Skip to main content

From Modal Skepticism to Modal Empiricism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Modal Epistemology After Rationalism

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 378))

Abstract

In this paper, I sketch and defend a thoroughgoing empiricist account of our knowledge of metaphysical possibility. I argue that our knowledge of Moorean metaphysical possibilities traces back to our knowledge of the actual world through empirical sources (such as observation and observation-sensitive theory). In this connection, I advocate a pluralist account, according to which deductive, inductive, and abductive inferences from actuality are all legitimate sources of our knowledge of possibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Lewis (1999, p. 418).

  2. 2.

    Here I have given examples of Moorean de re possibility claims, but there are of course very many corresponding Moorean de dicto possibility claims as well.

  3. 3.

    A notable recent exception is Williamson (2007).

  4. 4.

    See, especially, van Inwagen (1998, 67–84).

  5. 5.

    The following discussion is based on Van Inwagen (1998), reprinted Van Inwagen (2001). All references below are to the latter version.

  6. 6.

    Van Inwagen (2001, 246).

  7. 7.

    Ibid, 246–247: “My own view is that we often do know modal propositions, ones that are of use to us in everyday life and in science and even in philosophy, but do not and cannot know…modal propositions like [“It is possible for there to be a perfect being”, “It is possible that I exist and nothing material exist”, and “It is possible that there exist vast amounts of suffering for which there is no explanation”]. I have called this position “Modal skepticism”. This name was perhaps ill-chosen, since…I think that we know a lot of modal propositions, and…“skeptic” suggests someone who contends that we know nothing or almost nothing…however…there has been another sort of skeptic: someone who contends that the world contains a great deal of institutionalized pretense to knowledge of remote matters concerning which knowledge is in fact not possible…It is in this sense of the word that I am a modal skeptic.”

  8. 8.

    The following discussion of Van Inwagen’s views about the sorts of modal knowledge we do have is based on ibid, 246–251.

  9. 9.

    Ibid. Of course, one could rightly point out that mysteries remain here, but Van Inwagen’s point is that for a large class of modal claims to be individuated below, we lack even these preliminary sorts of answers regarding their sources of justification.

  10. 10.

    Ibid.

  11. 11.

    Ibid.

  12. 12.

    Ibid.

  13. 13.

    Here I have in mind Alvin Plantinga’s modal ontological argument. On this, see Plantinga (1974).

  14. 14.

    Here I am referring to the famous argument in Descartes (1985, CSM 2:54) for the real distinction between mind and body.

  15. 15.

    Chalmers (1996).

  16. 16.

    See, for example, Shoemaker and Swinburne (1984, 12–19).

  17. 17.

    Block (1976).

  18. 18.

    Ibid, 250: “Although I do not doubt that we have some modal knowledge, I regard much of this knowledge as mysterious. Some modal statements, I have said, we know by reasoning from what I have called “basic” modal knowledge – simple, obvious modal statements whose truth we are somehow in a position to know –… But how do we get started in this reasoning? How do we know the “simple, obvious” modal statements to be true? What is the ground of “basic” modal knowledge? I do not know how to answer these questions.” Italics mine.

  19. 19.

    A systematic investigation and presentation of his reasons for rejecting such accounts falls outside the bounds of our current inquiry. However, I discuss his reasons in some detail in “Van Inwagen on Modal Epistemology” (ms.).

  20. 20.

    There are no doubt reasonable worries about the extent of application with respect to this route to modal knowledge, but it should be less controversial that it applies at least to cases involving inferences to the possible existence of intrinsic qualitative duplicates of observed tokens of the type of entity at issue.

  21. 21.

    Timothy Williamson has independently appealed to our folk physics and folk psychology as at least a partial basis of our knowledge of possibility. The primary difference between his view and mine on this point is that Williamson ties our modal knowledge to our facility with counterfactual reasoning, whereas I make no commitment to such a connection. For a thorough exposition and defense of Williamson’s account of modal epistemology, see Williamson (2007).

  22. 22.

    Of course, if our modal claims can be supported by our folk theories, then it’s natural to think they can be justified by our scientific theories about how the world works as well. See the chapters by Fischer and Hanrahan in the present volume for detailed accounts of how this might go.

  23. 23.

    Van Inwagen (2001, 254).

  24. 24.

    Ibid.

  25. 25.

    See the chapters by Hawke and Roca-Royes in the present volume for excellent accounts of modal justification via analogy/relevant similarity.

  26. 26.

    One could strengthen the justification here by combining different sources of modal evidence. So, for example, one could also appeal here to our folk theory of how the world works as well.

  27. 27.

    Lehrer (1965, 168–175).

  28. 28.

    For helpful comments on a previous draft of this paper, I am grateful to Bob Fischer, Sonia Roca-Royes, Anand Vaidya, Christian Nimtz, Antonella Mallozzi, and the wonderful audience at the Directions in the Epistemology of Modality Workshop at the University of Stirling.

Bibliography

  • Block, N. (1978). Troubles with functionalism. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 9, 261–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. In French, Uehling, & Wettstein (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy (Vol. IV, pp. 73–121). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cottingham, J., Stoothoof, R., & Murdoch, D. (1984). The philosophical writings of Descartes (Vol. II). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1967). The problem of abortion and the doctrine of double effect. Oxford Review, 5, 5–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternative possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 66, 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kung, P. (2010). Imagining as a guide to possibility. Philosophy & Phenomenological Research, 81(3), 620–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1965). Knowledge, truth, and evidence. Analysis, 25(5), 68–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.K. (1999). Elusive knowledge. Reprinted in Lewis, D. K. Papers in metaphysics and epistemology, Vol. 2. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1975). In P. H. Nidditch (Ed.), An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S.. (2006). Imaginative blocks and impossibility: An essay in modal psychology. In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of the imagination: New essays on pretense, possibility, and fiction. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13(1), 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S., & Swinburne, R. (1984). Personal identity. Oxford: Basil-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1(3), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (1971). A defense of abortion. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 1, 47–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1998). Modal epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 92, 67–84. Reprinted in Van Inwagen, P. (2001). Ontology, identity, and modality: Essays in metaphysics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Felipe Leon .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Leon, F. (2017). From Modal Skepticism to Modal Empiricism. In: Fischer, B., Leon, F. (eds) Modal Epistemology After Rationalism. Synthese Library, vol 378. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-44309-6_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics