Skip to main content

The Problem of History

  • Chapter
Conservatism and Pragmatism
  • 189 Accesses

Abstract

Once Hegel, Marx, Darwin, and Maine, as representative figures of the 19th century, proffered a historical analysis of Enlightenment era concepts, the question of history itself became, at least potentially, either silent and opaque to the historian or open to explicit philosophical investigation. Thus, when we use historical analysis, we do better to make more transparent what we think the meaning and purpose of historical analysis is.

“The constellation [of life and history] really has been altered — by science, by the demand that history should be a science.” (the italics are in the original)

Friedrich Nietzsche, “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life”*

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. * Friedrich Nietzsche, (1997) “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life” in Untimely Meditations, Ed. Daniel Breazeale, Trans. R. J. Hollingdale, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), p. 77.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  2. Cornel West, (1989) The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism, (Madison, University of Wisconsin Press) p. 183.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  3. Martin Packer, (2011) The Science of Qualitative Research, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Jacquelyn Ann K. Kegley, (1973), “Royce and Husserl: Some Parallels and Food for Thought,” Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 14(3), p. 187.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Hans Georg Gadamer, (2004) Truth and Method, (London: Continuum) p. 215.

    Google Scholar 

  6. W.V.O Quine, (1963), “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” in From a Logical Point of View, (New York: Harper) p. 43.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Richard Rorty, (1985) “Texts and Lumps,” New Literary History, 17(1), p. 3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Richard Rorty, (1989) Irony, Contingency, and Solidarity, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press) p. 85.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  9. Friedrich Nietzsche, (1997) “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life,” in Untimely Meditations, Trans. R. Hollingdale, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) p. 95.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Richard A. Posner, (2001) Frontiers of Legal Theory, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press) p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Larry A. Hickman, (2007) Pragmatism as Post-Postmodernism: Lessons from John Dewey, (New York: Fordham University Press) p. 51. Postmodernist and relativist history, in its most excessive incarnations, results only in “expressions of an infinitely self-reflexive nexus of literary descriptions and redescriptions which are tantamount to interminable discursive flights that do not offer the possibility of firm, behavioral, referential perches,” as Larry Hickman put it (51). Rorty raises the relativism of infinite interpretability and redescription to an absolute of its own, the same way Nietzsche raised anti-reason to one.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  12. Thomas C. Grey, (1991) “What Good Is Legal Pragmatism?” in Pragmatism in Law and Society, Ed. Brint and Weaver , (Boulder: Westview Press) p. 9, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Martin Heidegger, (1962) Being and Time, Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson, (San Francisco: Harper).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Jean Francois Lyotard, (1979) The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Seth Vannatta, (2012) “Between Science and Fiction: Pragmatism and Conservatism in History and Law,” European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, 4(1), pp. 159–160.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2014 Seth Vannatta

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Vannatta, S. (2014). The Problem of History. In: Conservatism and Pragmatism. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137466839_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics