Skip to main content

What Is Philosophical Dialogue?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophy and Literature
  • 870 Accesses

Abstract

Through a close reading of a number of Platonic dialogues—namely, the Cratylus, the Gorgias, the Theaetetus, and the Apology—this chapter sheds light upon the event of philosophical dialogue, as well as upon the literary genre that shares its name.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 299.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 379.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Sallis (1975, 7): “In the dialogues philosophical activity is concretely presented, it is presented in an individual mode.”

  2. 2.

    This would become Feldweg-Gespräche (GA 77), translated by Brett W. Davis as Country Path Conversations.

  3. 3.

    There are many archaic examples of philosophical dialogue that antedate Plato’s works. For a partial list, see Hösle (2012, 71–73).

  4. 4.

    See Hösle (2012, xviii): “Whitehead’s famous remark that Western philosophy ‘consists of a series of footnotes to Plato’ strikes many people as an exaggeration; but there is no doubt that it is true of the philosophical dialogue. No one who had access to Plato’s works could have escaped his influence; even in the dark centuries his indirect influence can be seen.”

  5. 5.

    Indeed, Plato is the first author on record to use the noun διάλογος. See Jazdewska (2014, 19).

  6. 6.

    See Kahn (1996, 41): “The anonymity of the dialogue form, together with Plato’s problematic irony in the presentation of Socrates, makes it impossible for us to see through these dramatic works in such a way as to read the mind of their author.”

  7. 7.

    At the time of Plato, the word λόγος carried many different (though related) significations, including “speech,” “discourse ,” “word,” “statement ,” “story,” “account,” and, arguably, “argument.” I leave it largely untranslated throughout this chapter in order to avoid hastily deciding in favour of one of these significations to the exclusion of the others. On the risks involved in such hasty decisions, see Sallis (1975, 14–15).

  8. 8.

    The word “dialogue” is often mistakenly believed to refer specifically to a conversation between two people, an argument erroneously based upon the conflating of the Greek δία (meaning “through” or “across”) with the Greek δι (meaning “two”). However, the Greek word δiάλογος does imply a conversation, that is, a speaking involving at least two. (On the origin and history of this term in antiquity, see Jazdewska 2014, 17–36.) In Plato’s Gorgias, Socrates at one point holds a dialogue with himself. (This passage is mentioned in greater detail below.) In light of this, one might say that a dialogue entails a conversation between at least two perspectives, even if it does not literally involve two people.

  9. 9.

    For a much more comprehensive treatment of this text along these lines, please see Ewegen (2013).

  10. 10.

    On this point, Hans-Georg Gadamer is quite lucid: “Reaching an understanding in conversation presupposes that both partners are ready for it and are trying to recognize the full value of what is alien and opposed to them. If this happens mutually … it is finally possible to achieve … a common diction and a common dictum” (Gadamer 1975, 387).

  11. 11.

    Both meanings draw upon the original sense of the Greek διάλογος and διαλἐγεσθαι.

  12. 12.

    See Apology, 21b–e, et al.

  13. 13.

    See Gorgias, 454. See also Gadamer (1975, 383). See also Sallis (1975, 3).

  14. 14.

    See Gadamer (1975, 367–68).

  15. 15.

    See Protagoras, 337a ff.

  16. 16.

    See Gorgias, 454b.

  17. 17.

    See, for example, Euthyphro, 15c–d; Protagoras, 361c–d; Cratylus, 440a–d; Theaetetus, 209b–d.

  18. 18.

    Even Plato’s Apology, which is ostensibly a record of Socrates’s trial, is highly poetized.

  19. 19.

    Ποίησις derives from ποιέω, which principally means make, create, or produce.

  20. 20.

    On this, see Sallis (1975, 14–18).

  21. 21.

    For a similar point, see Hösle (2012): “By essence, a philosophical dialogue necessarily includes a philosophical question, argumentative efforts to answer it, their linguistic articulation, and a plurality of participants in the conversation. Accordingly, the philosophical dialogue has the task of clarifying the relation between certain kinds of people, certain philosophical views, and certain forms of debate, between certain arguments and the emotional reactions to them, between ways of thinking and ways of life, and also ideally between thoughts and language” (48–49).

  22. 22.

    See Sallis (1975, 22).

  23. 23.

    As Jill Gordon puts it, Plato’s dialogues are, in this way, “an occasion for self-examination” (Gordon 1999, 9).

Bibliography

  • Ewegen, Shane. 2013. Plato’s Cratylus: The Comedy of Language. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, Hans Georg. 1975. Truth and Method. Translated by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall. New York, NY: Continuum Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, Jill. 1999. Turning Toward Philosophy: Literary Device and Dramatic Structure in Plato’s Dialogues. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2010a. Country Path Conversations. Translated by Bret W. Davis. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010b. Letters to His Wife. Edited by Getrud Heidegger and translated by R.D.V. Glasow. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hösle, Vittorio. 2012. The Philosophical Dialogue: A Poetics and Hermeneutics. Translated by Steven Randall. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jazdewska, Katarzyna. 2014. From Dialogos to Dialogue: The Use of the Term from Plato to the Second Century CE. Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 54: 17–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, Charles. 1996. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1914. Apology. Translated by H.N. Fowler. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1921. Theaetetus. Translated by H.N. Fowler. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1925. Gorgias. Translated by W.R.M. Lamb. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1926. Cratylus. Translated by H.N. Fowler. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Symposium. Translated by Seth Benardete. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sallis, John. 1975. Being and Logos. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to S. Montgomery Ewegen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ewegen, S.M. (2018). What Is Philosophical Dialogue?. In: Stocker, B., Mack, M. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophy and Literature. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-54794-1_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics