enquiries, ed. Matthew H. Kramer, N. E. Simmonds, and Hillel Steiner, 113–232. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, Peter. 1998. Systematization of Private Law in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries. In Entwicklung der Methodenlehre in Rechtswissenschaft und Philosophie vom 16. bis zum 18. Jahrhundert, ed. Jan Schröder, 117–126. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, Hillel. 1994. An Essay on Rights. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sykes, Katie. 2011. Human Drama, Animal Trials: What the Medieval Animal Trials Can Teach Us About Justice for Animals. Animal Law 17: 273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thibaut, Anton Friedrich Justus. 1803. System des Pandektenrechts. Jena: Mauke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trahan, J.-R. 2008. The Distinction between Persons and Things: An Historical Perspective. Journal of Civil Law Studies 1: 9–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuori, Kaarlo. 2002. Critical Legal Positivism. Hants: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tur, Richard. 1988. The “Person” in Law. In Persons and Personality. A Contemporary Inquiry., ed. Arthur Peacocke and Grant Gillett, 117–129. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, Alan. 1988. Roman Slave Law. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wise, Steven M. 1996. The Legal Thinghood of Nonhuman Animals. Boston College Environmental Affairs Law Review: 471.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wise, Steven M. 2010. Legal Personhood and the Nonhuman Rights Project. Animal Law 17.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Visa A. J. Kurki .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kurki, V.A.J. (2017). Why Things Can Hold Rights: Reconceptualizing the Legal Person. In: Kurki, V., Pietrzykowski, T. (eds) Legal Personhood: Animals, Artificial Intelligence and the Unborn. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 119. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53462-6_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53462-6_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-53461-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-53462-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics