Skip to main content

Sceptical Anti-Aristotelianism

  • Chapter
Pierre Gassendi

Part of the book series: Synthese Historical Library ((SYHL,volume 30))

Abstract

According to Gassendi’s own account he conceived a dislike for Aristotelian philosophy during his student days in the college of Aix-en-Provence. His complaints at that time concerned an alleged ethical inadequacy in Aristotelianism, for the Peripatetic philosophy, in his view, did not measure up to the Stoic philosophical ideal to which Cicero had alluded in his praise of philosophy: “Philosophy can never be praised as she merits; the man who obeys her precepts may live all the days of his life without trouble”.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “Nunquam satis laudari digne poterit philosophia: cui qui pareat, omne tempus aetatis sine molestia possit degere” (Cicero, De senectute (Loeb classical library edition), I.2.); P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p.99.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. Gassendi’s letter to Henri du Faur de Pibrac, a prominent public figure, later President of the Parlement of Provence, son of Guy du Faur de Pibrac: P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, VI, p.2.

    Google Scholar 

  3. P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p.99.

    Google Scholar 

  4. “Verum mihi animos adiecit, timoremque omnem depulit et Vivis, et mei Charonii lectio, ex qua visus sum non iniuria suspicari sectam illam non esse penitus probandam, quod probaretur quamplurimis. Sed

    Google Scholar 

  5. et vires accrevere ex Ramo praesertim, ac Mirandulo: quorum idcirco mentionem facio, quod ingenuum semper duxerim profiteri per quos profecissem.” (P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p.99.)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. B. Rochot: 1955, “La vie, le caractère et la formation intellectuelle”, in B. Rochot et al.:. 1955, Pierre Gassendi 1592–1655, sa vie et son oeuvre (Centre International de Synthèse), Paris, pp.9–54, espc. p. 16

    Google Scholar 

  7. also R. Lenoble: 1971, Mersenne ou la naissance du mécanisme, 2nd Edition, J. Vrin, Paris, p.410.

    Google Scholar 

  8. P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, pp.99–106a; VI, p.30.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Idem, III p.106a-b.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Idem, III, pp. 107a–108a.

    Google Scholar 

  11. “Per mathematicas scimus, si quid scimus.” (Idem, III, p. 107a.) This statement was a criticism of the Aristotelians. It is not to be concluded from it that Gassendi was himself a mathematician in any sense, for he was not.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. B. Rochot: 1957, “Gassendi et les mathématiques”, in Revue d’histoire des sciences, 10, pp.69–78. Gassendi was doing no more than repeat what he had read in the writings of Vives, Ramus and Mersenne

    Google Scholar 

  13. cf. P. Dear: 1984, “Marin Mersenne and the probabilistic roots of ‘mitigated scepticism’”, in Journal of the history of philosophy, 22, pp.173–205.

    Google Scholar 

  14. P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p. 107b.

    Google Scholar 

  15. “Uno verbo de hac rerum natura nihil perviderunt: quando suas scholas ingressi, aliam naturam ingressi sunt cum hac exteriori minime congruentem.” (Idem, III, p. 108a.)

    Google Scholar 

  16. See H.O. Evennett: 1968, The spirit of the Counter-Reformation, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp.78–79, 84–86

    Google Scholar 

  17. also Robert Mandrou: 1978, From humanism to science 1480–1700, Penguin, Harmondsworth, pp. 156–159.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Ignatius of Loyola: 1558–1599, The constitution of the Society of Jesus, IV, Ch.13

    Google Scholar 

  19. Father Aquaviva S.J.: 1599, Ratio studiorum

    Google Scholar 

  20. George E. Ganss S.J. (Ed.): 1970, Saint Ignatius of Loyola. The constitution of the Society of Jesus, St. Louis, pp.215ff.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ganss claims: “One great merit of the Ratio of 1599 is that it produced a unity of procedure throughout the far-flung hundreds of Jesuit schools in Europe and the Americas. That procedural unity was greater than would be desirable or possible today; but it was a significant advantage and achievement amid the educational disorganisation of the 1500’s and 1600’s.” (Idem, p.216, note 4.)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ignatius, Constitution, IV, ch. 14.3; Aquaviva, Ratio studiorum, ch. 3 (“De studio philosophiae”).

    Google Scholar 

  23. For example, two text-books issued by faculty members of the Collegio Romano: Benedetto Pereira: 1576, De communibus omnium rerum naturalium principiis et affectionibus libri quindecim, Rome

    Google Scholar 

  24. and Francisco de Toledo: 1585, Commentaria, una cum quaestionibus in octo libros Aristotelis ‘de Physica…, Cologne; also the text-books of the Jesuits of Coimbra, for example: Conimbricenses: 1602, Problemata quae in… physicis…, Moguntiae, 1601; and Commentariorum… in octo libros physicorum…, Cologne. These text-books were used very widely in Jesuit schools.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. A.C. Crombie: 1977, “Mathematics and Platonism in the sixteenth-century Italian universities and in Jesuit educational policy”, in IIPIΣMATA, Festschrift für Willy Hartner, Wiesbaden, pp.63–94.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Cf. E.A. Fellmann, “Fabri, Honoré”, Dictionary of scientific biography, IV, pp.505–507.

    Google Scholar 

  27. It was true of all sixteenth and early seventeenth-century scholastic texts that I have consulted (see bibliography). Charles B. Schmitt has written as follows: “… even a casual reading of the Aristotelian commentaries of the period [late sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries] reveals a peculiar reluctance to quote authors other than the school tradition… the Aristotelian commentary had changed remarkably little over a period of several centuries, considering how much philosophical water had passed under the bridge since the beginning of the humanist criticism of the schools… All in all, the school philosophy was considerably more traditionally oriented — both in form and content — than were the other philosophical movements which emerged in the course of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries.” (Charles B. Schmitt: 1964, “Who read Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirándola?”, in Studies in the Renaissance, II, pp. 125–126.)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Paul Dibon, in his interesting work (1954), La philosophie néerlandaise au siècle d’or.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Tome I, L’enseignement philosophique dans les universités à l’époque précartésienne (1576–1650), L’Institut Français d’Amsterdam, Amsterdam, has painted a different picture of scholastic teaching as it was conducted in Holland. Dibon has given a number of examples of Peripatetic philosophers teaching in scholastic institutions who were adapting their teaching in order to reflect the new intellectual movements. This was especially true in Leyden, he claimed, in the cases of Daniel Voetius, Cornelius Valerius and Jaccheus. This detail is of particular interest, since Gassendi visited Leyden in 1629 and later sent outlines of his Epicurean project to scholars of the Academy (cf. infra, Chs. 2, 3).

    Google Scholar 

  30. P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p.99, 100.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Gassendi had a theory that the chyle passed through the choledoch duct, and had debated this theory with a certain Professor Merindol of Marseilles. He was forced to abandon it when the De lacteis venis of Gasparo Aselli was published in 1627. Cf. Gassendi’s letter to Peiresc of 16.5.1628 (P. Tamizey de Larroque (Ed.), Lettres de Peiresc, IV, pp. 186–189

    Google Scholar 

  32. also Georges Martin-Charpenel: 1957, “Gassendi physiologiste”, in B. Rochot et al.: 1957, Actes du Congrès du Tricentenaire de Pierre Gassendi (4–5 août, 1955), Digne, pp.207–215).

    Google Scholar 

  33. P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p. 102.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Idem, IV, p.76.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Idem, III, p.102. Cf. the letter of Gassendi to Peiresc of 28.2.1629, in which he referred to the dissections of Payan that he had witnessed at an earlier time, in P. Tamizey de Larroque (Eds.), Lettres de Peiresc, IV, pp.203–209

    Google Scholar 

  36. also Martin-Charpenel: (1957), “Gassendi physiologiste”.

    Google Scholar 

  37. “Postquam enim pervidere licuit quantis Naturae Genius ab humano ingenio dissideret intervallis, quid aliud potui, quam existimare effectorum naturalium intimas causas prorsus fugere humanam perspicaciam? Miserescere proinde, ac pudere coepit me levitatis et arrogantiae Dogmaticorum Philosophorum, qui et glorientur se arripuisse, et tarn severe profiteantur naturalium rerum scientiam.” (P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p.99.)

    Google Scholar 

  38. “Enitendum duxi, quantum in me esset, retundere huius tantae credulitatis aciem, probaturus num simul quidpiam ex turgida illa Aristoteleorum praesumptione detraherem.” (Idem, III, p. 100.) There seems to be a verbal echo of Vives who complained that the Aristotelian subtleties “break and blunt the spearhead of the intelligence” (“frangunt ingenii aciem ac retundunt”) (J.L. Vives, Opera omnia, 1782, Gregorio Majansio (Ed.): Joannis Ludovici Vivis Valentini opera omnia, 8 vols., B. Monfort, Valencia, VI, p.352).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Supra, p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Cf. supra, p. 15; Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism (Loeb classical library edition), I.190,200.

    Google Scholar 

  41. “Nullum veriorem hoc sapiente Christianum fore puto.” (J. Vives, Opera omnia, III, p. 17.) Concerning the ethical writings of Vives, cf. Carlos G. Norena: 1970, Juan Luis Vives, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Ch.10.

    Google Scholar 

  42. For an account of the storm and for a spirited defence of Pierre Charron that goes against the standard censorious view, cf. the study of Charron by a latter-day kinsman, Jean Daniel Charron: 1960, The “wisdom” of Pierre Charron. An original and orthodox code of morality, University of North Carolina Press, Chapel Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  43. P. Charron: 1601, De la sagesse livres trois, S. Millanges, Bordeaux.

    Google Scholar 

  44. See the objections of those whom Charron called “esprits faibles”, and others, as they are listed in 1606, Traicté de sagesse, D. Le Clerc, Paris, pp.224–225, and in the preface to the second and all subsequent editions of the Sagesse. The objections which Charron took most note of were the claim that he was a Pelagian heretic and the objections against his Pyrrhonism on the grounds of its alleged danger for the faith.

    Google Scholar 

  45. P. Charron: 1606, Traicté de sagesse, composé par Pierre Charron, Parisien, D. Le Clerc, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Idem., ch. 2, par.9; ch. 4, par.2,3; ch. 7,etc.

    Google Scholar 

  47. “Infame escrivain, cynique et brutal s’il en fut jamais” (P.F. Garasse S.J.: 1625, La somme théologique des véritez capitales de la religion chrestienne, S. Chappelet, Paris, p.665). Garasse was himself subsequently condemned by the Sorbonne

    Google Scholar 

  48. cf. Richard H. Popkin: 1968, The history of scepticism from Erasmus to Descartes, revised edition, Harper and Row, New York, pp.114–118.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Charron replied in Traicté de sagesse, ch. 2, par.9; ch. 4, pars.2,3.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, I.190, 200.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Idem., 1.8, 10, 196, 205.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Idem, 1.8, 10, 12, 17,28–30.

    Google Scholar 

  53. J. Vives, Opera omnia, VI, pp.23–24

    Google Scholar 

  54. cf. C.G. Norena, Juan Luis Vives, pp.248–249.

    Google Scholar 

  55. “Philosophia tota opinionibus et conjecturis verisimilitudinis est innixa” (J. Vives, Opera omnia, VI, p.417).

    Google Scholar 

  56. P. Charron, Traicté de sagesse, p.224.

    Google Scholar 

  57. “Ces sont choses opposites” (P. Charron, Traicté de sagesse, p.225).

    Google Scholar 

  58. “Pulchre porro me admones authorem hune mecum in solitudinem ducam… Charronio vero quis sanior iudex?” (Letter of 8.4.1621, P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, VI, pp. 1–2.)

    Google Scholar 

  59. Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirándola: 1520, Examen vanitatis doctrinae gentium, et veritatis Christi anae disciplinae distinctum in libris sex, quorum tres omnem philosophorum sectam universim, reliqui Aristoteleam et Aristotelis armis particulatim impugnant, ubicumque autem Christiana et asseritur, et celebratur disciplina, Mirandola.

    Google Scholar 

  60. “I came to the conclusion that it was much better and much more useful to reduce all the dogmas of the philosophers to uncertainty, than to reconcile them with one another as my uncle wished to do.” “Mihi autem venit in mentem consentaneum magis esse, et utile magis, incerta reddere philosophorum dogmata, quam conciliare, ut patrinus volebat.” (Preface written by Gianfrancesco Pico to his edition of his uncle’s works entitled: Giovanni Pico della Mirandola: 1572–1573, Opera omnia Joannis Pici, Mirandulae Concordiaeque comitis…, 2 vols., Basileae, II, p.738.)

    Google Scholar 

  61. “Quid restat praeterea ut non ipsa gentium doctrina et vana, et incerta prorsus iudicetur.” (G.F. Pico della Mirandola, Idem, preface.)

    Google Scholar 

  62. Idem, II, pp.812–815; pp.718–719. Ramus also supported this view; cf. Reijer Hooykaas: 1958, Humanisme, science et réforme: Pierre de la Ramée (1515–1572), E.J. Brill, Leyden, pp.9.ff.

    Google Scholar 

  63. This conclusion has been arrived at after a certain amount of discussion among the scholars. Fortunat Strowski argued in his work Montaigne F. Alean, Paris (1906), that the Examen vanitatis had a very considerable influence on later thinkers. The opposite view was taken insofar as it concerned the relationship of Pico’s work with that of Montaigne, in the work of Pierre de Villey: 1908, Les sources de l’évolution des essais de Montaigne, Fondation Thiers, Paris, II, p. 166, pp.324–325. In more recent times both R.H. Popkin, History of scepticism, pp. 19–22

    Google Scholar 

  64. and Charles B. Schmitt: 1964, “Who read Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola?” in Studies in the renaissance, II, pp. 105–132

    Google Scholar 

  65. and Charles B. Schmitt in 1967, Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola (1469–1533), Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, have been in general agreement that the influence of Pico was not great, but that the Examen vanitatis was of some importance as a source-book for the anti-Aristotelians in the sixteenth and early seventeenth centuries.

    Google Scholar 

  66. C.B. Schmitt: 1964, pp.128–129.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Charles B. Schmitt: 1972, Cicero scepticus: a study of the ‘Academica’ in the Renaissance, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, ch. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  68. “Aristotelis philosophiam, orbis terrarum pene totam et solam philosophiam esse” (preface to Bks IX and X of 1556, Animadversionum Aristotelicarum libri XX, A. Wechelum, Paris). For complaints of Ramus against the Aristotelian commentators, see the same preface, also Bk. II, p.67, Bk. III, p.97; cf. also Hooykaas, Humanisme, science et réforme, p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  69. C.B. Schmitt, Cicero scepticus, p.89.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Cf. C.B. Schmitt, Cicero scepticus, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Sextus Empiricus: 1562, Sexti philosophi Pyrrhoniarum hypotypwsewn [sic]… interprete Henrico Stephano, M. Juvenum, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  72. Sextus Empiricus: 1569, Adver sus mathematicos, Gentiano Herveto Aurelio interprete…, M. Juvenum, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Cf. R.H. Popkin, History of scepticism, pp.68–69.

    Google Scholar 

  74. “Quanto usui autem esse possit Sexti Empirici commentarius ad tuenda Christianae religionis dogmata adversus externos Philosophos, pulchre docet Francisus Picus Mirandulanus in eo libro quo Christianam tueter philosophiam adversus dogmata externorum Philosophorum.” (Preface of Gentian Hervet to his translation of Sextus Empiricus: 1569, Adversus mathematicos, as quoted by C.B. Schmitt (1964), p.114.)

    Google Scholar 

  75. See Charles B. Schmitt: 1967, Gianfrancesco Pico della Mirandola (1469–1533) and his critique of Aristotle, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, pp. 172–174. Another author who might very possibly have drawn Gassendi’s attention to Pico was Giovanni Battista Bernardi, author of a dictionary of philosophical quotations entitled Seminarium totius philosophiae… (1582–1585)

    Google Scholar 

  76. cf. C.B. Schmitt, Idem, pp.170–171.

    Google Scholar 

  77. P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, pp.99–100.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Cf. the account of Pyrrhonic doubt given by Sextus Empiricus: “Chapter XXVI of the expressions “I am non-apprehensive” and “I apprehend not”. Both the expressions “I am non-apprehensive” and “I apprehend not” are indicative of a personal state of mind, in which the sceptic, for the time being, avoids affirming or denying any non-evident matter of enquiry, as is obvious from what we have said above concerning the other expressions.’ (Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, I.201.) The Pyrrhonisms manner of proceeding has been described as follows: “The Academician takes active part in philosophical discussion, maintaining a definite position, a standpoint; the sceptic in the sense of Sextus [i.e. the Pyrrhonist] has no position… Although he throws arguments into the discussion, he takes no part in it. Although he confronts the dogmatist with counterarguments, he does so without accepting any of them as true or valid.” (Arne Naess: 1968, Scepticism, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, p.4.) Cf. P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, I, p, 13b.

    Google Scholar 

  79. “Quantis Naturae Genius ab humano ingenio dissideret intervallis” (P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p.99).

    Google Scholar 

  80. “Aristoteles… adolescentes in thesi, non ad hunc morem philosophorum tenuitur disserendi: sed ad copiam rhetorum in utramque partem, ut ornatius et uberius dici posset, exercuit.” (P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p. 100) Gassendi referred to Cicero, probably De oratore (Loeb classical library edition), I, xi. 49–54, as his authority.

    Google Scholar 

  81. “Tarn indigna opera” (P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p. 101).

    Google Scholar 

  82. “Sed utcumque se res habeat: seu dogmatice quid defendo, seu sceptico more quid experior: et, seu profero quidpiam verum, seu quidpiam dico probabile…” (P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p.101.)

    Google Scholar 

  83. Cf. A. Naess, Scepticism, p.2ff.

    Google Scholar 

  84. “Paradoxa mea publice disputata sunt apud celeberrimos illos totius Provinciae consessus…” (P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, I, p.98.)

    Google Scholar 

  85. Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, 1.1.

    Google Scholar 

  86. “At vero nostrates philosophi, quorum princeps idem, philosophorum omnium facile sapientissimus, Aristoteles Stagyrites fuit.” (J. Vives, Opera omnia, III, p. 18.)

    Google Scholar 

  87. “Nullum videtur fuisse ingenium Aristotélico praestantius.” (Idem, III, P.25.)

    Google Scholar 

  88. “Nugatoria et praepostera doctrina valde ineptum, nee ulla fere parte Aristoteleum…” (P. Ramus: 1556, Animadversionum Aristotelicarum libri XX…, Bk. 3, p.97.)

    Google Scholar 

  89. “Detrahant a Grammatica omnia definitionum partitionumque lumina: pro exemplis elegantibus misceant abecedaria figmenta.” (Idem, Bk. 2, p.67.)

    Google Scholar 

  90. Idem, preface to Bks. 9 and 10. Cf. R. Hooykaas, Humanisme, science et réforme, p.13ff.

    Google Scholar 

  91. P. Gassendi, Opera omnia, III, p. 101.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1987 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brundell, B. (1987). Sceptical Anti-Aristotelianism. In: Pierre Gassendi. Synthese Historical Library, vol 30. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3793-2_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3793-2_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-8187-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-3793-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics