Keywords

These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Introduction: Different Representations of the Genetic Determinism

For many years, the teaching of genetics has only been centered on the determinism of the phenotype by the genotype as shown in Fig. 9.1.

Fig. 9.1
figure 00091

The most common representation of genetic determinism

This linear and deterministic representation is important in explaining what genetics is but is limited and even dangerous, at least in human biology and more generally. The human phenotype includes not only the anatomy and physiology of any person but also his/her appearance built during his/her life; his/her illnesses and health; and his/her behavior, emotions, intelligence, skills, and any other learned competence. Most of these features are sociocultural and cannot be reduced to genetic determinism. For the learner, these ideas must be introduced in a more systemic manner. This does not mean that the genome is not important in explaining some phenotypic aspects, but to reduce all the phenotypes to a genetic influence is more ideological than scientific, expressing innatist ideas, namely, hereditarianism.

Several works illustrate the danger of this deterministic reductive representation. For instance, to justify sexism, a sociological analysis showed the imprinting of innatist values (Nelkins & Lindee1995). These authors suggested a parallel between DNA and the soul:

Today, these are the genes that allow [us] to talk about personality traits, the nature of immortality, and the sacred meaning of life, in a way that resembles that of religious narratives […]. DNA took in mass culture, the aspect of an entity similar to the soul. (p. 67)

Other authors, in biology or in epistemology of biology, developed the idea that genes take the place of God to explain the determinism of human behavior and performances and that thegenetic program is a kind of predestination by God: Everything happening was written in advance (Clément & Castéra2007; Keller2003; Kupiec & Sonigo2000).

Innatist ideas were very strong during the first half of the twentieth century, with a large extension of the Nazis’ ideology. During this period, the research in genetics was growing and being structured in France into institutes ofgenetics and eugenics. More recent works—such as those of the psychologists Keller (2005) in Germany, or Dambrun, Kamiejski, Haddadi, and Duarte (2009) in France—showed that, even today, differences among genres or ethnic groups are often justified by this deterministic representation of genetics, which is therefore linked to sexism and racism.

The idea of environmental influence on human phenotypes and performances became nevertheless more and more accepted during the twentieth century. Consequently, the traditional debatenature VERSUS nurture was progressively replaced by a new representationnature AND nurture. Percentages of contributions from both genotype and environment were proposed, for instance, to explain intelligence from research on twins (see the famous fraud of Burt reported by Lewontin, Rose, and Kamin (1984)). This additional representation (genes + environment, see Fig. 9.2) is still very popular in students’ conceptions (e.g., Lewis2004; Lewis, Leach, & Wood-Robinson2000) and even in school textbooks and teachers’ conceptions (Clément & Forissier2001; Forissier & Clément2003).

Fig. 9.2
figure 00092

The additive representation of the genetic determinism (genotype + environment)

Nevertheless, this representation is scientifically incorrect because the genes and their environment cannot be added; rather they interact, as has been demonstrated by researchers in genetics (e.g., Jacquard1972). What is the part played by each in the development of the heart, the brain, or the liver in our body? When the genotype and the environment interact, it is impossible to evaluate their importance by a percentage. All biologists agree with an interactive representation shown in Fig. 9.3 (e.g., Atlan1999; Jacquard & Kahn2001; Lewontin2000).

Fig. 9.3
figure 00093

The interactive representation of the genetic determinism (genotype in interaction with environment)

However, the interaction can be more complex than that in the representation in Fig. 9.3, as, for example, Lewontin’s (2000) description inTriple Helix: Genes, Organism and Environment. Similarly, Forissier and Clément (2003) described three levels of interaction (see Fig. 9.4):

Fig. 9.4
figure 00094

Interactive representation with three levels of interaction (Adapted from Forissier & Clément2003)

  1. 1.

    Between the genes and their environment (epigenetics) (see Fig. 9.5)

    Fig. 9.5
    figure 00095

    Epigenetic feedback loops. Epigeneticssensu stricto (1) is the feedback involving DNA (e.g., methylation, histone acetylation). Epigeneticssensu largo (2) involves all the levels of feedback. At each level, there is an interaction between a biological organization and its environment (Modified from Atlan1999)

  2. 2.

    Between the phenotype and its environment, for example, when one has an accident resulting in amputation of one’s leg

  3. 3.

    Between (1) and (2), for example, genetic manipulation or the use of a diet without phenylalanine to correct the effects of the gene mutation that causes phenylketonuria (Jacquard1972)

Since the late twentieth century, the reductionist representation of genetic determinism—all by the genes—has declined (Atlan1999), giving more and more importance to the theories of complexity (Atlan1979; Morin1990) with the new paradigms ofemergence (Stengers1997) andepigenetics (Morange2005a 2005b; Wu & Morris2001). The interaction between the genes and their environment (see Figs. 9.3 and9.4) is now accepted by the scientific community opening apostgenomic period that follows the limited information from human DNA sequencing. The main results of the Human Genome Project were first published in the special issues ofNature andScience in February 2001. Most authors have insisted on the importance of interactions between several levels of biological organization, with DNA being one of these levels (Képès2005; Lewontin2000; see Fig. 9.5). Nevertheless, there are two kinds of definition and representation of epigenetics (see Fig. 9.5).

The strict scientific definition ofepigenetics (Pouteau2007, p. 155) is only concerned with the control of the activity of genes by chemical modifications of the DNA itself (e.g., by methylation) or of proteins of the chromatin around the DNA (e.g., histone acetylation). A broader definition of epigenetics is concerned with all the nongenetic processes which, in interaction with the genes, are acting to build a phenotype. This last definition does not differ from the notion of epigenesis used during the seventeenth century against thepreformationist ideas and was used again in the 1940s by Waddington for the nongenetic processes by which the phenotype is emerging (for Waddington, “epigenesis + genetics = epigenetics”) (Van Speybroeck2002). The humancerebral epigenesis is a possible illustration of this kind of emergence, by interaction between the human genes (as the basis of thecerebral ontogenesis) and other processes such as selection of neural networks by individual activity—natural selection of synapses (Changeux1983) andneural Darwinism (Edelman1987).

More generally, the concepts ofdeterminism orinstructions are much debated today in biology. The alternative representation, from the consensual schema of the Darwinian theory of evolution (see Fig. 9.6), shows that several different structures, coming from processes of differentiation, are selected by their interaction with the environment and only the most adapted ones survive. This schema is documented for the cerebral epigenesis, with a first step of having redundant innervations, some of which are then selected for differentiation when they become functional depending on the activity of the organism (Changeux1983; Edelman1987). More recently, this same schema exists for embryology and cellular differentiation, namely, cellular or molecular Darwinism (Gayon2009; Kupiec2008 2009; Kupiec, Gandrillon, Morange, & Silberstein2009; Pàldi & Coisne2009).

Fig. 9.6
figure 00096

Darwinian selection as an alternative to the biological determinism

In all these cases, stochastic processes are very important for the differentiation, even if they are in interaction with the preexisting biological structures. For instance, a mutation can be stochastic but dependent on the preexisting gene. Similarly, the first redundant synapses can be stochastic, but the functional synapse depends on the interaction between cells in a precise location and so on. The same stochastic processes exist in molecular and cellular biology for understanding cell differentiation, embryology, and other biological processes. Cell differentiation results from the general schema, shown in Fig. 9.6, of an interaction between stochastic processes and biological preexisting structures.

In consequence, any determinism seems to be a special case of a probabilistic phenomenon though the regularity of such emergence is not in contradiction with the stochastic processes. For instance, when tossing a coin, each event (head or tail) is totally stochastic but is regularly 50%/50% after a thousand tosses for a fair coin.

To summarize this part, Figs. 9.1 9.2 9.3 9.4 9.5 and9.6 illustrate possible multiple representations of genetic determinism. The additive representation in Fig. 9.2 is out of date because it is in contradiction with the process of interaction. Nevertheless, the other representations are never totally false. For instance, causal determinism of phenotype by genotype in Fig. 9.1 is often used by researchers who try to identify the genetic determinism of a precise feature; however, this procedure is dangerous and scientifically wrong when it reduces any feature and particularly any sociocultural human feature to genetic determinism. Moreover, any research in biology today focuses on the analysis of greater complexity more with a systemic approach including interaction between biological structures, between them and their environment, and also with stochastic processes.

The social challenges of these scientific debates about multiple representations of human genetics are very important for improving health as well as for arguing against fatalism and exclusion of citizenship based on sexism or racism. The dangers of innatist ideas have been stated by researchers in several countries—for instance, in the USA, by Lewontin et al. (1984), Lewontin (2000), Beckwith (1993), and Gould (1997); in the UK, by Rose et al. (1977); and in France, by Jacquard (1972), Clément, Blaes, and Luciani (1980), Stewart (1993), Atlan (1999), Kupiec and Sonigo (2000), Clément and Forissier (2001), Jacquard and Kahn (2001), Séralini (2003), and others.

In the second part of this chapter, we analyze the multiple representations of genetic determinism and discuss the related issues from two sets of data: (1) an analysis of genetic diseases in French textbooks and (2) an analysis of two indicators of genetic determinism (photos of human twins and the metaphorgenetic program) in biology textbooks of 16 countries.

Analysis of Genetic Diseases in French Textbooks

Human genetic diseases are frequently used as examples in chapters on genetics in French secondary school textbooks. But the choice of a particular example over another can significantly impact the message to the learner. For this reason, we chose to list genetic disease examples found in chapters on genetics in school textbooks and to explore the way these examples are presented. Do they illustrate genetic determinism in a strict reductive sense (see Fig. 9.1) or rather do they introduce more complexity and systemic approach—showing interactions between the genome and its environment (see Figs. 9.3 and9.4)—and possibly notions of epigenetics (see Fig. 9.5) or debates on genetic determinism (see Fig. 9.6)?

Every human genetic disease is the result of interactions between the genotype and its environment (Chakavarti & Little2003) even when they appear illustrative of a simple, linear model of genetic determination (see Fig. 9.1). For example, in the case of phenylketonuria (a monogenic disease), a special diet can completely prevent the occurrence of mental retardation. Furthermore, a genetic disease represents a malfunctioning of or mutation in one or multiple genes but is not always hereditary (Séralini2003). In our analyses, we separate genetic diseases into two large categories—monogenic diseases, caused by a mutation in a single gene, and polygenic diseases, where multiple genes play a role in symptom development (Swynghedauw2000). Our research addresses both monogenic and polygenic diseases as well as chromosomal anomalies.

We analyzed 18 biology textbooks, published by four different French publishers, containing chapters dealing with human genetics (Castéra, Bruguière, & Clément2008). As genetics is only taught in the last 4 years of secondary education in France (i.e., students aged 15–18 years), only these school levels were included in the study. The main results are now summarized in the following section.

The first result indicates that the examples of genetic diseases or anomalies present in the textbooks are not reflecting their prevalence around the world. Monogenic diseases, which are rare, are the most represented (between 51 and 91% of examples, depending on the school level; see Table 9.1). For instance, cystic fibrosis affects 1 in 13,000 births in FranceFootnote 1. Even the chromosomal anomalies are relatively rare (1 in 800 births in France has Down syndromeFootnote 2). On the other hand, polygenic diseases are much more frequent: One American in two and one European in three will develop a cancer during the course of his or her lifetime (Séralini2003). Also there were 177 million diabetic patients in the world in the year 2000, and, according to Shaw, Sicree, and Zimmet (2010), this figure was predicted to rise to 300 million by the year 2025.

Table 9.1 Occurrences of genetic diseases by both school level and type of genetic determinism in the school textbooks analyzed

The prevalence of examples of monogenetic diseases probably corresponds to textbook authors’ wish to present conceptual ideas as simply as possible for the youngest students (14–15 years old). They start with the visual images of the chromosomes of the Down syndrome, the definition of a gene as a portion of chromosome, and then as a portion of DNA—while the definition of a gene is currently under debate (e.g., Abrougui & Clément2005; Chevassus-Au-Louis2001; Keller2003)—and finally they introduce a clear example of a monogenetic disease such as Duchenne muscular dystrophy. Nevertheless, the danger of the choice of these examples is to deeply anchor the deterministic representation of Fig. 9.1 in the students’ minds.

More complexity is introduced to students of 15–16 years old, with nearly half of the examples dealing with polygenic diseases, and even sometimes with modulator genes. The main examples are diabetes (sometimes presented as monogenic in the previous school levels, but no more here), and half of the examples are cancers.

Environmental influence is rarely addressed in the school level3 ème and is included in no more than one-third of genetic disease examples presented in the textbooks for the school levels2 nde , 1 ère andterminale. These results demonstrate the predominance of simplistic, causal deterministic mechanisms of genetic diseases (see the representation in Fig. 9.1) in the French secondary school textbooks studied (Table9.2).

Table 9.2 Environmental influence on genetic disease examples

However, diseases significantly influenced by environmental factors (e.g., diabetes, cancers) are relatively frequent in textbooks for students of 15–16 and 16–17 years old. The presence of such examples contributes to a less simplistic representation of genetic determinism. As shown in Fig. 9.7, the environment is mentioned in the discussion of cancers and diabetes in more than 50% of cases studied. In case of monogenic diseases or chromosomal anomalies, the environment can influence a disease by rendering the disease either partially reversible (e.g., by means of an adapted education in the case of Down syndrome) or completely reversible (e.g., in the case of phenylketonuria); however, environmental influence is rarely mentioned in French textbooks. Such representation is only justified for cystic fibrosis and Duchenne muscular dystrophy, both of which are strongly subject to monogenic determinism. With regard to Down syndrome, only one textbook (Bordas publisher, levelTerminale scientifique) (Castéra, Bruguière, et al.2008) makes reference to environmental factors capable of influencing the disease, by clearly indicating that an education program may allow better integration of Down syndrome patients in society.

Fig. 9.7
figure 00097

Environmental influence in ten genetic disease examples in the analyzed French textbooks

This underrepresentation of the environmental influence in the examples of genetic diseases is consistent with the biomedical model of health predominating in French biology textbooks. In contrast, textbooks from other countries are more focused on the model of health promotion (Carvalho et al. 2008).

A final point is that not even one of the analyzed textbooks contained the wordepigenetics nor any one explained its content. Furthermore, there was no debate on the notion ofgenetic determinism and no mention of the possible alternatives as shown in Fig. 9.6. These new concepts and representations of the human genetics were too recent (1999–2005) to be introduced in the analyzed textbooks (published between 2001 and 2004). The Didactic Transposition Delay (DTD)—the time between the scientific publications and their introduction in syllabuses and textbooks (Quessada & Clément2007)—is longer, and we hope these new representations will be present in the more recently published textbooks.

Nevertheless, important advancements have been made since publication of the previous French curricula and biology textbooks in 1995 toward a less simplistic presentation of the causes of genetic diseases—no longer only limiting these diseases to a single gene (that was totally dominant in the previous textbooks; see Abrougui1997). In the new syllabuses, multiple genes, as well as the interaction between the genome and its environment, are presented. Complex determinism models for diseases (such as cancers or diabetes) help to prevent students’ minds from being ingrained with the single, oversimplified conception of genetics, which nevertheless continues to predominate in biology textbooks.

Images of Twins and the Metaphor Genetic Program in Textbooks of 16 Countries

The results presented here come from research in the context of the project BIOHEAD-Citizen (Biology, Health and Environmental Education for Better Citizenship) (BIOHEAD-Citizen2004–2008). This research project included a comparison of the biology textbooks dealing with six selected topics, one of which is human genetics.

We analyzed 50 textbooks in 16 countries (with number of textbooks analyzed given in parentheses): Cyprus (2), Estonia (2), Finland (2), France (11), Germany (3), Hungary (3), Italy (7), Lebanon (4), Lithuania (2), Malta (2), Morocco (2), Poland (1), Portugal (4), Romania (1), Senegal (1), and Tunisia (3). The number of textbooks studied in each country differed because (i) in some countries, human genetics was taught at only one school level, whereas in other countries, it was taught at two or more school levels; and (ii) in some countries, there was only one official national publisher for school textbooks, whereas in others, there were several private publishers. In the latter case, the most significant publishers were chosen. For each analyzed textbook, a long grid was completed. We present here only some results, dealing with two indicators.

First Indicator: Photos of Human Twins

Photographs are considered as scientific images because they convey a scientific message (Clément1996). In this specific case, the message is the morphological similitude of identical twins, which corresponds to the identity of their genotypes. In contrast, some images are intended to show morphological differences between fraternal twins. Nevertheless, the images of monozygotic twins—the same clothes, the same hairstyle, the same behavior, and so on—can also have an implicit ideological message when they strongly suggest that features other than morphological ones can be genetically determined. Consequently, for each image of twins in the textbooks, we examined whether the twins were presented as having the same clothes, style and behavior or, on the contrary, if the images showed differences illustrating theparadox of the twins—psychologists such as Zazzo (1984) showed that identical twins tend to differ in their psychological characteristics and sociocultural appearances. Identical twins are also a good illustration of possible epigenetic differences. For instance, Fraga et al. (2005) showed that in 35% of the monozygotic twins studied, there were differences in the methylation of their DNA and histone acetylation; these epigenetic differences are more important in the older twins and in twins with different lifestyle or medical history.

The results of the analysis are spectacular (Castéra & Clément2007; Castéra et al.2008; Clément & Castéra2007). In all the images of identical twins in the textbooks, twins had exactly the same clothes, hairs, and so on (except one case where the color of the jacket was different, as well as the length of the hair), whereas the images clearly differ for the fraternal twins. Consequently, for all these images, the representation of genetic determinism corresponded to Fig. 9.1 (“genotype → phenotype”) with, moreover, implicit innatist ideas that are not scientifically correct, suggesting that the sociocultural features (e.g., clothes, hairstyle) would be determined by the genes.

Second Indicator: Occurrence of the Metaphor Genetic Program

This hereditarianist expressiongenetic program now appears questionable. The deterministic representation of genetics (see Fig. 9.1) suggesting that everything of our life is written in our DNA program—as a predestination written in the plan of God for some religions—is no longer accepted by biologists (Abrougui & Clément1997; Atlan1999; Clément2007; Kupiec & Sonigo2000; Morel & Miquel2001; Noble2007). Consequently, Atlan and other authors proposed to replacegenetic program bygenetic information. Is the Didactic Transposition Delay (DTD) sufficient for observing a diminution or suppression of this expressiongenetic program in the analyzed textbooks? The results (see Table 9.3) showed important differences in using this expression among the textbooks of 16 countries. In the textbooks of some countries, the expressiongenetic program is very commonly used:

Table 9.3 Total occurrences of “genetic program” and some expressions with the same implicit meaning
  1. (1)

    The Maltese textbooks are in fact British textbooks published in 1986. At that time, the deterministic model was very popular in several countries (Abrougui1997). In these Maltese textbooks, the termgenetic program was not used, but the same message was in the expression: “the DNA molecule forms a code which instructs the cell” (10 occurrences in a textbook and one occurrence in another textbook for 15–16 year olds) (see Table 9.3). The message is that the cells could simply follow these instructions to produce the phenotype, just like a program.

  2. (2)

    In Finnish textbooks, we found a strong presence of the notiongenetic program: 70 occurrences versus only five occurrences ofgenetic information in recently published textbooks (2004 and 2006). So even though the scientific community no longer uses the expression genetic program the Finnish textbooks still do. In another work, we found a trend of the Finnish teachers’ conceptions clearly correlated with the implicit metaphorgenetic program (Castéra, Clément, & Kosonen2009).

  3. (3)

    In Portuguese textbooks, there is both a persistence of the notion of agenetic program with at least one occurrence by level and an absence of a clear evolution between the various levels. A possible explanation in this case is the difficulty in changing the scientific and ideological content of the chapter on human genetics.

  4. (4)

    In France, there are strong differences in the occurrences of this metaphorgenetic program among the textbooks from three different publishers and also across school levels (the higher the level, the fewer its use), and it completely disappears at the end of the curriculum. Compared to syllabuses and French textbooks published in the 1990s, the occurrence of the metaphor genetic program is very infrequent in today’s textbooks, with this being increasingly replaced by the notiongenetic information. Nevertheless, the disappearance of the term genetic program is not complete, suggesting the influence of other parameters. One parameter is pedagogical. Teachers start using genetic program for teaching the youngest students and progressively use genetic information more frequently. This initial simplification (to start with the messagegenotype → phenotype) is educationally dangerous; Clément, Forissier, and Carvalho (2003) showed that the first concepts taught are those most memorized by students. The second parameter is the different strategies among the publishers. Thirdly, it is also possible that the difficulty of completely suppressing the notion genetic program was because that this was extremely central in the previous syllabuses. Therefore, the textbook authors and publishers still use this notion with a certain difficulty to change theirtraditional way of thinking.

  5. (5) (6) (7)

    In Moroccan, Lebanese, and Senegalese textbooks, we found the same kind of results as in those in France, possibly indicating a French influence, but sometimes with delay. On the contrary, some countries do not use, or else very rarely use, the metaphorgenetic program in textbooks.

  6. (8)

    Tunisian textbooks use only the concept ofgenetic information throughout the three school levels where human genetics is taught. The total absence of the use ofgenetic program is probably a consequence of the growing influence of Tunisian researchers in didactics of biology (Abrougui1997). Nevertheless, that does not yet mean a total disappearance of innatist ideas from the Tunisian textbooks (Clément, Mouehli, & Abrougui2006) nor does it mean its disappearance from the Tunisian teachers’ conceptions (Kochkar2007 2010).

  7. (9)

    In Germany, the metaphorgenetic program is totally absent. As in other Western European countries and the USA, genetic research developed in eugenics institutes has the goal of building genealogical trees and tracking patterns of occurrence of diseases and disabilities (Wolf2002). According to O’Mahony and Schäfer (2005), the collective memory of the Nazis’ eugenics program is an important background for not referring to a genetic program in communicating about human genetics.

  8. (10)

    In Cyprus, the textbooks use exclusivelygenetic information: eight occurrences in the textbooks for 15–16 year olds and 17 occurrences in the textbooks for 17–18 year olds. The explanation is not easy: It can be an effect of the complex history of this country, as well as a desire to avoid using the metaphor of a computer program.

  9. (11)

    In the Italian textbooks, the precise expressiongenetic program, occurs only twice and just in one textbook. The textbooks generally use terms likehereditary patrimony andgenetic patrimony which are more neutral than genetic program, with less implicit meaning. This could show the same desire as in Germany being cautious in dealing with hereditarianist ideology. The common past of Germany and Italy during the Second World War certainly had an influence on the way human genetics was taught, albeit sometimes awkwardly. For example, in one of the textbooks, the metaphor ofthe books of life is used. According to this metaphor of the book of life, it would be enough to know the alphabet and the genetic syntax to reach the essence of the human being. Today, such a conception is scientifically unacceptable and ethically dangerous.

  10. (12)

    In the Lithuanian textbooks, there is just one occurrence that could be considered as a notion similar to genetic program: The reproduction of cells isprogrammed in genes, but there is never the precise expression:genetic program. In Lithuania, the explanation for this absence seems to be deeply rooted in the past: The notion was traditionally absent in the previous syllabuses and textbooks. We have verified this for textbooks published since 1979.

  11. (13) (14) (15)

    Estonia, Poland, and Hungary are three other countries included in or influenced by the former Soviet Union, and their textbooks show the same trend as in Lithuania: no one mention ofgenetic program, but several mentions ofgenetic information. Only one exception was found in a Hungarian textbook with the termprogrammed by a gene (exactly the same expression quoted above in a Lithuanian textbook). Our hypothesis is that in these countries, there was one official line to teach biology based on the work of Lysenko (Лысéнко) and Michurin (Мичурин) in the former Soviet Union, with a negation of the idea of a genetic program even if at the end of the 1960s, the pseudoscientific, neo-Lamarckism ideas of Lysenko and Michurin were rejected. The role of DNA in hereditary information was then accepted and presented in all textbooks. However, without the idea of a genetic program, and the differences between human individuals were also always explained by environmental or social conditions.

  12. (16)

    Romania also was formerly influenced by the Soviet Union; we found five occurrences ofgenetic program and 19 occurrences ofgenetic information in the unique Romanian textbook, dealing with human genetics (with only 13 pages devoted to this topic).

In conclusion, there were contrasting results from the biology books used in these 16 countries. In each country’s textbooks, the representations of identical twins were linked not only to a scientific message (morphological resemblance correlated with the same genome) but also to an implicit ideological message (a suggested genetic determinism of sociocultural features such as clothes or hairstyle). This kind of social representation of identical twins, deeply anchored in nonscientific ideologies, is in contradiction with the renewal of scientific knowledge in human genetics, such as the importance of epigenetic processes in explaining differences even between monozygotic twins.

On the contrary, there were interesting differences among the 16 countries in terms of the use in their textbooks of the metaphorgenetic program, which was sometimes replaced by another deterministic metaphor the books of life. Language is never neutral and the expression genetic information is less ideological than genetic program, less deterministic and more open to interactions with environmental and epigenetic processes from a systemic perspective. We suggest several hypotheses to explain the occurrence (or absence) of the metaphor genetic programin each of these 16 countries. They illustrate interactions between science (the taught science) and society (its history and other characteristics), as well as ethical, cultural, and social implications of this use, and interactions between the taught scientific knowledge (K) with implicit values (V) and social practices (P)—the KVP model (Clément2004 2006). As a general conclusion, the multiple representations of human genetic determinism in school textbooks not only correspond to the renewal of the scientific knowledge in human genetics but are also correlated with sociocultural parameters, values, and, social practices, which differentiate the way by which human genetics is taught in different countries.