Skip to main content

Grice, the Law and the Linguistic Special Case Thesis

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Pragmatics and Law

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 7))

Abstract

This paper aims to investigate the applicability of Grice’s theory of conversational implicatures to legal statutes and other general heteronomous legal acts (while acts of private autonomy are excluded from the scope of the present investigation). After a brief presentation of Grice’s theory Sect. 1 and an attempt to adapt conversational maxims to normative discourse – which is assumed to be neither true nor false Sect. 2 – I will survey one of the most convincing arguments against the applicability of conversational maxims to the legal domain, the one based on the (absence of a precise, real) legislative intention Sect. 3. I will argue that this argument is not decisive, but that, however, conversational maxims do not apply to legislation: as a matter of fact, legal practice does not include Grice’s conversational maxims among its conventions Sect. 4. This inapplicability, which derives from the very nature of the cooperative principles and the maxims, fits other peculiarities of legal practice: perhaps the most relevant is what we may call the contextual indeterminacy of legal discourse, a characteristic that is rigidly coupled to its conflicting nature. I will claim that all these features explain why legislation and other general heteronomous legal acts are not special cases of ordinary conversations Sect. 5.

An earlier version of this paper was presented on March 30th 2015 at the Université Paris Ouest, Nanterre La Défense. I thank all the participants, and, in particular, Pierre Brunet, Carlos Bernal Pulido, and Alessio Sardo for their helpful comments and criticisms.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Instead I am not concerned with autonomous legal acts such as contracts (on this kind of acts see Poggi 2011). Moreover, I do not intend my thesis as applying to constitutional interpretation.

  2. 2.

    The clarification “at least to a certain extent” is indispensable when taking account of cases of the so-called exploitation or flouting of the maxims: cases in which a maxim is overtly violated, in order to intentionally exploit the evidence of violation and convey a certain message. In Grice’s opinion, irony, metaphors, meiosis and hyperbole fall into this category: c.f., e.g., Grice (1967, 1989b) and Levinson (1983).

  3. 3.

    Although this is not Grice’s opinion: “When I speak of the assumptions required in order to maintain the supposition that the Cooperative Principle and maxims are being observed on a given occasion, I am thinking of assumptions that are nontrivially required; I do not intend to include, for example, assumption to the effect that some particular maxim is being observed, or is thought of by the speaker as being observed. This seemingly natural restriction has an interesting consequence with regards Moore’s “paradox”. On my account, it will not be true that when I say that p, I conversationally implicate that I believe that p; for to suppose that I believe that p […] is just to suppose that I am observing the first maxim of Quality on this occasion” (Grice 1989b: 41–42). However, this point is questionable: even if it is true that the first Maxim of Quality is very important because “the other Maxims come into operation only on the assumption that this maxim of Quality is satisfied” (Grice 1989a: 27), it is true as well that – with the exception of the inference from “p” to “I believe that p” – this maxim does not seem to hold any specific implicature, so, pace Grice (Grice 1967), it would play a role which is completely different from the one of the other maxims. Moreover, sometimes the implicatures which are governed by the other maxims seem to be nothing else than the assumption to the effect that some particular maxim has been observed: see, e.g., the example (j) in the text.

  4. 4.

    Recently, the role of cancellability as a necessary condition for conversational implicatures has been challenged by Weirner (2006). For some replies to Weirner cf. (Blome-Tillmann 2008; Borge 2009).

  5. 5.

    Consider the following example proposed by Grice himself: “A: Where does C live? B: Somewhere in the South of France”. In this case there is “no reason to suppose that B is opting out, but his answer is, as he well knows, less informative than is required to meet A’s needs. This infringement of the first maxim of Quantity can be explained only by the supposition that B is aware that to be more informative would be to say something that infringed the second maxim of Quality” (Grice 1967 in 1989a: 32–33). For a critical discussion see Atlas (2005: 71ff).

  6. 6.

    Actually the implicature from “and” to “and then” is debated: in particular it is disputed whether it is really a standard Gricean implicature (i.e. whether the conjunction “and” has got an unique meaning equivalent to the logical operator “&”) and/or what are the conditions under which this implicature stands. I will not consider these difficulties here: see, e.g., Blakemore (1992: 80), Carston (1993, 1995), Davis (1998: 46ff.), and (Levinson 2000: 122ff).

  7. 7.

    I agree with the authors who claim that the maxims are also necessary to conclude that the speaker said what she said without implying anything.: “For even if what the speaker means is exactly what he/she says, the hearer must recognize this, even though that (that the speaker means is exactly what he/she says) is not something that is explicitly communicated. And here too the CP plays a role: if the speaker is taken to be speaking literally, it is because that preserves the assumption that the speaker is observing CP” (Rysiew 2007: 293. C.f. also Strawson 1973; Bach 1997).

  8. 8.

    The violation of a maxim can be justified by the respect of a different conflicting maxim, as in Grice’s example reported in footnote 5 above.

  9. 9.

    The former propriety is expressly emphasized by Grice (1967), whereas the second is not. For a discussion on the proprieties of the conversational implicatures c.f. (Sadock 1978; Levinson 1983; Atlas 2005; Bach 2005).

  10. 10.

    Actually, while, as far as I know, nobody neglects the fact that imperatives, and especially singular norms, such as “Alex close the door!”, are neither true nor false, the point is highly problematic as far as value judgements are concerned. These difficulties will be not considered here.

  11. 11.

    Defeasibility means that, given some set of conditions A, something else B will hold, unless or until defeating conditions C apply. A defeasible norm is, therefore, a norm that is subjected to implicit exceptions.

  12. 12.

    By “linguistic scale” it is meant a set of linguistic expressions of the same grammatical category (so-called scalar predicates) arranged according to a linear order of informativeness or semantic force. Given a scale of this kind, the first maxim of Quantity makes it possible to formulate a general predictive rule according to which, if a speaker states something that refers to a weaker point on the scale, it is implicated that the same does not hold with respect to a higher point on the scale. See: Horn (1972), Gazdar (1979), Soames (1982), Horn (1989), Atlas (1993), and Levinson (2000: 79).

  13. 13.

    This interpretative canon is the core of the attitude that Bobbio called “legal positivism as theory” and that has characterized the European jurisprudence of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. See Bobbio (1961).

  14. 14.

    For other criticisms to the interpretative canon based on a fictitious intention (especially in Marmor’s version: Marmor 2005), see Velluzzi (2007).

  15. 15.

    In the same sense: Davis (2007), Bianchi (2011 (especially 24ff.)), on this point see also Neale (1992) and (Sbisà 2007: 127–8).

  16. 16.

    So I adhere to what Greenberg termed “objective notion of communicative content” (see Greenberg 2011: 231). A similar (but not identical) opinion to that supported in the text has been sustained by Sbisà (2007), Green (2002, 2007), and, to some extent at least, Saul (2002a, b). Contra cf. instead Bianchi (2011). So, e.g., according to Sbisà, the conversational implicatures are implicitly made available by the text that can be ascribed to the speaker (to the speaker’s intention) iff ascribing them is reasonable (Sbisà 2007: 125ff.). By contrast, in my reading, the reason why the listener can ascribe an implicature to me the speaker is simply that the maxims allow that ascription (the maxims and the context, the maxims in that context).

  17. 17.

    Although, the dialogues (q) and (r) concern generalized implicatures (i.e. implicatures that are always produced, but that cannot be produced in special contexts), in my opinion, something similar is true also in the case of particularized implicatures (i.e. implicatures which require particular contexts): also particularized implicatures are partially independent of the speaker’s intention. See Poggi (2011).

  18. 18.

    An exception is the violation of the first maxim of Quality: aside from the hypothesis of exploitation, someone who deviates from this maxim is telling lies and lying is, obviously, a behaviour that produces general criticism, hostile reactions and penalties. With regard to this, however, as well as the conversational maxims there can also be social norms that prescribe their content.

  19. 19.

    Within Gricean literature, the exact content of the CP is controversial: see Thomas (1998) and Ladegaard (2009). In this paper, as clarified by the above formula, cooperation is intended exclusively as communicative cooperation, as direct cooperation from the common goal of understanding and making oneself understood and not as a sharing of further non-linguistic goals or interests.

  20. 20.

    Chiassoni points out that many gricean maxims correspond (more or less) to traditional legal canons of construction: Chiassoni (1999, 92ff).

  21. 21.

    I think that the lack of expectations really makes the difference. In fact, some philosophers of language (like Morra 2015) that there is not a sizable difference between legal interpretation and everyday conversations, because also in the ordinary communication conversational maxims are sometimes violated or at least not followed. However, I think that there is a considerable difference because in everyday interactions there is a general expectation that everybody follows the maxims – an expectation that makes it possible to lie or to be ironic. Nothing like this happens in legal interpretation.

  22. 22.

    Actually I cannot understand the second hypothesis and what differs from the first: I wonder whether the uncertainty about “how seriously parties to conversation are presumed to adhere to the relevant maxims” (Marmor 2011: 94) is equivalent to the doubt that one or both parties are violating the maxims.

  23. 23.

    Chiassoni (1999) seems to think that in legal interpretation (he does not distinguish between heteronomous legal acts and acts of private autonomy) conversational maxims do not hold because it is a different linguistic game from ordinary conversation, and he does not explain (why it is so and) what such difference consists in. I prefer to think that legal interpretation is a different game (also) because CP and conversational maxims do not hold.

  24. 24.

    Marmor (2008, 2011)

  25. 25.

    More exactly, as we will soon see, in a sense here there is nothing to understand.

  26. 26.

    This is a very simplified version: cf. Grice (1968, 1969).

  27. 27.

    Invoking a fictitious intention of a rational, counterfactual, ideal, lawmaker it is not a solution, for at least three reasons. First, because this intention can be constructed in several different ways (as one likes). Second because it seems to me that (neo-)Gricean account is incompatible with a fictitious intention – if we assume so, all the difference between natural and non-natural meaning vanishes. Third, because it would make a distorted imagine of legal practice.

  28. 28.

    I deal with this topic in Poggi (2013).

References

  • Atlas, J. D. (1993). The implication of conversation: The 1990 Leuven lectures. Claremont: Pomona College.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, J. D. (2005). Logic, meaning and conversation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Atlas, J. D., & Levinson, S. C. (1981). It-clefts, informativeness, and logical form: Radical pragmatics. In P. Cole (Ed.), Radical pragmatics (pp. 1–61). New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1994). Conversational implicature. Mind & Language, 9, 124–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (1997). The semantic-pragmatic distinction: What it is and why it matters. Pragmatik, 8, 33–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (2005). The top 10 misconceptions about implicature. In B. Birner & G. Ward (Eds.), Drawing the boundaries of meaning: Neo-Gricean studies in pragmatics and semantics in honor of Laurence R. Horn (pp. 21–30). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bianchi, C. (2011). Implicature, intenzioni e normatività. Esercizi filosofici, 6, 16–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, D. (1992). Understanding utterances. An introduction to pragmatics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blome-Tillmann, M. (2008). Conversational implicature and the cancellability test. Analysis, 68(2), 156–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bobbio, N. (1961). Il positivismo giuridico. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borge, S. (2009). Conversational implicatures and cancellability. Acta Analytica, 24(2), 149–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2013). The role of pragmatics in (re)constructing the rational law-maker. Pragmatics & Cognition, 21(2), 399–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1993). Conjunction, explanation, and relevance. Lingua, 90, 27–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1995). Quantity maxims and generalised implicature. Lingua, 96, 213–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni, P. (1999). Interpretative games: Statutory construction through Gricean eyes. Analisi e diritto, 18, 79–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, M., & Wróblewski, J. (1991). The rational law-maker and the pragmatics of legal interpretation. Journal of Pragmatics, 15, 421–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (1998). Implicature, intention, convention and principle in the failure of Gricean theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, W. A. (2007). How normative is implicature. Journal of Pragmatics, 39, 1655–1672.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, G. (1979). Pragmatics, implicature, presupposition and logical form. Orlando: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. S. (2002). Review of implicature: Intention, convention, and principle in the failure of Gricean theory, by Wayne Davis. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65, 241–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, M. S. (2007). Self-expression. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, M. (2011). Legislation as communication? Legal interpretation and the study of linguistic communication. In A. Marmor & S. Soames (Eds.), Philosophical foundations of language in the law (pp. 217–256). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. H. (1967). Logic and conversation. Reprinted in Grice 1989a, 22–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. H. (1968). Utterer’s meaning, sentence-,meaning and word-meaning. Foundations of Language, 4, 225–242; ried. in Grice 1989a, 117–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. H. (1969). Utterer’s meaning and intentions. Philosophical Review, 78, 147–177; ried. in Grice 1989a, 86–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. H. (1989a). Studies in the way of word. Cambridge/London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. H. (1989b). Further notes on logic and conversation. In P. H. Grice 1989a, 41–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The concept of law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L.R. (1972). On the semantic properties of logical operator in English. Ph.D. dissertation, UCLA: Los Angeles

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladegaard, H. J. (2009). Pragmatic cooperation revisited: Resistance and non-cooperation as a discursive strategy in asymmetrical discourse. Journal of Pragmatics, 41, 649–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (2000). Presumptive meaning. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. (2005). Interpretation and legal theory (2nd ed.). Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. (2007). What does the law say? Semantics and pragmatics in statutory language. Analisi e diritto, 127, 127–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. (2008). The pragmatics of legal language. Ratio Juris, 21, 423–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, A. (2011). Can law imply more than it says? On some pragmatic aspects of strategic speech. In A. Marmor & S. Soames (Eds.), Philosophical foundations of language in the law (pp. 83–104). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Morra, L. (2011). Implicature conversazionali nei testi di legge. Esercizi filosofici, 6(1), 214–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morra, L. (2015). Conversational implicatures in normative texts. In A. Capone & J. L. Mey (Eds.), Pragmatics, culture and society (pp. 537–562). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neale, S. (1992). Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 15, 509–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poggi, F. (2004). Norme permissive. Torino: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poggi, F. (2011). Law and conversational implicatures. International Journal for Semiotics of Law, 24(1), 21–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poggi, F. (2013). The myth of literal meaning in legal interpretation. Analisi e Diritto, 313–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reimer, M. (1998). What is meant by ‘What is said’. A reply to Cappelen and Lepore. Mind & Language, 13(4), 598–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rysiew, P. (2007). Beyond words: Communication, truthfulness, and understanding. Episteme, 4, 285–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sadock, J. M. (1978). On testing for conversational implicature. In Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics (pp. 281–298). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2002a). Speaker meaning, what is said, and what is implicated. Noûs, 36, 228–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2002b). What is said and psychological reality: Grice’s project and relevance theorists’ criticism. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25, 347–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sbisà, M. (2007). Detto, non detto. Le forme della comunicazione implicita. Laterza: Roma-Bari.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (1982). How presuppositions are inherited: A solution to the projection problem. Linguistic Inquiry, 13(3), 483–545.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F., et al. (1973). Austin and “locutionary meaning”. In I. Berlin (Ed.), Essays on J.L. Austin (pp. 46–68). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, J. (1998). Cooperative principle. In J. Mey (Ed.), Concise encyclopedia of pragmatics. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velluzzi, V. (2007). Whose intentions and authority? The legislature’s or the interpreter’s? Analisi e Diritto, 279–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H. (1963). Norm and action. A logical enquiry. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weirner, M. (2006). Are all conversational implicatures cancellable? Analysis, 66(2), 127–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francesca Poggi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Poggi, F. (2016). Grice, the Law and the Linguistic Special Case Thesis. In: Capone, A., Poggi, F. (eds) Pragmatics and Law. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 7. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30385-7_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30385-7_11

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-30383-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-30385-7

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics