Skip to main content

Time-Value in Economics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Economic Objects and the Objects of Economics

Part of the book series: Virtues and Economics ((VIEC,volume 3))

  • 302 Accesses

Abstract

Modern economics deploys the concept of time-value as if it were a descriptive, empirically-verifiable objective property of the sort studied by natural science in its investigation of the natural world. In particular, economics frames efficiency as a core feature of time-value understood in a purportedly descriptive sense. Economic time-value is stripped of its normative quality, and held up for scientific investigation and brute factual description of the sort associated with criterial and natural-kind concepts. As such, economics deploys the conceptual devices such as the “time-value of money” in its quest to objectively ascertain in a purportedly morally-neutral fashion behaviors that are favorable to capital efficiency maximization. Yet, as the paper shows, economics thus removes the relation of efficiency to time-value from the realm of normative choice – that is, from the realm of contested interpretive concepts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    In this paper I am discussing the concept of time-value in a wider sense than its narrow use in finance and banking that refers to the market value of an option over and above its intrinsic value. See, e.g., Oxford Dictionary of Finance and Banking. Oxford University Press. The broader philosophical concept of time-value that I exposit in a larger research project is that time depends on value, and value depends on time. There can be no valuation (whether economic, aesthetic, or moral) without time. While one may have a sense of timelessness when contemplating a masterwork of sculpture, the contemplation takes place within a duration of time. Conversely, there is no time without valuation; what appears to be “descriptive” or “factual” valuation is ultimately “prescriptive” and “normative.” Our virtually unainimous adoption of clocks and calendars is ultimately a convention that expresses a preference for using discrete equal units of fixed duration for counting time. Strictly speaking, there is no “law” of nature that dictates this choice.

  2. 2.

    “In reality the market lends more importance than is justified to the short-term future, ignoring the long-term damage this can inflict, particularly on relationships with workers, suppliers and customers” (Hutton and Jones, 2005 at 93).

  3. 3.

    “Investment and careful building-up of market share are sacrificed to boost profitability in the immediate future. It is the share price now that matters, not the higher return that could be achieved in five years’ time. In fact, the very structure of the financial economy prioritises short-term gain” (Hutton and Jones, 2005 at 92).

  4. 4.

    Cf. Aristotle, “Even God cannot change the past.” Nicomachean Ethics , Book VI, Sect. “Normative Dimension”, 1139b.

  5. 5.

    By ‘economic objects’ I mean abstract entities. Such thought-objects, as they occur in economic theory, purport to depict activities and events like ‘equilibrium,’ ‘demand,’ ‘marginal propensity to consume’, and so on.

  6. 6.

    As empirical research shows, if you offer someone the alternative of $100 now or $150 in 6 months, they will tend to prefer $100 now. People are inclined to prefer rewards in the present over rewards in the future. But notice that this is simply a conventional psychological tendency that does not settle the moral issue of how one ought to assign economic value across time orientations and time horizons. Presumably, in order to persuade people to place greater value on future rewards, the benefits associated with them need to be significantly greater than what is rationally expected.

  7. 7.

    Accounting for the nature of time itself is a highly complicated and contentious undertaking, exemplified in the vast philosophical literature on the ontology and metaphysics of time.

  8. 8.

    For an extended account of the idea of interpretation and interpretive concepts, see Dworkin, Justice for Hedgehogs (2011).

  9. 9.

    Economic efficiency denotes an economic state wherein resources are optimally allocated so as to serve each party in the best possible way, while at the same time minimizing waste and inefficiencies (allocational efficiency). In an economy that is economically efficient, any changes taking place to benefit one party will harm another (Pareto efficiency). Concerning production, efficiency implies that goods are being produced at the lowest cost, as well as the variable inputs of production (production efficiency).

  10. 10.

    The teletransporter puts one to sleep, then breaks one down into atoms, copying then relaying it to Mars at the speed of light. On Mars, another machine re-creates one’s body from local supplies of carbon, hydrogen, etc.) Every atom gets restored to precisely the same original arrangement. Parfit asks if teletransporter is a method of travel—if the person on Mars upon awaking is the same person as the individual entering the teletransporter back on Earth.

  11. 11.

    High Frequency Trading (HFT) involves the execution of complicated, algorithmic-based trades by powerful computers. The aim of HFT is to take advantage of minute discrepancies in prices and trade on them quickly and in huge quantities (MacKenzie 2011).

  12. 12.

    In economics, return on capital is a profitability ratio that measures the return that a given investment generates for capital contributors such as stockholders and bondholders. Return on capital is thus taken as a measure of how effective a company is at turning capital into profits.

References

  • Acocella, N. 1998. The foundations of economic policy: Values and techniques. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barenboim, D. 2008. Everything is connected: The power of music. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartels, D., and O. Urminsky. 2011. On intertemporal selfishness: The perceived instability of identity underlies impatient consumption. Journal of Consumer Research 38 (1): 182–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Begbie, J.S. 2000. Theology, music and time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blake, D., and J. Pickles. 2014. Value-Time Curve Psychology. Discussion paper PI 1403. http://www.pensions-institute.org

  • Catechism of the Catholic Church. 1994. Doubleday. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, M., A. Kumiega, and B. Van Vliet. 2012. Ethics, finance, and automation: A preliminary survey of problems in high frequency trading. Science and Engineering Ethics. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-012-9412-5.

  • Dworkin, R. 2011. Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S. 2006. Valuing future life and future lives: A framework for understanding discounting. Journal of Economic Psychology 27 (1): 667–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, P., and M. Sullivan. 2015. Against Time Bias. Ethics 125 (4):947–970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E.M. 2007. Socratic questions and Aristotelian answers: A virtue-based approach to business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics 78 (3): 313–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutton, W., and A. Jones. 2005. Time and money. In About time: Speed, society, people and the environment, ed. T. Aldrich, 88–105. Sheffield: Greenleaf Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, K.T. 2015. Aesthetics, human rights and economic life: Temporal perspectives. In Business and the greater good: Rethinking business ethics in an age of crisis, ed. K.J. Ims and L.J.T. Pedersen. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., and A. Tversky. 1979. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47 (2): 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keinan, A., and R. Kivetz. 2008. Remedying hyperopia: The effects of self-control regret on consumer behavior. Journal of Marketing Research 46 (6): 676–689.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewington, A., and E. Parker. 1999. Ancient Trees. London: Collins and Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G., and D. Prelec. 1991. Negative time preference. American Economic Review 81 (3): 347–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E.J. 1996. Subjects of experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie, D. 2011. How to make money in microseconds. London Review of Books 33 (10): 16–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scruton, R. 2016. Understanding music: Philosophy and interpretation. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S., and R. Swinburne. 1984. Personal identity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strotz, R.H. 1955-56. Myopia and inconsistency in dynamic utility maximization. Review of Economic Studies 23 (3): 165–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimbardo, P., and J. Boyd. 2008. The time paradox: The new psychology of time that will change your life. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kevin T. Jackson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Jackson, K.T. (2018). Time-Value in Economics. In: Róna, P., Zsolnai, L. (eds) Economic Objects and the Objects of Economics. Virtues and Economics, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-94529-3_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics