Skip to main content

From Visual Abduction to Abductive Vision

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Abduction in Context

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 32))

Abstract

In order to fathom Peirce’s mind, and thereby in order to do science and philosophy in Peircean way, vision seems to be a perfect point of departure. For vision allows us to rethink what true interdisciplinarity would be like in our research. In this article, I shall show the central importance of visual abduction and abductive vision in our future study of abduction as well as Peirce’s thought. As exemplified well in Magnani’s study of abduction, we have good reasons to go with and beyond Peirce. After briefly scheming Peirce’s view on perception as abduction, I shall report what has been done in recent years in the fields of visual abduction and abductive vision. The centrality of visual abduction in Magnani’s theory of manipulative abduction will be one focal point. Another will be an examination of Raftopoulos’ discussion of abduction in late vision.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Magnani (2009), especially Chap. 5 “Animal Abduction: From Mindless Organisms to Artifactual Mediators”, which was originally published in Magnani and Li (2007, pp. 3–38).

  2. 2.

    According to Campbell, the word “cotary” is a neologism from Latin, meaning “whetstone”. So, Peirce’s three cotary propositions of pragmatism are supposed to sharpen the concept of pragmatism (Campbell 2011, p. 54). I am indebted to Lorenzo Magnani for this reference. More detailed further hints are found in the editors’ footnote #1 for Peirce’s “Pragmatism as the Logic of Abduction” (EP, p. 530).

  3. 3.

    Elsewhere I discussed Magnani’s multiple distinctions of abduction in connection with the problem of classifying types or patterns of abduction. I am adopting my previous discussion in Park (2015) (Chap. 7).

  4. 4.

    Cadwallader cites “On a New List of Categories” (1867) [CP 1.545–1.559] and “Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man” (1868) [CP 5.213–5.263] in this regard (Cadwallader 1975, pp. 170–171).

  5. 5.

    Based on Peirce’s own recollection and the evidence from the large set of notes that began around 1865 (Ms. 1956), Cadwallader notes that “[a]s the 60s progressed, Wundt’s influence began to be apparent in Peirce’s writings”. Also, based on a large notebook (Ms. 1156), Cadwallader reports that Peirce showed continued interest in Wundt by referring to Wundt’s Physiological Psychology of 1874 at least 47 times (Cadwallader 1975, p. 171).

  6. 6.

    Here I am indebted to an anonymous reviewer, who convinced me that Raftotpoulos never denies the possibility of early abductive vision.

  7. 7.

    Cf. Atocha Aliseda’s interesting comments: “On the other hand, some authors take induction as an instance of abduction. Abduction as inference to the best explanation is considered by Harman [Har65] as the basic form of non-deductive inference, which includes (enumerative) induction as a special case”.

    This confusion returns in artificial intelligence. ‘Induction’ is used for the process of learning from examples—but also for creating a theory to explain the observed facts [Sha91]. Thus making abduction an instance of induction. Abduction is usually restricted to producing abductive explanations in the form of facts. When the explanations are rules, it is regarded as part of induction” (Aliseda 2006, p. 34).

References

  • Aliseda, A. (2006). Abductive reasoning. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. S. (1957). On perceptual readiness. Psychological Review, 64(2), 123–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cadwallader, T. C. (1975). Peirce as an experimental psychologist. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 11, 167–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, S. (2015). Biomorphism and models in design. in L. Magnani et al. (eds.), Philosophy and Cognitive Science II, Springer, 209-221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campos, D. G. (2011). On the distinction between Peirce’s abduction and Lipton’s inference to the Best explanation. Synthese, 180, 419–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, P. L. (2011). Peirce, Pragmatism, and the right way of thinking. Albuquerque, New mexico: Sandia National Laboratories.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1988). Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality: A reply to Jerry Fodor. Philosophy of Science, 55, 167–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1984). Observation reconsidered. Philosophy of Science, 51, 23–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, C. D. (2007). Johns Hopkins’s first professorship in philosophy: A critical pivot point in the history of American psychology. American Journal of Psychology, 120(2), 303–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, R. L. (1987). Perception as hypotheses. In R. L. Gregory (Ed.), The Oxford companion to the mind (pp. 608–611). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review 74, 88–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann, M. H. G. (1999). Problems with Peirce’s concept of abduction. Foundations of Science, 4(3), 271–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, J.R., Josephson, S.G. (eds.) (1994). Abductive Inference. Computation, Philosophy, Technology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1787, 1968). Critiques of pure reason (N. K. Smith, Trans.). New York: St. Martins Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2002). Understanding philosophy of science. London/New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leary, D. E. (2009). Between Peirce (1878) and James (1898): G. Stanley Hall, the origins of pragmatism, and the history of psychology. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 45(1), 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, S. H. (1997). Peirce’s theorematic/corollarial distinction and the interconnections between mathematics and logic. In N. Houser, D. D. Roberts & J. Evra (Eds.), Studies in the logic of Charles Sanders Peirce, Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (1991). Inference to the best explanation. London/New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackonis, A. (2013). Inference to the best explanation, coherence and other explanatory virtues. Synthese, 190, 975–995.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2001). Abduction, reason, and science: Processes of discovery and explanation. New York: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2007). Animal abduction. From mindless organisms to artifactual mediators. In L. Magnani & P. Li (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in science, technology, and medicine, Studies in computational intelligence (Vol. 64, pp. 3–37). Berlin/New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2009). Abductive cognition. The epistemological and eco-cognitive dimensions of hypothetical reasoning. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L., Li, P. (eds.). (2007). Model-Based Reasoning in Science, Technology, and Medicine, Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2010). Mindless abduction: From animal guesses to artifactual mediators. In M. Bergman, S. Paavola, A.-V. Pietarinen, & H. Rydenfelt (Eds.), Ideas in action: Proceedings of the applying Peirce conference (pp. 224–238). Nordic Pragmatism Network: Helsinki.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2011). Is instinct rational? Are animals intelligent?: An abductive account. In L. Carlson, C. Hoelscher & T. F. Shipley (Eds.), Proceedings of the 33rd Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 150–155), Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2015). Visual abduction. Unpublished paper presented at international workshop visual abduction or abductive vision? KAIST, Daejeon, Korea.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2015). Understanding visual abduction: The need of the eco-cognitive model, in L. Magnani et al. (eds.). Philosophy and Cognitive Science II, Springer, 117–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L., & Dossena, R. (2005). Perceiving the infinite and the infinitesimal world: Unveiling and optical diagrams in mathematics. Foundations of Science, 10, 7–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L., Civita, S., & Massara, G. P. (1994). Visual cognition and cognitive modeling. In V. Cantoni (Ed.), Human and machine vision: Analogies and divergences (pp. 229–243). New York: Plenum Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Minnameier, G. (2004). Peirce-suit of truth—Why inference to the best explanation and abduction ought not to be confused. Erkenntnis, 60, 75–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, J. (2002). Two visual systems and two theories of perception: an attempt to reconcile the constructivist and ecological approaches. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25, 73–144.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paavola, S. (2005). Peircean abduction: Instinct or inference? Semiotica, 153–1/4, 131–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, W. (2014). How to learn abduction from animals?: From Avicenna to Magnani. In L. Magnani (Ed.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology: Theoretical and cognitive issues. Heidelberg/Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, W. (2015). On classifying abduction. Journal of Applied Logic, 13(3), 215–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C.S. (1966). The Charles S. Peirce Papers: Manuscript Collection in the Houghton Library. The University of Massachusetts Press, Worcester, MA (1966), Annotated Catalogue of the Papers of Charles S. Peirce. Numbered according to Richard S. Robin. Available in the Peirce Microfilm edition. Pagination: CSP = Peirce / ISP = Institute for Studies in Pragmaticism.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1998). The essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings (Vol. 2). N. Houser & C. Kloesel (Eds.), Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press [Abbreviated as EP].

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2001). Is perception informationally encapsulated? The issue of the theorylandenness of perception. Cognitive Science, 25, 423–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. (2015). Abductive inference in late vision. In L. Magnani, P. Li & W. Park (Eds.), Philosophy and cognitive science: Western and Eastern studies II, Sapere, Heidelberg/Berlin: Springer, 155–176, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rock, I. (1983). The logic of perception. Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, C. (1994). Visual abductive reasoning. M.A. Thesis, University of Waterloo, Waterloo, On., Canada.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, C. (1995). Visual abduction in anthropology and archaeology. AAAI Technical Report SS-95-03, 155–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, C. (1996). Visual abductive reasoning in archaeology. Philosophy of Science, 63, 278–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelley, C. (2003). Multiple analogies in science and philosophy. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology. An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2011). Peirce’s notion of diagram experiment: Corollarial and theorematical experiments with diagrams. In R. Heinrich, E. Nemeth, W. Pichler, & D. Wagner (Eds.), Image and imaging in philosophy, science and the arts (Vol. 2, pp. 305–340). Frankfurt: Ontons Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P., & Shelley, C. (1997). Abductive reasoning: Logic, visual thinking, and coherence. Dalla Chiara, M. L. et al. (Eds.), Logic and scientific methods (pp. 413–427).

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiercelin, C. (2005). Abduction and the semiotics of perception. Semiotica, 153, 389–412.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Helmholtz, H. (1967). Handbuch der physiologischen Optik. Leipzig: Leopold Voss.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Woosuk Park .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Park, W. (2017). From Visual Abduction to Abductive Vision. In: Abduction in Context. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 32. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-48956-8_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics