Skip to main content

The Other’s Place in the Space of the Relation: Karl Löwith and Martin Buber as Theorists of Duheit

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Changing Faces of Space

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 39))

Abstract

This paper addresses the issue of human spatiality as existential givenness, taking as its fundamental orientation relationality, namely the natural tendency towards the other as my co-man (Mitmensch) for the purposes of instituting, together with him, the first place for such a spatiality : the being-with-one-another (Miteinandersein). If the being-with-one-another embodies the first place of this spatiality, then the encounter between an I and a you—that is to say, otherness declined in the second person, as Duheit—represents the culmination of such a place . On this basis the τόπος of the Miteinandersein emerges as an οἶκος and the achievement of such an ‘oikological’ rank makes the space of the relation a real Lebensraum, a living space. Given these assumptions, a comparison will be offered between two paradigmatic modes of interpreting Duheit, the outcomes of a short season in which continental philosophy questioned itself on this issue with unusual urgency and depth . On the one hand, the Zwischenontologie (“Between-ontology”) of Martin Buber, on the other, the Mitanthropologie (“With-anthropology”) of Karl Löwith . The comparison here proposed will reveal that the philosophical question of otherness is essentially a matter of measure, namely that the promotion of the space of the relation established by I and you to the rank of οἶκος and Lebensraum depends on its ability to stay within the limit of an anthropic perimeter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The current English translation of the German ‘Mitmensch’ is ‘fellow man’. In this case I prefer a more literal rendering, albeit one that is less grammatically correct: ‘co-man’ (Mit-Mensch), since in the economy of my discourse (as will be seen particularly in the lines dedicated to the illustration of Mitanthropologie) this term will designate the human being exclusively as a ‘relational being’, a ‘man-with-men’.

  2. 2.

    Zwischenontologie, literally translated, means ‘Between-ontology’, while Mitanthropologie is, literally, ‘With-anthropology’ [Translator’s note].

  3. 3.

    Therefore, I refer the reader to the main stages of this path of research in order to deepen the many themes that, for obvious reasons, will only be spoken of in passing here. In the first place: Cera (2010). Also: Cera (2007) and Löwith (2007). The comparison between Löwith and Buber was made in a first and larger version in Cera (2013).

  4. 4.

    See Löwith (1928). The version now included in Sämtliche Schriften (Löwith 1981), refers to the Second Edition, slightly revised, from 1962 (Löwith 1962). The textual references from the present paper will refer to this edition. In 2013 the text was reprinted in a single edition, preceded by a useful introduction of Giovanni Tidona (2013).

  5. 5.

    On this topic see Cera (2010: 283–311).

  6. 6.

    The first chapter of IRM is dedicated to a “re-enactment” of Principles (see Löwith 1981: 20–28).

  7. 7.

    As is known, Plessner characterizes the human being as “exzentrische Positionalität”. See Plessner (1981).

  8. 8.

    This is a partial translation of the original German edition (Theunissen 1977), to which, where necessary, I will make direct reference.

  9. 9.

    Buber presents a brief but dense survey of dialogicalism in Buber (1954). John Cullberg offers an in-depth real-time reconstruction (we are in 1933) of the “I-thou problem in the ontology of the present” (Cullberg 1933: 18–169). However, the historical reconstruction of reference is found in the now classic Casper (1967), next to which should be mentioned: Böckenhoff (1970). A more theoretical approach is proposed by the dialogical section of Theunissen’s book (Theunissen 1977: 242–373; partial translation in Theunissen 1984: 257–344). Among the publications of recent years: Wojcieszuk (2010) and Heinze (2011).

  10. 10.

    These pages are discussed in Löwith (1981: 145–147).

  11. 11.

    See Buber (1923). On the pre-dialogical stage of Buberian thought see Casper (1967: 17–65). Inaugurated ‘officially’ with Ich und Du, the dialogical turn is heralded in Buber (1919).

  12. 12.

    The bond between Löwith and Buber (between IRM and dialogicalism) has been addressed by the South Korean researcher Choi Sung-Sik (Choi 1993). However, since the author aims at an enrichment of the philosophical debate in his country—traditionally monopolized by the communitarian dimension of the ‘we’—through the engagement of the ‘Western category’ of Duheit, his interest focuses more on an exposition of Löwith’s and Buber’s positions than on their comparative analysis.

  13. 13.

    For purposes of clarification, it should be said that Löwith probably did not know Ich und Du at the time of preparing IRM, since although he discusses the positions of Ebner, Gogarten and Scheler, he does not make a single mention of it. It appears only fleetingly in the preface to the second edition (1962), in a list of references relating to the themes of Mitwelt and Mitmenschlichkeit, prepared by the author precisely to make up for a lack in the first edition (see Löwith 1981: 14).

  14. 14.

    That the renewed philosophical interest in the relational dimension should be ascribed to Feuerbach’s Principles is an assumption shared by all the thinkers linked to Dialogismus.

  15. 15.

    In 1936 Buber devoted an essay to the “Single One” (der Einzelne) of Kierkegaard (Buber 1936: 46–97). To the same theme is dedicated § 44 of IRM (Löwith 1981: 190–194).

  16. 16.

    For responsibility in Buber, see the section Responsibility (Verantwortung) in the essay Dialogue (Zwiesprache) (Buber 1929: 18–20). For the concept of responsibility in IRM see Löwith (1981: 125–133 and 185–187).

  17. 17.

    Both refer to the Humboldtian essay of 1827 Über den Dualis (Humboldt 1997) focused precisely on the distinction between “you” and “he”.

  18. 18.

    The cosmocentric turn of his anthropology also coincides with the re-evaluation of the Unmittelbarkeit in a Feuerbachian key. On this topic see Löwith (1988).

  19. 19.

    Theunissen recognizes the philosophically spurious character of the Buberian analysis, since “the thought about the ‘dialogical principle’ springs not from a metaphysical experience but from an ‘experience of faith’ and must, for this reason, first be translated into philosophical concepts. Such a translation is necessarily inadequate” (Theunissen 1984: 269–270). See also Theunissen (1964).

  20. 20.

    The time proper to the I-It bond, one that generates the world as experience, is the past (see Buber 1970: 55–56). On Gegenwärtigkeit (presentness), as the eminent character of Buberian ontology, Casper insists (see Casper 1967: 278–279).

  21. 21.

    See the famous work of 1949, which originally appeared in English during Lowith’s ‘exile’ in USA (Löwith 1957).

  22. 22.

    Although the explicit elaboration of the category of the Zwischen would take place only in a course held in Jerusalem in 1938 and published in 1943: What is Man? (Buber 1943), it is beyond dispute that the system of dialogicalism has always rested on these theoretical assumptions, beyond their explicit formalization.

  23. 23.

    A critique to which, however, Ferdinand Ebner exposes himself (see Casper 1967: 259–269).

  24. 24.

    On the Löwithian skeptical ethos see Cera (2011).

  25. 25.

    Theunissen speaks of a Theologie des Zwischen: “the purpose, exceeding the philosophy, of Buber's dialogicalism” (Theunissen 1977: 330 and 330–346).

  26. 26.

    The analysis of Heidegger’s Mitsein is proposed in § 21 of IRM (Löwith 1981: 96–98). On Löwith’s critiques of the layout of existential analytics see Theunissen (1977: 413–420), Koltan (2011), Cera (2010: 99–159). For a comparison between Buber and Heidegger on the subject of Duheit see Gordon (2001).

  27. 27.

    Quote from the Afterword to the 1957 edition of I and Thou (Buber 1970: 164–165).

  28. 28.

    Even Lévinas expressed himself in a critical manner regarding the extension of the ‘you’ to things (see Lévinas 1967).

  29. 29.

    The two definitions, quoted by Theunissen (1977: 2), are respectively by Husserl and Rosenstock-Huessy.

References

  • Böckenhoff, J. (1970). Die Begegnungsphilosophie. Ihre Geschichte. Ihre Aspekte. Freiburg/München: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (1919). Worte an die Zeit. Eine Schriftenreihe, Heft 1: Grundsätze. Munich/Zürich/Vienna: Dreiländer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (1923). Ich und Du. Leipzig: Insel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (1929). Dialogue. In Buber 2002 (pp. 1–45).

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (1936). The question to the single one. In Buber 2002 (pp. 46–97).

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (1943). What is man? In Buber 2002 (pp. 140–244).

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (1954). The history of the dialogical principle. In Buber 2002 (pp. 249–264).

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. (2002). Between man and man (M. Friedman, Trans.). London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. [1923] (1970). I and thou (W. Kaufmann, Trans.). New York: Scribner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buber, M. [1950] (1965). Distance and relation (Urdistanz und Beziehung). In M. Buber (Ed.), The knowledge of man (M. Friedman, Trans.) (pp. 59–71). London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casper, B. (1967). Das dialogische Denken. Eine Untersuchung der religionsphilosophischen Bedeutung Franz Rosenzweigs, Ferdinand Ebners und Martin Bubers. Freiburg/Basel/Wien: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cera, A. (2007). Introduzione. In Lowith 2007 (pp. 5–50).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cera, A. (2010). Io con tu. Karl Löwith e la possibilità di una Mitanthropologie. Napoli: Guida.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cera, A. (2011). Esistenza teorica e virtù della scepsi. L’ethos filosofico di Karl Löwith. In P. Amato, M. T. Catena & N. Russo (Eds.), L’ethos teoretico. Scritti per Eugenio Mazzarella (pp. 213–231). Napoli: Guida.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cera, A. (2013). Mitanthropologie, Zwischenontologie. L’antropologia löwithiana a confronto con il dialogismo di Martin Buber. La Cultura, 51, 251–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choi, S.-S. (1993). Der Mensch als Mitmensch. Eine Untersuchung über die Strukturanalyse des Miteinanderseins von Karl Löwith im Vergleich mit dem dialogischen Denken von Martin Buber (Dissertation). Köln.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cullberg, J. (1933). Das Du und die Wirklichkeit. Zum ontologischen Hintergrund der Gemeinschaftskategorie. Uppsala: Lundequistska.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feuerbach, L. [1843] (1986). Principles of the philosophy of the future (M. H. Vogel, Trans.). Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, H. (2001). The Heidegger-Buber controversy: The status of the I-thou. Westport/London: Greenwood.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. [1927] (2001). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinze, E.-M. (2011). Einführung in das dialogische Denken. Freiburg/München: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koltan, J. (2011). Der Mitmensch. Zur Identitätsproblem des sozialen Selbst ausgehend von der Frühphilosophie Martin Heideggers und Karl Löwiths. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévinas, E. [1963] (1967). Martin Buber and the theory of knowledge. In P. Arthur Schilpp & M. Friedman (Eds.), The philosophy of Martin Buber (pp. 133–150). La Salle (Illinois): Open Court Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith, K. (1928). Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen. Ein Beitrag zur anthropologischen Grundlegung der ethischen Probleme. München: Drei-Masken Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith, K. (1962). Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen. Ein Beitrag zur anthropologischen Grundlegung der ethischen Probleme. Freiburg/München: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith, K. [1928 & 1962] (2007). L’individuo nel ruolo del co-uomo (A. Cera, Trans.). Napoli: Guida.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith, K. [1949] (1957). Meaning in history. The theological implications of the philosophy of history. Chicago/London: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith, K. [1962] (1981). Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen. In K. Löwith, Sämtliche Schriften Band 1. Beiträge zur Anthropologie, hrsg. von K. Stichweh (pp. 9–197). Stuttgart: Metzler (original edition: Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  • Löwith, K. [1967] (1988). Vermittlung und Unmittelbarkeit bei Hegel, Marx und Feuerbach. In K. Löwith, Sämtliche Schriften Band 5: Hegel und die Aufhebung der Philosophie im 19. Jahrhundert – Max Weber, hrsg. von B. Lutz (pp. 186–220). Stuttgart: Metzler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plessner, H. [1928] (1981). Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch. Einleitung in die philosophische Anthropologie. In H. Plessner, Gesammelte Schriften IV, hrsg. von G. Dux et al. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenzweig, F. [1921] (1971). The star of redemption (W. V. Hallo, Trans.). New York/Chicago: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenzweig, F. [1925] (1999). “The new thinking”: A few supplementary remarks to the star of redemption. In A. Udoff & B. Galli (Eds.), Franz Rosenzweig’s “the new thinking” (pp. 67–102). Syracuse: Syracuse University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. [1912] (1973). The idols of self-knowledge. In M. Scheler (Ed.), Selected philosophical essays (D. Lachterman, Trans.) (pp. 3–97). Northwestern University Press: Evanston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. [1923] (2008). The nature of sympathy (P. Heath, Trans.). New Brunswick/London: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. [1928] (2009). The human place in the cosmos (M. Frings, Trans.). Evanston (Illinois): Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Theunissen, M. (1964). Bubers negative Ontologie des Zwischen. Philosophisches Jahrbuch, 71, 319–330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Theunissen, M. (1977). Der Andere. Studien zur Sozialontologie der Gegenwart (zweite Auflage). Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Theunissen, M. [1977] (1984). The other. Studies in the social ontology of Husserl, Heidegger, Sartre, and Buber (Ch. Macann, Trans.). Cambridge (Massachusetts) and London: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tidona, G. (2013). Einführung. Über die Grenzen der Phänomenologie und unterwegs zur Dialogik. “Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen”. In K. Löwith, Das Individuum in der Rolle des Mitmenschen. Ein Beitrag zur anthropologischen Grundlegung der ethischen Probleme (pp. 11–79). Freiburg/München: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Balthasar, H. U. [1973] (1988). Theo-drama. Theological dramatic theory I: Prolegomena (G. Harrison, Trans.). San Francisco: Ignatius.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Humboldt, W. [1827] (1997). On the dual form. In W. von Humboldt, Essays on language (T. Harden & D. Farrelly, Trans.) (pp. 111–136). Frankfurt am Main: Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wojcieszuk, M. A. (2010). Der Mensch wird am Du zum Ich. Eine Auseindersetzung mit der Dialogphilosophie des XX. Jahrhunderts. Freiburg: Centaurus.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Agostino Cera .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Cera, A. (2017). The Other’s Place in the Space of the Relation: Karl Löwith and Martin Buber as Theorists of Duheit. In: Catena, M., Masi, F. (eds) The Changing Faces of Space. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 39. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66911-3_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics