Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Theory and Decision Library C ((TDLC,volume 4))

Abstract

In this chapter we introduce topological structure, and use this to obtain additive representations under continuity assumptions. As before, the set of alternatives is a Cartesian product ПiєIΓi. As always (with Chapter V excepted) I is the finite set {1 ,...,n}. Furthermore, we shall from now on assume that every Γi is a connected and separable topological space. A reader not interested in general topology may simply assume that Γi is a convex subset of a Euclidean space, e.g. Γi is \(\mathbb{R}_ + ^{{m_i}} \) , or \(\mathbb{R}\). Then all topological assumptions in the sequel are satisfied, and can be ignored. ПiєIΓi will always be endowed with the product topology, hence is connected (see Kelley, 1955, Chapter 3, problem 0) and separable too. The condition of topological separability has been added only for simplicity of presentation. It can nearly always be omitted (see Remarks A3.1 and III.7.1). The crucial assumption is connectedness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Reference

  1. Such a view has been expressed in Aumann(1962, p.446). Some further discussions of the ‘rationality’ of completeness (and other elementary conditions for preferences) can be found in Shafer(1986, p.469), and throughout Hogarth Reder(1987).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Wakker(1988d) gives arguments in favour of the algebraic approach. Further comments will be given here in section III.8. More elaborated topological results are provided in Vind(1986a, Chapter III).

    Google Scholar 

  3. There have been many vivid discussions about ordinal versus cardinal utility. Recent references are Cooter Rappoport(1984, 1985), and Basu(1982). Hence, to avoid unintended connotations, in the literature often the expression ‘unique up to a linear/positive affine transformation’ is used instead of cardinal, and ‘unique up to a strictly increasing transformation’ instead of ordinal. Sometimes ordinal is used instead of continuously ordinal. In psychological literature the terms ordinal scale and interval scale (the latter for cardinal representation) are customary. The reason for our choice of terminology is linguistic. The adjective cardinal is more convenient than the noun (interval) scale, and ‘unique up to a positive affine transformation’ is inconvenient because of its length.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Other usual scale types are ‘nominal scales’, for which only the = and # relations are relevant, and ’ratio-scales’, where in comparison with cardinal scales also a natural ’zero-point’ is given. Also sometimes ’consists of’ in section III.2 has been changed into ’is a subset of the set of’, or ’is a superset of the set or. Although in principle many more kinds of scale types could be thought of, in practice mainly the above-mentioned ones occur. Luce Narens(1987) use ’homogeneity arguments’ to explain this.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Lemma I.3.2 in Vind(1986a) may serve as an illustration of the meaning of topological connectedness.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Recent proofs are provided in Jaffray(1975) and Richter(1980).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Fishburn(1970) gives as well the topological approach, as the algebraic approach, as a `mixture-space-approach’.

    Google Scholar 

  8. There is mainly one exception concerning generality, and that is the result of Gorman(1968). His generalization falls somewhat outside the scope of this monograph; its derivation will not be given. An efficient derivation of it is provided in Theorem V.2.4 in Vind(1986a). Example III.6.8(b) will show two aspects in which our approach is less general than that of KLST.

    Google Scholar 

  9. rf8 For this mainly Blaschke(1928) and Keeney Raiffa(1976)) were inspiring to us. Also Fleming(1952) uses this way of constructing a grid; he uses an infinitesimally small mesh.

    Google Scholar 

  10. and without Keeney Raiffa(1976, Chapter 3) available

    Google Scholar 

  11. In Keeney Raiffa(1976) it is called the corresponding trade-offs condition.

    Google Scholar 

  12. This result was pointed out in Debreu(1960, introduction).

    Google Scholar 

  13. e.g. in Wakker(1988a)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Probably Lemma III.1.5 in Vind(1986a) is the most advanced result to show that topological separability need not be assumed unless exactly one coordinate is essential.

    Google Scholar 

  15. In this we follow Pfanzagl(1968, Definitions 8.5.12 and 8.6.3), Vind(1986a, condition c3), and Fuhrken Richter(1988).

    Google Scholar 

  16. That independence is required only for equal subalternatives of length n - 2, has also been established by Gorman(1968, section 4.4) for the case where his stronger restrictive assumptions are satisfied. The problems of CI with equivalences instead of preferences, and without weak separability (or monotonicity) are addressed in Mak(1988).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Debreu(1960, p.17, lines 2–4) suggests that this will suffice, and uses it in his proof. Also Corollary IV.2.6 in Vind(1986a) shows this, for the Thomsen condition.

    Google Scholar 

  18. A recent reference is Be11(1987).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wakker, P.P. (1989). Additive Representations. In: Additive Representations of Preferences. Theory and Decision Library C, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7815-8_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7815-8_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4036-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7815-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics