Keywords

Introduction

[W]e move in science into an unknown language with unknown grammar and try, with a dictionary in our hands, to compose grammatically correct sentences.(Markoš 2002, p. 180)

Language , writes Marcello Barbieri, is “the quintessential example of semiosis”.Footnote 1 According to Martin Heidegger, Man is not simply a living creature who possesses language along with other capacities – no, “language is the house of Being in which man ek-sists [sic – ‘stands out’] by dwelling, in that he belongs to the truth of Being, guarding it”.Footnote 2 In Jesper Hoffmeyer’s words, our species’ evolutionary acquisition of language implied a “switch from an umwelt containing very few transformation rules to a grammatical umwelt”.Footnote 3 We are fundamentally linguistic creatures. “Humans”, says Thomas A. Sebeok , “have evolved a way of modeling their universe in a way that not only echoes ‘what is out there’ but which can, additionally, dream up a potentially infinite number of possible worlds”.Footnote 4 Edmund Husserl was of a similar opinion: “Clearly it is only through language and its far-reaching documentations, as possible communications, that the horizon of civilization can be an open and endless one, as it always is for men”.Footnote 5

And so the stage is set. To most people, language largely constitutes reality. And yet language is free to evolve at the inkling of an eye or by the hunch of a confused mind. Without a doubt, language does in many senses open the world up to us – but it also conditions and constrains us. As David Abram writes, “[e]very attempt to definitively say what language is is subject to a curious limitation. For the only medium with which we can define language is language itself. We are therefore unable to circumscribe the whole of language within our definition”.Footnote 6

A second caveat is also required: there are phenomena that cannot (best) be described in a scientific language. The academic genre is given to objectification and generalization, and might thus not be capable of capturing all phenomena which are not easily objectifiable. This reminder is no less important given the implicit topic matter of this text, subjective experience. The reader should therefore keep in mind warnings à la those of Gabriel MarcelFootnote 7 with regard to the pitfalls of methods of objectification. By objectifying subjective phenomena, and describing them in scholarly language, we convert them into another genre, and consequently a different mode of being – and this scholarly mode of being is not in all respects true and faithful to the phenomena. In particular, the detachment necessitated by abstract analysis is (if it were to become our only mode of being) irreconcilable with full-fledged participation as incarnated, engaged beings on par with other creatures.

“I Language, Therefore I Model”

Sultan knows: Now one is supposed to think. That is what the bananas up there are about. The bananas are there to make one think, to spur one to the limits of one’s thinking. But what must one think? One thinks: Why is he starving me? One thinks: What have I done? Why has he stopped liking me? One thinks: Why does he not want these crates any more? But none of these is the right thought. Even a more complicated thought – for instance: What is wrong with him, what misconception does he have of me, that leads him to believe it is easier for me to reach a banana hanging from a wire than to pick up a banana from the floor? – is wrong. The right thought to think is: How does one use the crates to reach the bananas?(Coetzee 1999, p. 28)

Uexküll and Language

Jakob von Uexküll (1864–1944), notes Han-Liang Chang, “rarely referred to language communication”.Footnote 8 On one of the rare occasions where he did refer to language, in a letter to Heinrich Junker dated 29th March 1937, Uexküll said that “[l]in-guistics itself is rather remote from my area”, though he complimented Junker for being “on the right path by making it into a biological science”.Footnote 9 The German-Baltic biologist further noted: “Language interests me mainly as a means of communication between man and animals, and as a means of communication between animals themselves”.Footnote 10

In a 1917 article entitled “Darwin and the English Morality”,Footnote 11 Uexküll comments on the difference that human language makes in our studies of animals and human beings.Footnote 12

It is clear that the mechanical effects of the physical and chemical forces alone do not lead us to insight about animal life, and, furthermore, that knowledge of these factors requires that the builder or operation manager affects the body machine.

These factors have been known since ancient times – they were called “drives” or urges and distinctions were made between food drive and sex drive, one spoke about self-preservation drive, and in animal communities or animal states [Tierstaaten] the social drives were detected.

As long as the topic is processes in the animal world, one must be satisfied with the identification of such drives, which one treats as given factors of nature and seeks to investigate objectively.

But if the topic is humans, whose language we understand and whose utterances resemble our own – then we are capable of providing part of the drives with sensory content that makes psychological understanding possible.Footnote 13

Is Language External or Internal to the Umwelt?

The reality of signs, and of Umwelten, entails that living beings are enmeshed in worlds of meaningful, significant phenomena and occurrences. BarbieriFootnote 14 and several other biosemioticians have suggested that even though there are examples of symbolic activity in animals, “[a] systematic use of symbols at the basis of our behaviour is indeed what divides human language from animal communication”. As Sebeok believed and Hoffmeyer thinks, I too think of language as being a species-specific human capability that has tremendous impact on the character of human affairs and of the human being. However, as we shall see, I think about language in terms of the conceptual Umwelt – an “outer” yet, as a rule, thoroughly integrated layer of the Umwelt. Language , then, is intimately tied to perception – language frames perception, and simultaneously language is grounded in (core) perception – and, indeed, in a sense language is perception (as scholars within ecological linguistics freely admit, language is a perception system).

Sebeok and Hoffmeyer both see language as transcending the human Umwelt. Particularly relevant here is Sebeok’s view on language as a secondary modelling system, whereas the Umwelt is the primary modelling system.Footnote 15 The distinction between primary and secondary modelling systems derives from the Tartu-Moscow schoolFootnote 16; however, in that tradition Juri LotmanFootnote 17 and others regarded language as the primary modeling system. This was because it had a central position in culture, and so, any secondary modeling system was supra-linguistic or, in other terms, language-derived. While Sebeok positions the Umwelt as fundamental, he simultaneously positions language as external to it. Admittedly, he saw “organism-environment interaction (i.e. species-specific Umwelt) as a crucial component of the growth of language in the individual”Footnote 18 – but he nevertheless asserted that language ultimately escapes the Umwelt, a view also adopted by Hoffmeyer.

The claim that language is a modeling system has an important implication, namely that language is not first and foremost (and was not originally) a verbal communication system. “Language ”, wrote Thomas Sebeok and Marcel Danesi, “is, by definition, a secondary cohesive modelling system providing humans with the resources for extending primary forms ad infinitum”.Footnote 19 In Prisca Augustyn’s words, the Umwelt, “in Sebeok’s working definition, ‘is a model generated by the organism’ […] to which language adds a secondary, cognitive dimension”.Footnote 20 While language transcends the Umwelt, it also gives it depth or detail. Sebeok thought that language initially above all had served “the cognitive function of modeling, and, as the philosopher Popper as well as the linguist Chomsky have likewise insisted […], not at all for the message swapping function of communication. The latter was routinely carried on by nonverbal means, as in all animals, and as it continues to be in the context of most human interactions today”.Footnote 21

The Tripartite Umwelt Model

Figure 1 shows the tripartite model of the human Umwelt.Footnote 22 In addition to the three aspects of Umwelt, the illustration displays Uexküll’s four main categories of functional cycles,Footnote 23 two of them in generalized form.

Fig. 1
figure 1

The tripartite model of the human Umwelt

By core Umwelt, I mean the aspect of Umwelt within which one interacts directly and immediately with other creatures or Umwelt objects, in (to use a figure of speech) “face-to-face” encounters.Footnote 24 By mediated Umwelt, I mean the aspect of Umwelt in which Umwelt objects are encountered indirectly by way of some mediation (memory, fantasy, anticipation, modern media, etc.). I suggest that this particular aspect of Umwelt can generally be associated with Uexküll’s notion of the Suchbild, the search image. Footnote 25 By conceptual Umwelt, I mean the aspect of Umwelt in which one navigates among Umwelt objects in terms of predicative reasoning in general or human language in particular. Conceptual Umwelt objects are in the latter case Umwelt objects whose functional meaning is imprinted linguistically. Though the conceptual Umwelt is particularly central in the human case (to the point where we confuse linguistic reality with reality as such), a number of “higher” animals qualify for being attributed conceptual Umwelten as well, in so far as they are capable of conducting predicative reasoning.Footnote 26 I theorise that these three layers interact dynamically so that one or two of the layers are occasionally temporarily suspended (in other words, human perception is subsequently focused – more or less exclusively – on different Umwelt layers).

The conceptual Umwelt is the most novel in evolutionary terms and, thus, corresponds broadly to what Sebeok characterised as humans’ secondary modelling system. But as we have seen, both Sebeok and Hoffmeyer think of human language as being external to the human Umwelt. For both of them the Umwelt represents the “animal” side of the human creature, whereas human culture can only be understood in terms of something (particularly language) that escapes the Umwelt. In my perspective, human language is a special case of more widespread systems of predicative reasoning, and enmeshed in the Umwelt that is our lifeworld, our phenomenal world. Language is internal to the Umwelt, i.e. part of the Umwelt, and there is a dynamic relationship between the conceptual side of Umwelt and the other aspects of Umwelt. This situates the Umwelt as a rich notion capable of serving as theoretical and methodological foundation for studies of the world of the living and the world of human affairs alike (for example, the tripartite model of the Umwelt may be applied as an ethogram in ethology, or for similar mapping purposes in ethnographic work).

The Role of Language and Predicative Reasoning in the Umwelt

While Sebeok held that supra-linguistic phenomena were constitutive of a tertiary modeling system, my assertion is rather that the impact of language on the human Umwelt is “thrown back in” and saturates other aspects of Umwelt. This concerns language-derived practices and far more. In short: the practice of languaging changes the human Umwelt not by escaping or sidelining it, but by fundamentally transforming it. In this process of recalibration, the core Umwelt may become “background” or otherwise loose in meaning.

Taking one step back, I will now explain what I mean by predicative reasoning, or the criterion for being endowed with a conceptual Umwelt. By predicative reasoning, I mean the mental act of ascribing a specific feature to someone or something. Animals that ascribe specific features to other living beings or objects in this manner are arguably capable of carrying out a fundamental form of logical reasoning. They thereby exercise a capacity which is indicative of rational judgment, and thus proto-linguistic capacities. An animal’s capacity for predicative reasoning can be more or less advanced and complex. And as we see, we can define the conceptual Umwelt as related to any kind of reasoning.

The inclusion into the tripartite Umwelt model of this notion makes it clear that I too conceive of the ability to language as a modelling system, or as an important aspect of the modelling system that is the Umwelt. This holds true even for proto-language in form of predicative reasoning, which must be assumed to be quite widespread among animals. These animals, too, have cognitive modelling capabilities that go well beyond the work performed by the core Umwelt, which is based in automated perceptual acts.

But some animals participate in human language. Animals that recognize, understand and act on a number of human words arguably have conceptual Umwelten that envelop elements of language (this rests on the assumption that they actually understand words as words). For example, sheep herding dogs respond to verbal commands such as “Come by”, “Lie down”, “Stop”, “Stand”, “Walk up”, “Steady”, “Right there”, “There, now”, “Look back” and “That will do”.Footnote 27

As Stephen J. Cowley points out, “[l]anguage and perception use bidirectional coupling that links experience with wordings; you thus anticipate what is (un)likely to come next”.Footnote 28 In the human context this implies, for one thing, that “our world is encultured”.Footnote 29 “We see and hear and otherwise experience very largely as we do because the language habits of our community predispose certain choices of interpretation”, as Edward Sapir writes.Footnote 30 As we become a part of a particular culture or language, notes Abram, “we implicitly begin to structure our sensory contact with the earth around us in a particular manner, paying attention to certain phenomena while ignoring others, differentiating textures, tastes, and tones in accordance with the verbal contrasts contained in the language”.Footnote 31 Bert H. Hodges strikingly observes that languaging binds us together and empowers us: “Humans may find their identity, partly at least, within the interactions we call linguistic. Perhaps language is metaphorically a kind of weak force that binds humans in ways that make them effective causal agents in the physical world”.Footnote 32

In order to make a more convincing case for the phenomenon of predicative reasoning, I will now, as background for this notion, outline the workings of the tripartite Umwelt in more detail. Specifically, my claim is that we can generally conceive of six types, or categories, of acts, and that these can be located within the three different aspects of the Umwelt:

  • Core Umwelt

    • Automated acts of perception

    • Automated mental acts

  • Mediated Umwelt

    • Wilful acts of perception

    • Wilful mental acts

  • Conceptual Umwelt

    • Habitual acts of perception

    • Habitual mental acts

The elements involved are quite few: perceptual acts and mental acts which are each either automated (by which I mean the exact and physiologically based matching of something with something else), wilful (by which I mean the agenda- and interest-driven matching of something with something else) or habitual (by which I mean the learned matching of something with something else). But the distinctions implied are crucial: whereas conscious animals (with a brain, mind, and mental activity) carry out all six types of acts, non-conscious creatures, in so far as they perceive (in a broad sense), only carry out two, namely automated acts of perception and wilful acts of perception. These do not have any conceptual Umwelt, their Umwelten consist only of two aspects, the core aspect and the mediated aspect. Habitual, i.e. conceptual acts are reserved for conscious creatures (but even bacteria can carry out wilful acts of perception, i.e. make choices based on interpretation).

Here, language is implicitly said to be habitual. This is not to be associated with behaviourist language acquisition theories based on the work of, for instance, Burrhus Frederic Skinner.Footnote 33 According to this approach language is learned by way of simple stimulus-response mechanisms, and habit formation occurs as imitations of correct associations are encouraged via a sort of positive response. Within an Uexküllian framework, it does of course make sense to say that associative learning occurs, but language acquisition is more meaningfully looked upon as happening in the context of the individual Umwelt, or more specifically by way of the contextualization in (or integration into) the Umwelttunnel (i.e., the personally experienced chain-of-events throughout someone’s life) of the learner. Language acquisition, therefore, is extensively based on interpretation (as well as on social expectations). Moreover, the characterization of language as habitual is not only relevant for language acquisition, but just as much for adult, mature language practices at large.

Previously I defined predicative reasoning as the mental act of ascribing a specific feature to someone or something, and contrasted it with automated acts of perception. We now see, for one thing, that it must also be distinguished from wilful acts of perception. In general terms automated acts can be said to be code-based, whereas both wilful acts and habitual acts are interpretation-based.Footnote 34 Simple creatures such as bacteria are capable of interpretation, and thus of making choices, but they are not capable of predicative reason, which is a capacity that is displayed only by conscious (brained, mindful) creatures.

Languaging as Perception , Action and Self-Deception

I began to wonder if my culture’s assumptions regarding the lack of awareness in other animals […] was less a product of careful and judicious reasoning than of a strange inability to clearly perceive other animals – a real inability to clearly see, or focus upon, anything outside the realm of human technology, or to hear as meaningful anything other than human speech.(Abram 1997, p. 27)

Languaging is More-than-Linguistic

In this third section I outline some core perspectives of distributed language (DL), before proceeding to present my notion of the anthropocentric mistake and discuss some implications. The distributed language perspective, which I consider to be largely aligned with my approach based on the Umwelt theory , is dealt with using five key terms, namely languaging, first-order languaging, movement, interactivity and enkinaesthesia.

Languaging is a term originally coined by Humberto MaturanaFootnote 35 to refer to complex behaviors oriented to the creation and sustaining of “consensual domains”.Footnote 36 He held that all living systems language. Footnote 37 By contemporary proponents of the DL view the term is rather used to emphasise that language is an activity rather than some set of formal abstracta. In Cowley’s words, “[l]anguage is activity in which wordings play a part”.Footnote 38 “Rather than view language as an object”,Footnote 39 DL enthusiasts tend to say, we should focus on first-order activity or human languaging.

A crucial distinction is Nigel Love’s first-order languaging and second-order language (said to have originated in Love’s work in 2004,Footnote 40 where there is talk of first-order “activity” and second-order “cognition”Footnote 41). As Martin Neumann and Stephen J. Cowley point out, “linguists typically confuse language with second-order constructs”.Footnote 42 In Paul Thibault’s words, first-order languaging refers to “the organization of process on different scales that takes place when persons engage in talk together”.Footnote 43 “First-order languaging crucially involves synchronized interindividual bodily dynamics on very short, rapid timescales of the order of fractions of seconds to milliseconds. […] Persons in talk enact, exploit, respond to, and attune to such events in order to engage with others and to coconstruct their worlds with them”.Footnote 44 Thibault further explains that “[f]irst-order languaging is a whole-body sense-making activity that enables persons to engage with each other in forms of coaction”.Footnote 45 As we see, this notion encompasses movement. “Since human movements both enact and elicit interpretations”, writes Sune Vork Steffensen, “we orient to norms (and judge people by how they do so)”.Footnote 46 “While language can be mapped onto grammatical, semantic, discursive functions, human activity is whole bodied movement. As we orient to circumstances, and each other, we give a particular sense to the vagueness of (verbal) language. […] While rooted in bodily movement, language is symbiotic: at times, dynamics dominate, at times, the verbal aspect of language”.Footnote 47

As Cowley notes, “[v]erbal patterns constrain bodily movements and the feeling of thinking as people co-ordinate the flow of activity. […] Co-ordination becomes a means of embodying thoughts”.Footnote 48 The motive of interindividual bodily dynamics overlaps with that of interactivity. Thibault observes that research in infant semiosis “shows very clearly that from the very earliest stages of the child’s meaning-making, that is, well before the onset of language, the processes involved are in fact fundamentally dialogic and intersubjective”.Footnote 49 Steffensen defines interactivity as “sense-saturated coordination that contributes to human action”.Footnote 50 If it wasn’t for the qualifying term human, one would think that this definition should make the term applicable in animal studies as well, since many animals are no less coordinated than ourselves, and perform wonderful coaction.

Interactivity points us further, to the notion of enkinaesthesia, coined by philosopher Susan Stuart.

“Enkinaesthesia” is a neologism I will use to refer to the reciprocally affective neuro-muscular dynamical flows and muscle tensions that are felt and enfolded between co-participating agents in dialogical relation with one another. Enkinaesthesia, like intersubjectivity and intercorporeality relates to notions of affect, but in this case it is with the affect we have on the neuro-muscular dynamical flow and muscle tension of the other, including other animals, through our direct and our indirect touch.Footnote 51

Enkinaesthesia, then, is our felt sensitivity to the sensitivity of others – and a crucial aspect of interactivity, coaction, and social life. Enkinaesthesia arguably makes us human – and, indeed, animal.Footnote 52 Lived experience, in Stuart’s view, is, first and foremost, enkinaesthetic.

Language and Self-Deception: The Anthropocentric Mistake

Identity is an intriguing thing. It is so obvious to us, who we are – or so it appears. Human identity is largely a linguistic phenomenon.Footnote 53 But fundamental as language is in constituting human cognitive reality, we are not entirely linguistic creatures. Man is not a sign. Man is not language. Man is not simply what it thinks it is (Man is not identity). Rather, Man is a creature who organizes ecological reality in linguistic categories – both perceptually and behaviourally.

It is very commonplace, therefore, to commit the anthropocentric mistake, namely to reason (erroneously) that human reality is practically all there is. We tend to think in terms of language, and in terms of language, all is language. All is human language – therefore all is human. What we do not realize when committing this mistake is that it is not only Man who judges, who categorizes, who organizes, who is different, and so forth.

The anthropocentric – or indeed linguistic – mistake, then, consists in mistaking human reality for reality as such.Footnote 54 Misjudging the nature of reality, we misjudge our nature – living nature – human nature. To put it bluntly, current mainstream views on language which are aligned with the anthropocentric mistake result in a string of distorted realities. They distort our view on consciousness, on experience, on knowledge/knowing, on reality, and on value, by making us believe that these are human phenomena only (or predominantly). As a result, philosophy of consciousness, phenomenology, epistemology and philosophy of science, ontology, ethics and aesthetics all underachieve in comparison with their innate potential.

The classical Thomas theorem in sociology can shed light on the psychology of the anthropocentric mistake: “If men define situations as real, they are real in their consequences”.Footnote 55 If people intuitively define human language and everything that can be associated with it as real, and Abram is correct in stating that we have developed an inability to “hear as meaningful anything other than human speech”,Footnote 56 as cited in the motto of this section, then from a psychological perspective it makes perfect sense to disregard non-linguistic reality almost completely.

The anthropocentric mistake can be further clarified with reference to Cowley’s notion of taking a language stance: “[H]earing ‘words’ is like seeing ‘things’ in pictures. This is described as taking a language stance. To defend the position, it is argued that, first, we learn to hear wordings and, later, to use ‘what we hear’ as ways of constraining our actions”.Footnote 57 As described by Cowley, this implies “that humans depend on taking ‘a language stance’ or hearing utterances as if they really were little units (a view further encouraged by literacy)”.Footnote 58

This latter sentence resonates well with Abram’s observation: “Only when a more thoroughly phonetic system of writing spreads throughout a culture do its members come to doubt the expressive agency of other animals and of the animate earth. Only in the wake of the alphabet does language come to be experienced as an exclusively human power”.Footnote 59

In Search of the Dark Matter of Our Enlightened Worlds

According to J. von UexküllFootnote 60 everything that falls under the spell of the Umwelt is retuned and transformed until it has become a useful carrier of meaning, or it is totally neglected. As we have seen, language is a powerful framer of behavior and of perception. In the context of human beings, the Umwelt is quite fluid (i.e. amenable to change) both individually and temporally for society as such. As languaging and human practices develop, so do our respective Umwelten. What is gained in this process, and what is lost? What is certain is that nowadays language, language-derived practices and various media playing into our mediated Umwelten are becoming ever more dominant. What then of our actual encounters with other living beings? If reality as we perceive it is consistently linguistic, then what role do we have to assign to non-human nature?

Despite these tendencies toward alienation from nature, it remains the case, as we have seen earlier, that all languaging is underpinned by interbodily dynamics and sensual, carnal experience. And of course, any human doing is furthermore underpinned by an array of intercellular and ecological activities. We are just not always aware that this is the case – it belongs to the untold, the unseen which nevertheless sustains our conversations and our thoughts, our doings and our deeds.

In Language : The Cultural Tool, Daniel L. EverettFootnote 61 introduces the notion of “‘dark cognitive and cultural matter’ that appears in what is not said in discourse”.Footnote 62 Though critical of aspects of Everett’s book, Cowley nevertheless concurs that this is an interesting concept. “In Everett’s idiom”, he writes, “dark cultural matter imbues language with values”. Cowley adds that “language shapes lives as individuals sensitize to dark cultural matter”.Footnote 63

Everett’s point, or claim, is that any culture envelops much that is simply taken for granted. Therefore a full transcription of an everyday conversation will not spell out all there is to say about what two or more people have just talked about. What two persons both take for granted may be treated as given, when they speak. And it does indeed appear to be the case that volatile conversations are often characterized by uncertainty about what the other person is taking for granted.

How can we escape having a tunnel vision of language (seeing only what is in plain sight)? How do we contribute to shaping our own Umwelten in a healthy, sustainable, ecologically grounded manner? How can we co-create Umwelten that we are not all too ashamed to pass on to our children? We may have to reeducate ourselves. Learn how to see again. How can we study the “dark matter” of our enlightened worlds? Given all the dark matter underpinning and surrounding verbal practices, a foray into the hinterland of language – the land which sustains us – is definitively called for. Best of luck on that journey!

The Genesis and Modalities of Language

We get into the habit of living before acquiring the habit of thinking.(Camus 1942 [1983, p. 8])

Origin and Evolution of Language

An Umwelt trajectory can be characterized as the course through evolutionary (or cultural) time taken by the Umwelt of a creature, as defined by its changing relations with the Umwelten of other creatures.Footnote 64 One way to portray the Umwelt trajectory of humankind in the most general terms possible would be to depict the human Umwelt in its aspect of emerging layers or aspects (cf. the core Umwelt, the mediated Umwelt, and the conceptual Umwelt). In the history of life in general, the core Umwelt is without doubt the initial Umwelt. It is equally clear that the next layer to emerge must have been the mediated Umwelt, followed by the conceptual Umwelt as the latest and most advanced aspect of Umwelt. But humankind must have had all three aspects of Umwelt from the outset, and several animal species likewise. So if we were to portray the Umwelt trajectory of humankind in these terms, we would have to go very far back in our pre-human evolutionary history. A macro-evolutionary event that is more characteristic of human existence is the emergence of languaging practices (followed, later on, by literacy).

As Sverker Johansson remarks, however, “there is no consensus on when the transition from non-language to language took place, nor any consensus on the species of the first language users”.Footnote 65 Our subspecies, Homo sapiens sapiens, might not have been the first one to language, since other human subspecies (now extinct) might perhaps have developed the practice of languaging before us. Johansson examines whether Neanderthals had language, and asserts that “the preponderance of the evidence supports the presence of at least a spoken proto-language with lexical semantics in Neanderthals”.Footnote 66 This conclusion, he writes, would be strengthened if genetic data suggesting that interbreeding between Neanderthals and modern humans took place were confirmed.Footnote 67 Just as there is no consensus on when language emerged, neither is there any consensus on “the nature of this transition – was it a sharp single-step leap […] or a gradual evolution in many small steps”Footnote 68? Noam Chomsky is among those who argue that the transition must have been sharp.Footnote 69

“If language is not a purely mental phenomenon”, writes Abram,Footnote 70 “but a sensuous, bodily activity born of carnal reciprocity and participation, then our discourse has surely been influenced by many gestures, sounds, and rhythms besides those of our single species” – including birds.Footnote 71 What is remarkable with regard to the evolution of language is that of the genes that have been identified as relevant for language abilities, “virtually all […] are present also in animals. All known genes of language, in other words, are genes of the primary modelling system that we have inherited from our animal ancestors”.Footnote 72 This is consistent with the view, shared by Chomsky and Sebeok , that language evolved as an exaptation, i.e. that the function of language has changed from one (e.g., cognitive modelling) to another (e.g., communication).Footnote 73

Hoffmeyer too shares this view, and builds on both Thomas Sebeok and Gregory BatesonFootnote 74: “Implicit [in G. Bateson’s theory] is the idea that [the verbal aspect of] language has not – at least to begin with – served any communicational purpose (similar in style to that of body language) whatsoever, but that it has more likely been associated with the development of a quite new type of inner, mental concept – let us call it a cognitive model”.Footnote 75 As we have seen, the tripartite Umwelt model implies that the conceptual Umwelt must have emerged long before language. The modelling capabilities involved in predicative reasoning were arguably there for hundreds of millions (but not billions) of years before language evolved. This suggests that human language is a later, more commanding derivative of such capabilities. Just like predicative reasoning does for any animal endowed with it, language affords the human organism with the capacity to organise its Umwelt objects and factors more meticiously. Despite all the matchless characteristics of language, this suggests that the difference between language and other forms of predicative reasoning is in the end a matter of degree, or perhaps more fittingly of magnitude.

Acquisition of Language in Childhood

Besides Umwelt trajectories, the evolution and development of language can also be depicted in terms of an Umwelt transition,Footnote 76 i.e. a lasting, systematic change within the life cycle of a being from one typical appearance of its Umwelt to another. A human child arguably goes through several Umwelt transitions, or a very multifaceted one, as it learns to language. As Albert Camus says in his Myth of Sisyphus, “[w]e get into the habit of living before acquiring the habit of thinking” – and similarly, we arguably get into the habit of languaging before acquiring language.

With reference to Adolf Portmann’s work, Barbieri neatly describes how being born prematurely (due to our short gestation period relative to lifespan compared with other mammals) affects our brain development and implicitly our capacity for language learning: “In all other mammals, the wiring of the brain takes place almost completely in the dark and protected environment of the uterus, whereas in our species, it takes place predominantly outside the uterus, where the body is exposed to the lights, the sounds and the smells of a constantly changing environment”.Footnote 77 In effect, he suggests, the constraint of the birth canal “has split the foetal development of our brain into two distinct processes, one within and one without the uterus”.Footnote 78 This is crucial biological background for our species’ character of being a generalist species, and for our understanding of language learning.

The Various Linguistic Modalities of the Human Umwelt

In point 4 of the platform for a semiotics of being,Footnote 79 I refer to speechless Umwelten, spoken Umwelten and alphabetic Umwelten as distinct categories of human Umwelten. Practically every human being, we may assert, experiences within his/her lifetime a transition from a speechless Umwelt to a spoken one – most persons further to a more or less alphabetic or pictographic one. Additionally, there are situations – states of mind – where we so to speak loose (or deliberately pause) our ability to speak, or to perceive in terms of language. These are border cases of the speechless and the spoken, some of them bordering on insanity.

Beyond the Anthropocentric Mistake: Languaging as if Nature Mattered

Today’s intrepid researchers have yet to notice that the human body, in itself, is no more autonomous – and no more conscious – than an isolated brain. Sentience is not an attribute of a body in isolation; it emerges from the ongoing encounter between our flesh and the forest of rhythms in which it finds itself, born of the interplay and tension between the world’s wild hunger and our own.(Abram 2010, p. 110)

The recently deceased Estonian geologist and palaeontologist Ivar Puura (1961–2012) coined the notion of semiocide, which he defined as “a situation in which signs and stories that are significant for someone are destroyed because of someone else’s malevolence or carelessness, thereby stealing a part of the former’s identity”.Footnote 80 “By wholesale replacement of primeval nature with artificial environments”, writes Puura, “[a]t the hands of humans, millions of stories with billions of relations and variations perish”.Footnote 81 As Timo Maran notes,

Puura most correctly stresses that nowadays the phenomenon of semiocide is very widespread both in human culture and society as well as in relations between culture and nature. Unfortunately, semiotics appears to have overlooked this dark side of semiotic relations, as is evident from the lack of a conceptual framework and studies dedicated to this topic. […] This is a question of the ethical responsibility of semiotics.Footnote 82

Language is relevant here for two reasons. First, because when languages are going extinct, semiocide occurs and, second, because language can make us blind to the ongoing non-linguistic semiocide. The way we language around for example animals is telling of our relationship towards them. As Arran Stibbe notes, “the discourses we use to construct our conceptions of animals and nature have important consequences for the well-being of the animals and the ecosystems that support life”.Footnote 83 If cognition is situated, embodied, extended and distributed, then we can engage in “thinking with animals”Footnote 84 in a literal sense. This chapter ends with three theses on the ethos of human-animal relations, which have implications for ethics, ontology and epistemology:

  1. 1.

    Language and languaging largely originated in human-animal co-action. Language did not emerge in a merely human setting.

  2. 2.

    In the modern era many people are inexperienced with regard to traditional human-animal encounters (and thus alienated with regard to nature).

  3. 3.

    In the future, it would be beneficial for people and animals alike if languaging practices around animals would entail less anticipated muteness and rely more on enkinaesthesia, “the entwined, blended and situated co-affective feeling of the presence of the other”.Footnote 85