Keywords

These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

1  Introduction

From antiquity to the beginnings of the 20th century philosophers took ge­­ometry as the paradigmatic example of science. Geometry defined what was to be considered as scientific know­ledge. “More geometrico” was considered as a sign of quality for philo­sophical and scientific argu­mentation. At the beginning of the 20th century, the privileged philosophical status of geometry seemed to be as solid as it always had been. For philosophers such as Russell, Cassirer or Carnap, to name but a few, philosophical problems posed by geometry played a central role in their investigations – at least at the beginnings of their careers:

  1. (i)

    Russell started his philosophical career in 1897 with the dissertation The Foundations of Geometry.Footnote 1 A few years later, in The Principles of Mathematics he treated themes from ge­o­metry at great length.Footnote 2 In The Analysis of Matter Russell was engaged in using topological methods for the “logical analysis” of space and time.Footnote 3

  2. (ii)

    Throughout his life, Cassirer considered Klein’s Er­lan­gen Pro­gramme as a guide­line for the epistemology of his “Cri­­­tical Ide­alism” characterizing the task of epistemology as finding the ultimate invariants of scientific knowledge. In Sub­stanzbegriff und Funk­tions­begriff and much later in The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms he dedicated cen­­tral chapters to concept formation in geometry which he considered as a pa­ra­dig­matic case for concept formation in science überhaupt.Footnote 4

  3. (iii)

    Carnap’s first philosophical publication was his dissertation Der Raum. Ein Beitrag zur Wis­­sen­schafts­­lehre. Footnote 5 There he sought to establish the topological structure of space as a modernized version of a Kantian synthetic a priori. Moreover, the geometrical considerations of this work may be regarded as an important source for his later philosophy.Footnote 6

The high esteem of 20th century philosophy of science for geometry and, more generally, for mathematics, went well beyond the philosophical currents that in the following decades were to form analytic philosophy of science. For instance, also in phenomenology great emphasis was put on geometry as a paradigmatic example of scientific knowledge. This is evi­­denced not only by the work of Husserl himself but also by the contributions to a phenomenological philosophy of mathematics by mathematicians and philosophers such as Hermann Weyl, Dietrich Mahnke or Oskar Becker.Footnote 7 The same holds for some currents of Neokantian philosophy of science, for instance, the Marburg school of Neokantianism whose members, such as Hermann Cohen, Ernst Cassirer, and Paul Natorp, emphasized the role of mathematics in many works.

In sum, in the early decades of the last century, geometry certainly did not belong to the sciences “neglected by received philosophy of science” – on the contrary, at that time geometry was one of the hot topics of received philosophy of science.

This was soon to change, however. While geometry as a methematical discipline experienced a golden age during the 20th century mathematics, it lost its privileged status in philosophy. This became apparent first by the fact that traditional geometry’s most promising offspring – topology – fell into philo­sophical disregard. The philosopher’s traditionally high appreciation of geometry did not extend to topology as its modern successor. On the contrary, in the 20th century topology may be rightly characterized as a science “neglected by received philosophy of science”. Even more, the philosophical neglect of topology was just the harbinger of a fundamental sea-change in philosophy of science, namely, the substitution of geometry, and more generally of mathematics, as a core issue of philosophy of science, by logic. Painted with a broad brush the 20th century mainstream logical empiricist 20th century philosophy of science was a logic-centered philosophy of science, concentrating on logical questions concerning the logical structure of science.Footnote 8

Since from the mathematical point of view there is no essential epistemological, ontological, or methodological difference between geometry and topology, the negligible amount of attention that philosophy paid to topology in the last century must be attributed to a change in the way philosophers understood the aims and methods of philosophy of science. This renders philosophy’s neglect of topology an intricate problem for the history of phi­losophy of science.

For the following it is useful to distinguish between two dif­ferent aspects according to which the relations between traditional philosophy and geometry on the one hand, and between 20th century philosophy and topology on the other, differed from each other:

First, 20th century philosophy of science showed no interest in topology as an object of philosophical reflection. There has been no “philosophy of topology” in analogy to disciplines such as “philosophy of physics”, “philosophy of biology”, or “philo­sophy of geometry” (as it existed as a living philosophical discipline till the beginning of the last century). Second, traditionally geometry had also served as a source for inspiration and as an arsenal of conceptual tools for philosophy itself. This fruitful exchange did not find a continuation between the 20th century philosophy of science and topology. Ideas from topology hardly found their way in the conceptual tool kit of the philosopher of science.

My thesis is that this twofold neglect of topology by philosophy of science was just the first sign of a fundamental sea-change in philosophy of science, namely, the replacement of mathematics as a guiding science for philosophy by logic. Although the core disciplines of science were ma­the­­ma­­ti­zed sciences, mainstream philosophy of science was to treat science from an exclusively logical point of view. The disregard of mathematical, in particular geo­me­­trical and topological, aspects of science by philosophers of science was in stark contrast to the emphasis that they put on the logical aspects of the scientific enter­prise.

2  Topology as a problem for philosophy of science

What is topology? It goes without saying that a short paper like this is not the ap­­propriate place for answering this question.Footnote 9 As a mathematical discipline in its own right, recognizable also for non-mathematicians, topology came into being around the turn of the last century. Let us mention the names of Cantor, Poincaré, Frechet, and Hausdorff, to name just a few of the leading figures. Topological ideas and problems may be traced back, however, to Leibniz and Euler: one may think of the famous “Seven bridges of Kö­nigs­berg” or “Euler’s theorem” dealing with the relation between the vertices, edges, and faces of polygons, from which Lakatos squeezed so much juice for philosophy of mathematics.Footnote 10

In broadest outline, then, topology is concerned with the conceptual ana­ly­sis of spatial notions, such as “space in general”, “connectedness”, “neighborhood”, “ap­pro­­ximation”, “convergence”, “continuity”, “mappings”, “transformations”, “boundedness”, and many others. Evidently, these concepts may have had their origin in our daily experiences with physical space but they make sense far beyond the original Euclidean frame.

A first step to overcome the traditional Euclidean conception of space was to consider general metrical spaces:

(2.1) Definition.

A metrical space (X, d) is a set of points endowed with a distance func­tion d: X x X → R (R the real numbers) satisfying the axioms:

  1. (i)

    d(x, x) = 0.

  2. (ii)

    x ≠ y ⇒ d(x, y) = d(y, x) > 0.

  3. (iii)

    d(x, y) + d(y, z) ≥ d(x, z) (Triangle Inequality). ♦

The requirements (2.1) (i) and (ii) may be considered as almost analytical for any reasonable notion of distance, while (2.1) (iii) rather faithfully reflects a property of the Euclidean distance function.

A further, more radical step away from traditional geometry toward topology in its proper sense, was the generalization from metrical to general topological spaces that freed the topological, i.e. the spatial, from any vestige of a quantitative metric or distance function.

In the literature a variety of equivalent definitions of a topological space exists. Arguably, the following is the most common one:

(2.2) Definition.

Let X be a set and denote by PX the power set of all subsets of X. A topological space (X, OX) is defined as a set X with a class OX ⊆ PX, called the open sets of the topological space, that satisfy the following requirements:

  1. (i)

    X and the empty subset Ø are open sets.

  2. (ii)

    The union of any collection of open sets is open.

  3. (iii)

    The intersection of two open sets is open.

OX is called a topology or a topological structure on X. ♦

A metrical space (X, d) such as the Euclidean space is rendered a topological space by defining the metrical topology as the one that is generated by the “open balls”:

U(x, ε) :  = {y; d(x, y) < ε, x ∈ X and ε > 0}.

It should be noted that in general a set X, in particular the set of points of Euclidean space, can be endowed with many different topological structures OX. Among the many possible topologies on a set X one may mention the coarsest topology defined as O0X = {Ø, X} and the discrete topology defined as O1X = PX. All other topologies OX on X are “between” these two extreme topologies. More precisely, the topologies OX on X can be partially ordered by set-theoretical inclusion:

{Ø, X} = O0X ⊆ OX ⊆ O1X = PX

It would be an egregious error to take the profusion of possible topologies OX on X as evidence that the concept of topology is arbitrary and therefore trivial. The point of defining a topological structure on a set X is not to define just any one, but rather to define an interesting one. What is to be considered as an interesting topological structure highly depends on the specifics of the situation. It requires considerable skill and mathematical ingenuity to find “good” topologizations and to exploit them in a fruitful manner.

One of the early masters of this “art of topologizing” was the American mathematician Marshall H. Stone who obtained spectacular results by applying the new topological devices in many areas of mathematics, in particular in lattice theory and functional analysis.Footnote 11 Stone coined the maxim “You must always topologize”.Footnote 12 He con­ceived of topology as a universal method or per­spec­tive from which every mathematical problem should be looked at, i.e. all objects should be considered as topological ones. The topological was a kind of a general a priori form, under which mathematical objects and relations were to be perceived in order to reveal their essential aspects.

Perhaps one may say that Stone sought to conceive of topology as a generalized “transcendental aesthetics” roughly in Kant’s sense, based on a general topological a priori. The fruitfulness of Stone’s topological was amply demonstrated in many areas of 20th century mathematics.Footnote 13 Nevertheless, among philosophers his work has remained virtually unknown up to this day.

Since the axioms for a topological structure are extremely general, it is not to be expected that from them strong specific results can be obtained. Rather, an important task of topology is to single out appropriate special classes of topological spaces for which one can prove more specific results. For instance, the already mentioned metrical spaces are an important class, metrizable spaces and Hausdorff spaces provide more general classes, among many others.Footnote 14

Studying a topological space in isolation seldom yields interesting results. Rather, relations between topological spaces are of crucial importance. Hence the second fundamental concept of topology, which has to be mentioned, is that of a continuous map between spaces:

(2.3) Definition.

Given two topological spaces X and Y a set-theoretical map X—f → Y is called continuous (with respect to the topologies OX and OY defined on X and Y, res­pec­tively), if and only if for every B ∈ OY the inverse image f-1(B) = {a; f(a) ∈ B} is an element of OX. Roughly, then, (set-theoretical) topology may be de­­scribed as the theory of topological spaces and continuous maps between topological spaces.

After these preparations some important general types of topological problems may be described as follows:

  1. (i)

    Given topological spaces X and Y, can one prove (or disprove) that they are “equivalent” in a sense to be specified?

  2. (ii)

    Given topological spaces X and Y, does there exist a non-trivial continuous map X—f → Y?

  3. (iii)

    Can one find interesting invariants that can be calculated to characterize topological spaces in an efficient way (e.g. fundamental groups, higher homotopy groups, (co-) homology theories)?

For many, apparently “elementary” spaces these problems are still unsolved today.

3  Philosophers and topology: Some examples

Let us now briefly mention some of the few philosophical attempts to come to terms with topology. The most important example is certainly Russell but he was not the only philosopher who was interested in topology. For instance, Carnap in his dissertation Der Raum had proposed to save a Kantian synthetic a priori of space by conceiving of the metrical structure of space as a mere convention but retaining the topological structure of Euclidean space as a core a priori. This proposal seems not to have impressed his fellow philosophers. Moreover, Carnap himself gave it up soon after the publication of Der Raum. In the Aufbau traces of topology are still noticeable, but in his later work in philosophy of science topology and geometry does no play a role at all.Footnote 15 Cassirer emphasized in his philosophy of science the importance of geometry for philosophy of science, but offered only some general, passing remarks on the role of topology.Footnote 16 Compared with Carnap’s and Cassirer’s remarks Russell’s topological project was by far as the most sustained and detailed one. Russell developed his topological ideas with various degrees of precision and explicitness in several contributions, beginning with Our Knowledge of the External World, later in a more detailed way in The Analysis of Matter, and finally in On Order in Time. Footnote 17 Indeed, Russell sought to use the methods of topology for the core task of scientific philosophy, to wit, for logical analysis.

According to Russell the aim of logical ana­lysis was the elimination of sus­pi­cious or otherwise undesired entities from philo­so­phi­cal discourse. In Our Knowledge of the External World he sought to show by means of examples

the nature, capacity, and limitations of the logical-analytic method in philo­sophy. … The central problem by which I have sought to illustrate method is the problem of the relation between the crude data of sense and the space, time and matter of mathematical physics.Footnote 18

In other words, Russell proposed to apply topology as a means for the solution of a genuine philosophical problem, namely, the logical analysis and the elucidation of the complex relation between sense data and the mathematical conceptualizations of physics.

More precisely, Russell wanted to show that the basic mathematical structures of physical space-time – usually conceived of as structured sets of spatial and temporal points (instants) – could be logically reconstructed from ‘crude sense data’, later to be characterized as ‘events’. He credited Whitehead with the basic ideas of this approach:

I owe to Dr. Whitehead the definition of points, the suggestion for the tre­a­t­­ment of instants and “things”, and the whole conception of the world of phy­sics as a construction rather than an inference. What is said on these to­pics here is, in fact, a rough preliminary account of the more precise results which he is giving in the fourth volume of our Principia Ma­the­matica.Footnote 19

Regrettably, the announced fourth volume of Principia Mathematica never saw the light of the day. In Process and Reality Whitehead put forward something like a topo­lo­gical philosophy, but it was not more than a sketch and had no influence on mainstream analytic philosophy of science.

A more detailed account of the construction of points can be found in The Analysis of Matter; Russell’s last original work on the matters of points (more precisely on temporal points, i.e. instants) was “On Order in Time”. For instants as well as for spatial points Russell used the same con­­struc­­tional me­thod. His paper opens with the fol­­lo­wing contention:

[I]nstants are mathematical constructions, not phy­si­cal entities. If, therefore, there are instants, they must be classes of events having certain properties. For reasons explained in Our Knowledge of the External World, pages 116-120, an instant is most naturally defined as a group of events having the following two properties:

  1. (1)

    Any two members of the group overlap in time, i.e. neither is wholly before the other.

  2. (2)

    No event outside the group overlaps with all of them.Footnote 20

Intuitively, Russell’s sketchy construction of an instant may be described as an “onion con­struc­tion”, i.e., Russell defines an instant as the limit of a nested collection of temporal intervals. In modern terms, Russell’s construction resembles a construction of instants by maximal filters. In mathematically rigorous terms, such con­structions were carried out by Tarski and Stone around the same time. The crucial point in this con­struction was the existence of maximal filters (ultra-filters). Their existence can only be ensured by the axiom of choice or a similar principle as also Russell had noted. In other aspects, however, Russell’s constructions remained vague and even seem to be mathematically flawed in some respects.Footnote 21

Evidence that philosophy of science had actually lost contact with topology was that neither Russell nor any other philosophers of science ever took notice of the path-breaking work of the American mathematician Marshall H. Stone who in the 1930s proved one the most important theorems of the 20th century mathematics, to wit, Stone’s representation theorem. This theorem established surprising and deep relations between logic and topology, and it could have easily been used to secure what Russell sought to achieve, namely the construction of (temporal and spatial) points from temporal intervals and spatial points from spatial regions.

Despite his prominence as a philosopher, Russell’s excursions into topology did not arouse much interest among his colleagues. In the following decades philo­so­­phers now and then paid due reference to the later Russell’s talent for dealing with the conceptual tools of topology but his project did not find followers. Worse, no philosopher realized that Russell’s sketch of a topological logical analysis had long been superseded by the ongoing evolution of topology. It never occurred to the mainstream philosophers of science that meanwhile mathe­ma­ticians had produced much better topological tools than those that Russell had vaguely adumbrated. Topological and geometrical methods in philosophy of science showed up again only much later, and in a context quite unrelated to Russell’s original project.

4  The return of mathematical methods in philosophy of science

Russell’s attempt to introduce topological methods in philosophy of science for the logical analysis of philosophical and scientific notions remained unsuccessful. Under the reign of a reductionist logical philosophy mathematics, and a fortiori, geometry and topology, was doomed to be considered as irrelevant as an object and as a tool of philosophy of science:

  1. (i)

    Being allegedly reducible in one way or other to logic, mathematics ceased to be an interesting object for the investigations of philosophy of science in its own right. Rather, from the perspective of logical philosophy of science, the only philosophically interesting area of mathematics was its logical foundation. The huge rest of “real mathematics” was considered as philosophically uninter­es­ting, being relevant only for mathe­maticians or those who were concerned with its applications of mathematics.

  2. (ii)

    From the perspective of a strictly logical philosophy of science any project to use mathematics as a tool for philo­sophy of science made no sense. Tapping the conceptual sources of geometry and topology for understanding and elucidating the structure and the function of em­pirical theories seemed pointless. Rather, the only legitimate tool for phi­lo­so­phy of science was logic.

Through the decades the conceptual limitations of a strictly logical approach to philosophy of science became more and more visible. Even an arch logical empiricist such as Carnap came to admit that that logic of science might not be everything that philosophy of science had to say about science. He therefore proposed a kind of division of labour that proposed to complement the purely logical studies of science by other kind of investigations that dealt with the non-logical aspects of the sciences, for instance, history, sociology and psychology of science. Whether this plan is convincing need not be discussed here. Rather, I’d like to point out that also in this more liberal conception of philosophy of science the monopoly of logic for the study of the formal structure of science remained intact. That is to say, the tool for dealing with the formal structure of scientific theories continued to be logic and logic alone.

This contention, however, gradually lost unanimous agreement. Van Fraassen hails Patrick Suppes to have been the first who envisaged another way of dealing with the formal structure of science by questioning the basic as­sum­p­tion of received philosophy of science. More precisely, he diagnoses the fundamental error as having put too much emphasis on matters linguistic:

The mistake, I think, was to confuse a theory with the formulation of a theory in a particular language. The first to turn the tide was Patrick Suppes with his well-known slogan: the correct tool for philosophy of science is ma­the­matics, not metamathematics. This happened in the 1950s – be­witched by the wonders of logic and the theory of meaning, few wanted to listen.Footnote 22

In the decades after the 1950s the “semantic approach” in philosophy of science gained momentum. This is not to say that it could establish itself as a new unique orthodoxy. After all, Suppes’s general recommendation to replace logic by mathematics as the basic tool of philosophy of science could be interpreted in many different ways – and indeed it was.

Suppes himself preferred a set-theoretical approach that conceived of scientific theories as set-theoretical structures. More precisely, he proposed to describe empirical theories such as mechanics or optics in terms of set-theoretical predicates in an analogous way as from a set-theoretical perspective a mathematical theory such as the theory of groups may be described in terms of the set-theoretical predicate “… is a group structure”. Others, such as van Fraassen and Giere preferred a more geometrical account that reconstructed empirical theories essentially in terms of families of models or representations basically characterized by geometrical or topological structures, to wit, state spaces or phase spaces as the basic means for spatial representations in a generalized sense.Footnote 23

Theories offer something like conceptual spaces, patterns for spatial activities, or maps. Having a theory is having a map that can be used to guide one’s actions. Topology, as a general theory of space, investigates the structure of these generalized spaces. As long as one sticks to a narrow conception of (Euclidean) space this spatial characterization of a theory is doomed to remain vague and metaphorical, since clearly the “spaces” that are used in the various theoretical representations of science are not Euclidean ones. Here topology comes to the rescue, since it provides an ample spectrum of thoroughly analysized spatial concepts that can be used for this purpose.

5  Conclusion

Although in a short paper like this we had to leave out many details, it should have become clear that the philosophical vicissitudes of topology in 20th century philosophy of science offer a rich and multi-facetted agenda for history of philosophy of science that deserves further in-depth investigations. In particular the question why in the beginnings of the last century geometry lost its privileged status in philosophy and couldn’t pass it on to topology requires further investigations. A too quick and simplistic answer would be that topology did not appear on the radar of philosophy because it was too technical and inaccessible a discipline for philosophers to squeeze some philosophical juice out of it. This answer is not convincing. Philosophy of science was often prepared to invest a lot of conceptual effort to come to terms with the intricacies of modern formal logic – and it is not always clear whether this was worth all the effort. Many examples show that philosophy of science did not shy away from considerable technical labor to come to terms with, say, quantum theory or relativity theory.

In contrast, philosophy of mathematics succumbed to the vice of elementarism or fundamentalism, as one may call it. Philosophers of mathematics, who sub­scribed to this doctrine located the philosophical relevance of mathematics entirely in its foundations, be they be claimed to be of a logical or set-theoretical nature or of any other kind. Consequently, topology and other advanced areas of mathematics disappeared from the agenda of philosophy of science. Such an attitude starkly contrasted with that of philosophy of the empirical sciences.

Recently the situation has changed again. After logic had lost its monopoly in phi­losophy of science, a new “mathematical philosophy of science” has begun to gain momentum. At least partially this new mathematical philosophy of science is informed by ideas that have a close affinity to geometry and topology. In other words, after having overcome the neglect from classical logic-centered philo­sophy of science the philosophical vicissitudes of topology and geometry continue to be an inter­esting topic on the agenda of history of philosophy of science.