Skip to main content

A Philosophical Resonance: Hedwig Conrad-Martius versus Edith Stein

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Empathy, Sociality, and Personhood

Part of the book series: Contributions To Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 94))

Abstract

This article seeks to unearth the philosophical resonance of Hedwig Conrad-Martius’s ideas in Edith Stein’s thinking and thus to add an element of content to the better-known personal relations between the two phenomenologists. Here, resonance has two meanings. The first is phenomenological and appears as a manifestation of a spiritual communality between the two philosophers. The second relates to the constitutive establishing of a new hermeneutical framework from which new possibilities might emerge for understanding the ideas under discussion. The discussion starts with presenting Conrad-Martius’s and Stein’s basic stance regarding core metaphysical aspects that serve as an introduction to the idea of the I, the explication of which within the writing of both philosophers occupies the bulk of the article. The discussion presents the dual structure of the I in the thinking of both Conrad-Martius and Stein and analyzes their different stances toward it: While the former regards it as an utmost indication of the realism of the I, the latter illuminates its reconciliation within the Christian religious faith.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    References to the discussed or cited works appear in parentheses in the body text. All translations from the German original into English are mine. Emphases follow the original unless stated otherwise. The above quotation is taken from the ending essay (without title) by Conrad-Martius that was added to the volume of the collected letters of Stein to Conrad-Martius. The essay is based on a lecture that Conrad-Martius delivered to the Society for Christian-Jewish Collaboration. See especially, Conrad-Martius 1960: 74.

  2. 2.

    Herbstrith describes Stein’s stay with Conrad-Martius before her baptism, see: Herbstrith 1972: 24–25.

  3. 3.

    This recalls Levinas statement: “To meet a man is to be kept awake by an enigma”, however “Upon meeting Husserl, the enigma was always that of his work”, Levinas 1998, 111. Cited from: Kenaan 2016: 481.

  4. 4.

    I have addressed the issue of philosophical resonance regarding Husserl and other figures within the phenomenological discourse. See: Miron 2016a: 465–480.

  5. 5.

    For further reading about the relations between HCM and Stein, see: Avé-Lallemant 2003.

  6. 6.

    The above used expression “hermeneutical efficiency” is inspired by, yet not equivalent to, the Gadamerian ‘Principle of History of Effect’ (Wirkungsgeschichte) that requires “an inquiry into history of effect every time a work of art or an aspect of the traditions is led out of the twilight region between tradition and history so that it can be seen clearly and openly in terms of its own meaning”. See Gadamer 2004: 299.

  7. 7.

    Baseheart emphasizes Stein’s “divergence from Husserl who insisted on philosophy being radically new, a ‘science of beginning’” (Baseheart 1997: 23–24) and “rare respect for other thinkers – even for those with whom she differed greatly. Yet, Stein remained faithful to Husserl’s idea of presuppositionlessness, excluding preconceived theories and ‘naive’ premises” (ibid, 123ff).

  8. 8.

    HCM expresses her commitment to the “Existence thesis” also in: Conrad-Martius 1916a: 396; Conrad-Martius 1931a, 233.

  9. 9.

    See my discussion of HCM’s ontology in: Miron 2017: 99–101. See also: Mohanty 1977: 3–9. HCM later admitted that Husserl never rejected or doubted the reality of the world but regarded it as a hypothetical being (Conrad-Martius 1958: 398). However, unlike Husserl, HCM does not see any problem with the empirical experience (Conrad-Martius 1956a: 351) and even regards the then new natural sciences as elucidating the real foundations of such experience (Conrad-Martius 1958: 401).

  10. 10.

    See in particular: Husserl 1913: §§ 35–47. See Becker’s view that regards Husserl’s transcendental turn as a result of his reassessment of the issue of intentionality : Becker 1930. In this context, see also: Vendrell Ferran 2008: 71–78.

  11. 11.

    The letter is from 3 February 1917.

  12. 12.

    Stein’s words are cited from: Baseheart 1997: 32. Baseheart discusses there the complexity of Stein’s early relation to Husserl, establishing that: “[Stein] is simply making an honest effort to implement the methodology that Husserl had impressed on his pupils and that she could use it in a way that did not involve agreement with an idealist position. She appears to use the method not as an ultimate suspension of the natural belief, but as a legitimate method of rescinding from existence in the consideration of empathy” (ibid).

  13. 13.

    HCM cites these words from the theologian Peter Wust, to whose Book Dialektik des Geistes (Augsburg, 1928) she mentions as sharing the spirit of her discussion. See, Conrad-Martius 1932a: 261, note no. 6.

  14. 14.

    Both HCM and Stein relate to the orientation then called “the turning toward the object” (“Die Wendung nach Objekt”), which implied the reconsideration of the idea of “intention” as it appeared in Husserl’s Logische Untersuchungen. Moriz Geiger well characterized this orientation as follows: “Wenn die Zeit vorher fast allgemein die Gegenstände als Vorstellungen eines Ich ansah, so trat jetzt die Spannung zwischen Ich und Objekt wieder in ihr Recht. Das Gegenüber von Ich und Objekt und die Überwindung der Spannung – nicht durch Hineinnahme des Objekts in das Subjekt, sondern durch den Begriff der gegenstandsgerichteten Intention – das gab dem Aufbau der unmittelbar gegebenen Welt einen anderen Aspekt” (Geiger 1933: 13).

  15. 15.

    See also: Conrad-Martius 1932a; 257–258.

  16. 16.

    This determination relates to HCM’s writings from the 1940s, see: Pfeifer 2005: 87; Hart 1972: 545–638.

  17. 17.

    The expression perfectum opus rationis indicates a science of ultimate realities. This science is essentially incomplete not only because of the being of ultimate realities but also due to the restrictedness of the human mind. See in this regard, Lebech 2010: 146 f.

  18. 18.

    Stein related to the issue of the relation of philosophy and theology on other occasions. See for example: Stein 1987: 135–136, Stein 1929: 317–322.

  19. 19.

    See my discussion of “the gate of reality” in: Miron 2014.

  20. 20.

    HCM’s idea of reality assumes a fundamental structure of the real being that is composed of two inseparable constituents: the essence (die Washeit) or the “whatness” of the thing, and the “bearer” (Träger) (this term is discussed extensively in: Conrad-Martius 1916b: 407, 482, 497–498, 514, 525–526). The relation of the essence to its bearer is formal, hence it “cannot be destroyed”, and is reciprocal, i.e., the bearer is specified by the essence that in turn is carried to the extent that it specifies its bearer (Conrad-Martius 1923: 167–168).

  21. 21.

    Elsewhere, I have discussed at length the internal elements of being in HCM’s thinking. See: Miron 2016c.

  22. 22.

    To this extent, no difference separates the one who was raised as a Catholic and a person that, like Stein, made the decision to convert to Catholicism. I have discussed the affinity regarding the volitional choice between Stein and the Jewish thinker Yeshayahu Leibowitz. See: Miron 2016b: 119–124.

  23. 23.

    Calcagno well described the discussed aspect as follows: “What Stein experiences is not merely the gegebebheiten (givens) of the phenomenologist, but the plenitude omnitudinis (Fülle, or fullness) of creation” (Calcagno 2007: 127).

  24. 24.

    For further reading, see: Miron 2017.

  25. 25.

    For a comprehensive account of HCM’s philosophy of Being, see: Miron 2015; Miron 2014.

  26. 26.

    For further reading regarding the idea of “light” (Licht) in HCM’s thinking, see: Conrad-Martius 1938; Pfeifer 2005: 61–66.

  27. 27.

    It is worth noting that despite devoting a special attention to the word I, Stein, unlike HCM, uses the word ego rather often. It seems that this choice relates to Stein’s greater ambivalence in regarding Husserl’s stance, as opposed to HCM, who explicitly and remarkably distances herself from the founding father of phenomenology: “The entire physical, mental (psychische), empirical, and ideal or categorical world in Husserl’s phenomenology – be it individual or collective - must descend backwards into the subjective in order to arrive at the mysterious ‘Ego’, out of whose living ‘activity’ the entire validity of Being and meaning is plainly deducible. […] We cannot go back to this ego” (Conrad-Martius 1958: 400). See Ales Bello’s interpretation of Stein’s idea of the ego as closely related to Husserl, Ales Bello 2008.

  28. 28.

    Stein discusses at length the various aspects of the internal element of the human subject, see: Stein 1922: II 2.3c (159–166). Ales Bello suggested a detailed discussion of Stein’s concept of the soul that is composed of several meanings: psyche, unity of spirit and psyche, an entire autonomous aspect of the human subject. See: Ales Bello 2008: 152.

  29. 29.

    See here the entire section “I, Soul. Person”, in: Stein 2002: 374–380.

  30. 30.

    The translation of the citation is taken from, Schulz 2008: 168.

  31. 31.

    The translation of the citation is taken from, Schulz 2008: 170.

  32. 32.

    Schulz argued that in Finite and Eternal Being Stein uses the concept of the “person” to indicate the ontology of spirit. See: Schulz 2008: 170. See also ibid., 173–173.

  33. 33.

    See also: Conrad-Martius 1948: 111.

  34. 34.

    This insight surely enables Stein to maintain a close and complex dialogue with Husserl. Ales Bello and Baseheart stress the continuity, while Schulz emphasizes the divergence.

  35. 35.

    See in this context Ales Bello’s interpretation according to which Stein is not interested in describing the tension between the internal or “center” and the external or “periphery” but in a “balanced vision of human being” (Ales Bello 2008: 156).

  36. 36.

    For Stein’s use of the image of “apartment”, see: Alfieri 2012: 37; Miron 2013: 102. The consolidation of the most private and personal together with the most spiritual and lofty in Alfieri’s idea of apartment throws much light on Edith Stein ’s analogy between the individual personality and the community . See: Stein 2004. For further reading, see: Calcagno 2007: 25–44; Baseheart 1997: 30–75.

  37. 37.

    Elsewhere I designated the thinking of Stein as “radicalism of immanence”. See: Miron 2016b: 140.

  38. 38.

    The secondary literature that is mentioned in the footnotes can be considered as representative of this view of Stein’s thinking.

  39. 39.

    In cases of difference between the time of creation and publication, the year mentioned first within square brackets is the year of the work’s writing, while the second year denotes the year of publication. Archive materials are taken from the Munich Estate Archive, Die Nachlässe der Münchener Phänomenologen, Die Bayerische Staatsbibliotheck, München (BSM). The signification of these material is with the letter ‘N’ attached to the year.

References

  • Ales Bello, A. 2008. Edmund Husserl and Edith Stein: The Question of the Human Subject. Trans. Calcagno A. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 82/1: 143–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alfieri, F. 2012 Die Rezeption Edith Steins. Internationale Edith-Stein-Bibliographie 1942 –2012. Festgabe für M. Amata Neyer OCD. Würzburg, Echter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Avé-Lallemant, E. 2003. Edith Stein und Hedwig Conrad-Martius – Begegnung in Leben und Werk. In Edith Stein, Themen-Bezüge-Dokumente, ed. B. Beckmann and H.B. Gerl Falkovitz. Würzburg: Kӧnigshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baseheart, M.C. 1997. Person in the world, introduction to the philosophy of Edith Stein. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, O. 1930. Die Philosphie Edmund Husserl’s. Kantstudien 35: 119–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calcagno, A. 2007. The Philosophy of Edith Stein. Pittsburg: Duquesne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. 1916a. Über Ontologie. Conrad-Martiusiana: AI3, 1-14, Bavarian State Archive (BSM), Munich, Nachlass.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1916b. “Zur Ontologie und Erscheinungslehre der realen Außenwelt”, Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 3 (Halle, 1916 [1913]).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1923. Realontologie [1923], special print in Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung VI (Halle: Max Niemeyer, 1924), 159–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1931a. “Seinsphilosophie”. Schriften zur Philosophie, vol. 1, [1931] 1963. München: Kösel, 15–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1931b. Seins und Nichts, Schriften zur Philosophie, vol. 1, [1931] 1963. Kösel, München, 89–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1931c. Entwurf zu einer universalen Schematik realen Seins, BSM, Nachlass AII2: 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1932a Die Fundamentale Bedeutung eines substanziellen Seinsbegriffs für eine theistische Metaphysik, Schriften zur Philosophie, vol. 1. Kösel, München 1963 [1932], 257–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1932b. Was ist Metaphysik? Schriften zur Philosophie, vol. 1. Kösel, München 1963 [1931], 38–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1932c. Dasein, Substantialität, Seele. Schriften zur Philosophie, vol 1., [1932] 1963. Kӧsel, Munich, 194–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1963. Existentialle Tiefe und Untiefe von Dasein und Ich, Schriften zur Philosophie, vol. 1. München: Kösel 1963 [1934], 228–244. (Conrad-Martius 1934).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1938 Licht und Geist, Schriften zur Philosophie, 3 vols. (Munich: Kӧsel-Verlag, 1965 [1938]), Vol. 3, 261–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1948. Seele und Leib. Schriften zur Philosophie, vol. 3 [1948] 1965, Kösel, München, 107–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1956a. Über das Wesen des Wesens. Schriften zur Philosophie, 3 vols. Kӧsel-Verlag, Munich 1965 [1956], Vol. 3, 335–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1956b/1965. Wirkender und Empfangender Geist. Schriften zur Philosophie, vol. 3. München: Kösel, 295–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1956c. Phänomenologie und Spekulation. Schriften zur Philosophie, vol. 3, München: Kösel-Verlag, [1956] 1965, 370–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1957. Das Sein. Kӧsel-Verlag, Munich.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1958. Die transzendentale und die ontologische Phänomenologie, Schriften zur Philosophie, vol. 3. Kösel-Verlag, München, 1965 [1958], 393–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1960. Edith Stein, Briefe an Conrad-Martius Hedwig. München: Kӧsel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H-G. 1933/2004. Truth and Method Second Revised edition. Trans. Weinsheimer J and Marshall DG). Continuum, London/New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geiger, M. 1933. Alexander Pfaender methodische Stellung. Neu Muenchener Philosophiche Abhandelungen, Leipzig.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, JG. 1972. Hedwig Conrad-Martuis’ Ontological Phenomenology (diss). Chicago, Illinois.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbstrith, W. 1972. Edith Stein, Teresia a Matre Dei OCD. Freising: Kyrios.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 1971/1983 Das Wahre Gesicht Edith Steins. Kaffke, München, Freising.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1913/2012 Ideas, General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Trans. Boyce Gibson WR, Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenaan, H. 2016. Husserl and Levinas: The ethical structure of a philosophical debt. The European Legacy 21 (5–6): 481–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lebech, M. 2010. Beginning to read Stein’s Finite and Eternal Being. In Phenomenology 2010, 4, Traditions, Transitions and Challenges, Zeta, ed. N. Dermot Moran and H. Reiner Sepp, 138–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. 1998. The Ruin of Representation. In Discovering Existence with Husserl. Trans. Cohen RA and Smith MB. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miron R. 2013. Untitled book review of Alfieri (Alfieri, 2012). Iyyun, The Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly 62 (January 2013): 98–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miron, R. 2014. The gate of reality – Hedwig Conrad-Martius’ Idea of Reality in ‘Realontologie’. Phänomenologische Forschungen: 59–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. The vocabulary of reality. Human Studies 38 (3): 335–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016a “Introduction” and “Husserl and other phenomenologists”. In: Miron R (ed.), Husserl and Other Phenomenologists, a special issue of The European Legacy, 21, 5–6: 465–466, 467–480. (This issue is forthcoming as an independent volume with the same title by Routledge, 2018).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016b. Faith and Radicalism: Edith Stein vis-à-vis Yeshayahu Leibowitz. The Review of Rabbinic Judaism 19: 118–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miron R 2016c In the Midst of Being – The Journey into the Internality of Reality in Hedwig Conrad-Martius’ Metaphysics. Phenomenological Ontologies: Individuality, Essence and Idea, special issue of Discipline Filosofiche, 26/1: 232–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miron, R. 2017. The Ontological Exclusivity of the I, Phänomenologische Forschungen: 97–116..

  • Mohanty, J. 1977. Phenomenology: Between Essentialism and Transcendental Philosophy. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer, A.E. 2005. Hedwig Conrad-Martius, Eine Phänomenologische sicht auf Nature und Welt, Orbis Phenomenologicus. Würzburg: Kӧnigshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, P.J. 2008. Toward the subjectivity if the human person: Edith Stein’s contribution to the theory of identity. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 82 (1): 161–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharkey, S.B. 2008. Edith Stein and Thomas Aquinas on being and essence. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 82 (1): 87–013.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. 1922. Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der Geistwissenschaften, I, Psychische Kausalitat, Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, V: 1–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1929. Husserl’s Phänomenologie und die Philosophie des hl. Thomas V. Aquino. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phaenomenologische Forschung, Festschrift Edmund Husserl (zum 70, Geburtstag gewidmet): 315–338, Halle.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1946. Ways to know god – The ‘Symbolic Theology’ of dionysius. The areopagite and its factual presuppositions. The Thomist IX (1): 379–420.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1962. Welt und Person, Beitrag zum chreistlichen Wahrheitstreben. Nauwelaerts and Herder, Louvain Freiburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 1970/1989 On the Problem of Empathy. Translation of Zum Problem der Einfiihlung by Stein W. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 2nd ed., 1970. Revised ed.: Collected Works of Edith Stein, III. ICS Publications, Washington, D.C. (Stein 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. Essays on the Woman [Die Fraus]. Trans. Oben FM. Collected Works of Stein Edith, II, ICS Publications, Washington, DC.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 1991. Einführung in die Philosophie, Edith Steins Werke, XIII, 1991. Herder, Freiburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———.1993. Erkenntniss und Glaube, Edith Steins Werke, XV. Herder, Freiburg, Basel Wien.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Finite and Eternal Being, An Attempt at an Ascent to the Meaning of Being. Trans. Reinhardt KF. ICS Publications, Institute of Carmelite Studies, Washington DC.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2004. Der Aufbau der menschlichen Person. Vorlesung zur philosophischen Antropologie,” Neu bearbeitet und eingeleitet von B. Beckmann-Zӧller, ESGA XIV, Freiburg-Basel-Wien: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Self Portrait in Letters: Letters to Roman Ingarden, The collected works of Edith Stein, volume 12. ICS publications, Institute for Carmelite Studies, Washington, DC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vendrell-Ferran Í 2008 Die Emotionen, Gefühle in der realistischen Phänomenologie. Akademie, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ronny Miron .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Miron, R. (2017). A Philosophical Resonance: Hedwig Conrad-Martius versus Edith Stein. In: Magrì, E., Moran, D. (eds) Empathy, Sociality, and Personhood. Contributions To Phenomenology, vol 94. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-71096-9_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics