Skip to main content

Nonmonotonicity and Knowability: As Knowable as Possible

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Rohit Parikh on Logic, Language and Society

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 11))

Abstract

According to the anti-realistic theory of meaning, everything that is true is knowable. Fitch’s (1963) paradox—based on very standard assumptions made in modal logic—is seen as a challenge to this theory. In this paper I argue that there is something wrong with Fitch’s derivation of the absurdity. Assuming—for the sake of argument— the thesis of anti-realism, I argue with Beall (2000) that this doesn’t lead to disaster in case we allow some contradictions to be true. By making use of a nonmonotonic consequence relation, I show that for all of Tennant’s (1997) so-called ‘Cartesian propositions’ that are true, we can derive that it is true and not false that they are knowable.

I would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments and suggestions. This paper builds on joint work with Pablo Cobreros, Paul Egré and Dave Ripley, and I want to thank them as well. This work was done with main support from the Marie Curie Initial Training network ESSENCE-project, and the NWO-sponsored Language in Interaction-project.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    van Benthem (2004) argues that Tennant’s limitation is too weak. The thesis of verificationalism should not be limited to propositions that can be known consistently, but rather to propositions that one can learn consistently. Van Benthem observes that there are sentences that can be known consistently, but that cannot be consistently learned: \(\phi = (p \wedge \Diamond \lnot p) \vee \mathbf{K}\lnot p\).

  2. 2.

    \(\textit{LP}\) is so named by Priest (1979), who has advanced the logic widely in philosophy, though the logic was introduced, for the same reason of accommodating ‘glutty theories’ (true inconsistent but non-trivial theories), by Asenjo (1966) and Aseno and Tamburino (1975).

  3. 3.

    Notice that the semantics is just like that of Fuzzy Logic, but now limited to three truth values.

  4. 4.

    For a more elaborate discussion of this proposal, see Cobreros et al. (2015).

  5. 5.

    The definition of \(T(\phi )\) is taken from the analysis of minimal truth-makers proposed by van Fraassen (1969).

  6. 6.

    Cf. van Fraassen (1969). This path is taken in Cobreros et al. (2015).

  7. 7.

    \(\phi '\) is a sentence in Negative Normal Form of \(\phi \) if (1) it is logically equivalent with \(\phi \), and (2) negations only stand in front of atomic formulas.

  8. 8.

    ‘Thus, if necessity is to be treated syntactically, that is, as a predicate of sentences, as Carnap and Quine have urged, then virtually all of modal logic [...] must be scarified’ (Montague, 1963, p. 9).

  9. 9.

    The thesis could still receive value 1, though, if we used Łucasiewics’ conditional, which is like material implication, except that it assigns to \(\phi \rightarrow \psi \) value 1 if both \(\phi \) and \(\psi \) have value \(\frac{1}{2}\).

  10. 10.

    Recall that \(\models ^{prt}\) is neither transitive (if the language contains a similarity-relation or a transparent truth-predicate) nor does it validate explosion. It is by the latter feature, and not by non-transitivity, that it solves the the knower.

References

  • Alxatib, S., & Pelletier, F. R. (2011). The psychology of vagueness: Borderline cases and contradictions. Mind and Language, 26, 287–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alxatib, S., Pagin, P., Sauerland, U., et al. (2013). Acceptable contradictions: Pragmatics or semantics? A reply to Cobreros. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42, 619–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asenjo, F. (1966). Calculus of antinomies. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 7, 103–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aseno, F., & Tamburino, J. (1975). Logic of antinomies. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 16, 17–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beall, Jc. (2000). Fitch’s proof, verificationism, and the knower paradox’. Australian Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 241–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2012). Tolerant, classical, strict. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 347–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2013). Reaching transparent truth. Mind, 122, 841–866.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2015). Pragmatic interpretations of vague expressions: strong meaning and nonmonotonic consequence. Journal of Philosophical Logic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, F. (1963). A logical analysis of some value concepts. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 28, 135–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1967). Logic and conversation. William James Lectures. Harvard University, reprinted in Studies in the Way of Words, 1989. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1963). Syntactic treatment of modality. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 16, 153–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (1979). The logic of paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8, 219–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (1991). Minimally inconsistent LP. Studia Logica, 50, 321–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ripley, D. (2011). Contradictions at the borders. In R. Nouwen, R. van Rooij, H.-C. Schmitz, & U. Sauerland (Eds.), Vagueness in communication. Berlin: LICS, Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ripley, D. (2012). Conservatively extending classical logic with transparent truth. Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 354–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salerno, J. (Ed.). (2009). New essays on the knowability paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Serchuk, P., Hargreaves, I., & Zach, R. (2011). Vagueness, logic and use: Four experimental studies on vagueness. Mind and Language, 26, 540–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tennant, N. (1997). The taming of the true. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J. (2004). What one may come to know. Analysis, 64, 95–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1969). Facts and tautological entailments. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 477–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert van Rooij .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van Rooij, R. (2017). Nonmonotonicity and Knowability: As Knowable as Possible. In: Başkent, C., Moss, L., Ramanujam, R. (eds) Rohit Parikh on Logic, Language and Society. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 11. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-47843-2_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics