Skip to main content

Being Concrete About Culture and Cultural Evolution

  • Chapter
Perspectives in Ethology

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Ethology ((PEIE,volume 13))

Abstract

Culture consists of behavior. The units are practices shared by members of a group and acquired as a result of membership in the group. Although it is common to define the units of culture as abstractions, such as culturgens or memes, these abstractions in no way help to explain a group’s practices. Instead, they only direct research away from the context and consequences that result in transmission of a practice from one group member to another. If culture is to be described as an evolutionary process, one must have a sufficiently general definition of “evolutionary process” to allow genetic evolution and cultural evolution to be examples. This may be accomplished by defining an evolutionary process as composed of variation (within a pool of replicators), transmission (by copying), and selection (by differential transmission). The replicators of cultural evolution are practices, which are units of operant behavior (i.e., behavior under control of consequences and context). Practices are transmitted from individual to individual by imitation and instruction. Instruction may be understood with the concept of a rule, which is a verbal discriminative stimulus (i.e., a verbally created context). Instruction consists of rule-giving, which results in rule-following on the part of the instructee. New rules come into a culture frequently as a result of rule-making, the generation of new rules on the basis of non-social stimuli. Selection in cultural evolution occurs because imitation and instruction of competing practices have differential consequences in the long run, consequences that impact reproductive potential. Since such long-term consequences have little effect on behavior, an adaptive practice (i.e., one that pays in the long run, called “self-control”) is strengthened in the short-term by social reinforcers delivered by rule-givers. A behavioral analysis focuses on environmental events that are observable and, so, susceptible to research. The postulating of fictitious inner entities, whether they be memes, “devices,” or “modules,” only impedes understanding of culture and cultural evolution. Natural selection, because it is short-sighted and opportunistic, may be expected to produce mechanisms that aid and abet valuable behavioral functions. The key to understanding cultural evolution lies in understanding practices in the light of their environmental contexts and short- and long-term consequences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ainslie, G., & Herrnstein, R. J. (1981). Preference reversal and delayed reinforcement. Animal Learning & Behavior, 9, 476–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alcock, J. (1998).Animal behavior: An evolutionary approach (6th ed.). Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baum, W. M. (1973). The correlation-based law of effect. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 20,137–153.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Baum, W. M. (1989). Quantitative prediction and molar description of the environment. The Behavior Analyst, 12,167–176.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Baum, W. M. (1994). Understanding behaviorism: Science, behavior, and culture. New York: Addison Wesley Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baum, W. M. (1995). Rules, culture, and fitness. The Behavior Analyst, 18,1–21.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Baum, W. M. (1997). The trouble with time. In L. J. Hayes & P. M. Ghezzi (Eds.), Investigations in behavioral epistemology (pp. 47–59). Reno, NV: Context Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baum,W. M. (1998). Why not ask, “Does the chimpanzee have a soul?”. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21,116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1985). Culture and the evolutionary process. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1982). The extended phenotype: The long reach of the gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1989). The selfish gene (New ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (1984). Spontaneous and deferred imitation in the pigeon. Behavioural Processes, 9, 347–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, R. (1987). Practical reason and a science of morals. In S. Modgil & C. Modgil (Eds.), B. F. Skinner: Consensus and controversy (pp. 319–327). New York: Falmer Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenn, S. S. (1991). Contingencies and metacontingencies: Relations among behavioral, cultural, and biological evolution. In P. A. Lamal (Ed.), Behavioral analysis of societies and cultural practices (pp. 39–73). New York: Hemisphere.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerin, B. (1992). Behavior analysis and the social construction of knowledge. American Psychologist, 47,1423–1432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guerin, B. (1997). How things get done: Socially, non-socially; with words, without words. In L. J. Hayes & P. M. Ghezzi (Eds.), Investigations in behavioral epistemology (pp. 219–235). Reno, NV: Context Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerin, B. (1998). Religious behaviors as strategies for organizing groups of people: A social contingency analysis. The Behavior Analyst, 21, 53–72.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, M. (1980). Cultural materialism. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrnstein, R. J., & Loveland, D. H. (1964). Complex visual concept in the pigeon.Science, 146,549–551.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. M. (1998). Theory of mind in nonhuman primates. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27,101–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • .Honig, W. K., & Staddon, J. E. R. (Eds.). (1977). Handbook of operant behavior. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horne, P. J., & Lowe, C. F. (1996). On the origins of naming and other symbolic behavior. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 65,185–241.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Logue, A.W. (1988). Research on self-control: An integrating framework. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11,665–709.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Logue, A. W. (1995). Self-control: Waiting until tomorrow for what you want today. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lumsden, C. J., & Wilson, E. O. (1981). Genes, mind, and culture: The coevolutionary process. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moerk, E. L. (1996). Input and learning processes in first language acquisition. In H. W. Reese (Ed.), Advances in child development and behavior (Vol. 26, pp. 181–228). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (1994). The language instinct. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S., & Bloom, P. (1992). Natural language and natural selection. In J. H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture (pp. 451–493). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pulliam, H. R. (1983). On the theory of gene-culture co-evolution in a variable environment. In R. L. Mellgren (Ed.), Animal cognition and behavior (pp. 427–443). Amsterdam: Elsevier/North-Holland.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rachlin, H. (1994). Behavior and mind: The roots of modern psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachlin, H. (1995). Self-control: Beyond commitment. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 18, 109–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rachlin, H., & Green, L. (1972). Commitment, choice, and self-control. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 17,15–22.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1990). A mechanism for social selection and successful altruism. Science, 250, 1665–1668.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1961). The generic nature of the concepts of stimulus and response. In Cumulative record (Enlarged ed., pp. 347–366). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. (Original work published 1935).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behavior. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1969). An operant analysis of problem solving. In Contingencies of reinforcement: A theoretical analysis (pp. 133–171). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1971). Beyond freedom and dignity. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1981). Selection by consequences. Science, 213, 501–504.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J., & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological foundations of culture. In J. H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture (pp. 19–136). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teitelbaum, P. (1977). Levels of integration of the operant. In W. K. Honig & J. E. R. Staddon (Eds.), Handbook of operant behavior (pp. 7–27). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. T. (1977). Contrasting orientations to the theory of visual information processing. Psychological Review, 84, 67–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaughan,W., Jr. (1988). Formation of equivalence sets in pigeons. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 14, 36–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wasserman, E. A., DeVolder, C. L., & Coppage, D. J. (1992). Nonsimilarity-based conceptualization in pigeons via secondary or mediated generalization. Psychological Science, 3, 374–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, M. J. (1990). Mediationism and the obfuscation of memory. American Psychologist, 45, 328–335.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, E. O. (1975). Sociobiology: The new synthesis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuriff, G. (1987). Naturalist ethics. In S. Modgil & C. Modgil (Eds.), B. F. Skinner: Consensus and controversy (pp. 309–318). New York: Falmer Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Baum, W.M. (2000). Being Concrete About Culture and Cultural Evolution. In: Tonneau, F., Thompson, N.S. (eds) Perspectives in Ethology. Perspectives in Ethology, vol 13. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-1221-9_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-1221-9_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4613-5447-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4615-1221-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics