Keywords

These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Generally speaking, it seems no one doubts that healthFootnote 1 is a good thing and illness bad, that the former is the norm and the latter an anomaly. It is impossible even to define health as anything other than the normal state of an organism. Nor is there any other definition of illness than “a deviation of physiological life from the norm.” However, the anomaly of physiological life called an illness is not a meaningless accident or an arbitrary creation by external, evil forces outside the patient. Apart from the inevitable illnesses of growth or development, all thoughtful physicians opine that the true cause of illness lies in internal, deeply rooted changes in the organism itself and that the external immediate causes of a sickness (e.g., a cold, exhaustion, infection) are only occasions for the manifestation of the inner cause. The same symptoms that those who do not know better usually take for the illness itself (e.g., a fever, a chill, a cough, various aches, abnormal secretions) in fact express only the successful or unsuccessful struggle of the organism against the destructive action of those internal disorders. Undoubtedly, these disorders are the genuine essence of the illness, even though their ultimate basis is for the most part enigmatic. The practical conclusion from this is that the chief object of the art of medicine is not the external symptoms of an illness, but its inner causes. The art of medicine must, at least, determine their factual presence [424]and then,Footnote 2 through curative actions, help the organism itself by speeding up and supplementingFootnote 3 these natural processes without forcing them.

The chronic illness of humanity , international hostility, which expresses itself in war , is in a similar position. To treat its symptoms, i.e., to direct our treatments not on the internal causes, but only on their external manifestations, would even on the best occasion only be a doubtful palliative. The simple and unconditional rejection of this illness would make no real sense. External wars have taken place as long as there has been moral disorder within humanity, and they still may be necessary and useful just as fever and vomiting serve as necessary and useful symptoms of an illness that belies a deep physical disorder.

Properly speaking, concerning the issue of war we ought to pose not one, but three different questions. In addition to the general moral value of war, there is anotherFootnote 4 question that has to do with its significance in the as yet unfinished history of humanity . Finally, there is a third question, a personal one, concerning how I, i.e., any human being who through conscience and reason recognizes the obligatory nature of moral demands, should regard here and now the fact of war and the practical consequences that follow from it. Confusing or incorrectly separating these three questions—one concerning general or theoretical morality, another the historical and finally a question of personal or practical morality—form the chief cause of all the misunderstandings and misconceptions regarding war, particularly those prevalent in recent times.Footnote 5

A principled condemnation of war was already a common enough occurrence a long time ago in human development. Everyone agrees that peace is good and war evil. We automatically, as it were, utter the expression: the blessings of peace, the horrors of war. No one so much as ventures to say the opposite: “the benefits of war” or “the disasters of peace.” Prayers are said in all churches for times of peace and for deliverance from the sword or battles, which are placed alongside fire, famine, pestilence, earthquake and flood. Except for savage paganism, all religions condemn war in principle. The Jewish prophets already preached the coming pacification of all humanity and even of all nature. The Buddhist principle of compassion for all living creatures demands the same thing. The Christian commandment to love one’s enemies excludes war, since a loved enemy ceases to be an enemy, and for that reason [425]one cannot wage war on him. Even the bellicose religion of Islam looks on war as only a temporary necessity, condemning it in principle. “Fight your enemies as long as Islam is not established,” and then, “let all hostility cease,” because “God hates aggressors” (Qur’an, surah II).Footnote 6

With respect to morality in general, there are not and cannot be two views on this subject. Everyone unanimously agrees that peace is normal and what should be the case, whereas war is an anomaly, i.e., what should not be the case.

II

Thus, as to the first question about war, there is only one undisputed answer: War is an evil. Evil can be either unconditional (e.g., a mortal sin, eternal damnation) or relative, i.e., one evil can be less evil than another and compared to this other must be considered a good (e.g., a surgical operation for saving a life).

Defining war negatively as an evil and a horror does not exhaust its meaning. There is also something positive about war—Footnote 7 not in the sense that it is in itself normal, but simply in the fact that it happens to be a real necessity under the given conditions. This point of view towards abnormal phenomena in general cannot be avoided,Footnote 8 but mustFootnote 9 be adopted owing to the direct demands of the moral principle and not in contradiction to it. So, for example, everyone will agree that throwing children from a window onto the pavement below is in itself godless, inhuman and unnatural.Footnote 10 However, if in the case of a fire there is no other means to extricate unfortunate infants from a blazing house, then this terrible action becomes not only permissible but even obligatory. Obviously, the rule to throw children from a window in extreme cases is not an independent principle on the same level as the moral principle of saving those who are perishing. On the contrary, the latter moral demand remains here the sole motivation for acting. There is no deviation in this instance from the moral norm. Throwing children from a window is only a direct application of that norm in a manner that, though irregular and dangerous, turns out to be, owing to its real necessity, the only possible one under the given conditions.

[426]Does war depend upon a necessity that makes this in itself abnormal course of action permissible and even obligatory in certain circumstances? This question can be answered by turning to history. Sometimes, however, it is erroneously viewed from the broader perspective of natural science, where the necessity of war is connected with the allegedly universal principle of the struggle for existence.

In fact, though, neither in the animal kingdom nor among humans does the struggle for existence have anything in common with war. When it is said that a certain animal species has been victorious in the struggle for existence, this does not mean that it has defeated some enemies in direct clashes or in public battles. It only means that due to sufficient adaptation to the external environment or to the surrounding conditions, the species has managed to survive and multiply, which not all have equally succeeded in doing. If Siberian mammoths disappeared owing to their defeat in the struggle for survival whereas martens were victorious, this certainly does not mean that martens were braver and more powerful than mammoths and eliminated them in open combat by employing their teeth and paws. Similarly, the Jewish nation, which disarmed a long time ago and is comparatively small in numbers, has turned out to be indestructible in the historical struggle for existence, whereas military successes over many centuries did not protect the enormous Roman Empire from ruin nor those of the bellicose powers that preceded it.

The struggle for existence takes place independently of wars and utilizes other methods that have nothing in common with fighting. Similarly, war, for its part, has other grounds, independent of the struggle for a means to continue living. If the entire issue were over these means, if hostile clashes took place only for the sake of livelihood, then the primitive epoch of history would have been the most peaceful. For very few people were alive at the time, their demands were simple and a great expanse for their satisfaction stretched out before them. Fighting and mutual extermination posed only risk and no profit. In this respect, the normal outcome of any quarrel is by itself obvious. “And Abram said unto Lot, Let there be no strife, I pray thee, between me and thee, and between my herdmen and thy herdmen; for [427]we be brethren. Is not the whole land before thee? Separate thyself, I pray thee, from me: if thou wilt take the left hand, then I will go to the right; or if thou depart to the right hand, then I will go to the left. And Lot lifted up his eyes, and beheld all the plain of Jordan, that it was well watered every where, before the LORD destroyed Sodom and Gomorrah, even as the garden of the LORD, like the land of Egypt, as thou comest unto Zoar. Then Lot chose him all the plain of Jordan; and Lot journeyed east: and they separated themselves the one from the other” (Genesis 13: 8–11).

If, however, such an amicable agreement only rarely took place at the time and, in general, primitive human relations more closely resembled a “war of all against all” (as in the well-known theory of the philosopher Hobbes) ,Footnote 11 then this was the result not of a necessary struggle for existence but of the free play of evil passions. Envy , not hunger, caused the fratricide with which history opens. The oldest monument of poetry that has been handed down to us—the bloody song of Cain’s grandson, Lamech—speaks not of material need, but of savage spite, revengeFootnote 12 and fierce arrogance. “And Lamech said unto his wives, Adah and Zillah, Hear my voice; ye wives of Lamech, hearken unto my speech: for I have slain a man to my wounding, and a young man to my hurt. If Cain shall be avenged sevenfold, truly Lamech seventy and sevenfold” (Genesis 4: 23–24).

III

At a time when the human race was few in number and multiplying slowly compared to most other animals, the predominance of such feelings would have threatened humanity with quick ruinFootnote 13 if the war of all against all had not been ­counterbalanced by the gentile connection. This connection, rooted in the maternal instinct, is developed by means of family feelings and relations and is strengthened in the religion of ancestor-veneration. The gentile way of life (in the broad sense),Footnote 14, Footnote 15 which resulted from all this, can be considered the primitive stage of historical development, since humanity, properly speaking, never consisted of single, separate solitary individualsFootnote 16 in a state of war with each other. The gentile connection [428]existed right from the start and “the war of all against all,” as a general rule, expresses a mutual relationship not between separate units,Footnote 17 but only between separate gentile groups. Of course, this does not mean that each gens was in fact inFootnote 18 constant war with all the others, but only that no single gens was completely secure or protected from the possibility of war with any other gens. Such a state of affairs, however, could not last forever. Only rarely did a war between gentes end with the destruction of the weaker gens. Achieving a certain equality of power, the outcome of the struggle was a religiously consecrated treaty or agreement. On the other hand, in order to avoid destruction in an unequal struggle the weaker gentile groups either separately joined a more powerful gens, agreeing to conditions of submission, or many of them together formed a union with various rights (a federation). Thus, war itself gives rise to treaties and rights as a guarantee of peace. Such gentile unions are already the embryo of the state.

From the time when we begin to have continuous historical records, a considerable part of the human race was already living under the state system. There are two fundamental types of such states: the Western or Hellenic polity, i.e., a small city community, and the vast Eastern despotism of either one nation (for example, in Egypt) or of many nations (the so called “universal monarchies”Footnote 19).

Without the state, it would have been impossible to have human cultural progress based on a complex collaboration (cooperation) of many forces. To a large extent, such collaboration was impossible for isolated gentes living in a state of constant blood feud with each other. In the state, we find human masses for the first time acting in solidarity. These masses already banished war and moved it out to the wider circumference of the state. In the gentile way of life, all (adult males) are always armed, whereas in the state warriors form either a special caste or profession, or finally (with universal conscription) military service forms only a temporary occupation of the citizenry. In the state, the organization of war is the first great step towards the realization of peace . This is especially clear in the history of the vast conquering powers (the universal [429]monarchies). Each conquest meant a dissemination of peace, i.e., an expansion of the circle within which war ceased being a normal phenomenon and instead became a rare and reprehensible accident—criminal civil dissension. The “universal monarchies” strove indubitably, though also only semi-consciously, to give peace to the world by subduing all nations to one common power. The greatest of these conquering powers, the Roman Empire, frankly described itself as the peace—pax Romana.

However, there were monarchies at an earlier time that also strove for the same goal. Discoveries in the nineteenthFootnote 20 century leave no doubt that the Assyrian and the Persian kings considered their true vocation to be the subjugation of all nations in order to establish a peaceful order on Earth, although their idea of this task and of the way to fulfill it was usually too simplistic. The historical plans of the Macedonian monarchy that included the entire world were more complex and productive. It rested on the superior power of the Hellenic culture, which deeply and firmly penetrated into the subjugated Eastern world. The Romans came to a completely clear idea of universal and eternal peace and firmly believed in their vocation to subjugate the entire world to the power of one single law. Virgil, in particular, immortalized this idea. Besides the very well-known expression “tu regere imperio populos”Footnote 21 etc.

You, o Roman, have the right to rule over nations mightily,

To protect humbly, subduing the obstinate by arms Footnote 22

he returns to it at every opportunity in his Aeneid as the highest motive inspiring the entire poem. Jupiter is represented, for example, as saying to Venus about her descendants:

Romulus shall call that people ‘Romans,’ after his own name.

I set no limits to their fortunes and

no time; I give them empire without end.Footnote 23

Aeneid I 278–294

The same supreme god tells Mercury that Aeneas, the ancestor of the Romans, is destined to conquer an Italy stirring with war [430]in order to establish the nobleFootnote 24 line of the Teucer, who will “place all earth beneath his laws” (The Aeneid, book IV, pp. 229–231).Footnote 25

Comparing the four “universal monarchies,” we find in their succession a steady approach to the idea of universal peace, both with respect to their extension as well as with respect to inner principles. The first of these, the Assyro-Babylonian kingdom, did not extend beyond the bounds of the Near East, was supported by incessantFootnote 26 devastating campaigns and its laws consisted solely of military decrees. The second “universal monarchy,” the kingdom of Cyrus and the Achaemenides, added to the Near East a significant portion of central Asia and extended in the other direction to Egypt. It rested from within on the serene religion of Ormuzd,Footnote 27 which legitimated morality and justice. In the third monarchy, that of Alexander and his successors, the historical East was united for the first time with the historical West, and not only the power of the sword but also the ideal principles of Hellenic culture welded the two sidesFootnote 28 together. Lastly, the progress represented by the fourth monarchy, the Roman Empire, consisted not only in that the Romans extended the earlier unity all the way to the Atlantic Ocean, but also in that they gave this unity a solid political center and a stable judicial form. War played an inevitable role and armed might served as the necessary support in this whole business of establishing peace. War and peace were accurately symbolized by the two opposed but inseparable faces of the Roman god Janus.Footnote 29

War proves to be the most forceful unifier of the inner forces within each warring state or union. At the same time, it serves as the condition for the subsequent rapprochement and coming together of the opponents themselves. We see both of these most clearly in the history of Greece. Only three times in its entire history did the majority of  Footnote 30 the separate tribes and city-states unite for a common cause and manifest their inner national connection in a practical way. Each of these times, it was due to a war: the Trojan War at the beginning, the Persian Wars at the middle, and the campaign of Alexander the Great as its culminating achievement. It was thanks to the last that the creations of the Greek national genius finally became the common property of humanity.

The Trojan War established the Greek element in Asia Minor, where nurtured by other cultural elements, it first blossomed. [431]Greek poetry (the Homeric epos) was born on the shores of Asia Minor, and it was there that the most ancient school of their philosophy (Thales of Miletus, Heraclitus of Ephesus) arose and developed. The emergence of the united national forces in the struggle with the Persians brought forth a second, even richer blossoming of spiritual creativity, and Alexander’s conquests, which cast the ripe seeds of Hellenism onto the ancient and cultured soil of Asia and Egypt, yielded the great Hellenic-Eastern synthesis of religious and philosophical ideas. It was these ideas, along with the subsequent unification by the Roman state that created the necessary historical condition for the dissemination of Christianity. Without the Greek language and Greek ideas, as well as without the “Roman peace” and Roman militaryFootnote 31 roads, the preaching of the Gospels could not have taken place so quickly and on such a wide scale. Greek words and ideas entered the public domain only thanks to the militaristic Alexander and his generals. Over many centuries of war, the Roman “peace” was achieved and preserved by the Roman legions, and for these legions roads were constructed and along them the apostles passed. The churches sing, “Yes verily, their sound went into all the earth, and their words unto the ends of the world.”Footnote 32 This “all the earth” and these “ends of the world” are only the wide circle (orbis) that Rome’s bloody sword sketched around itself.

Therefore, all the wars of which ancient history abounds merely extended the sphere of peace, and the pagan “bestial kingdoms” Footnote 33 prepared the way for those who would announce the kingdom of the son of man.

However, in addition to this the military history of antiquity shows us important progress in the direction of peace even in another respect. Not only has war achieved peaceful ends, but with the further march of history fewer and fewer active military forces were needed to attain these ends, whereas, on the contrary, the peaceful results became ever the more numerous and important. This paradoxical fact is indisputable. In order to take Troy, an almost universal conscription among the Greeks was necessary for 10 years,Footnote 34 and the direct result of this terrible exercise of its forces was insignificant. A great catastrophe [432]crowned Greek history, namely, the conquest of the East by Alexander the Great, and the universal cultural consequences of this catastrophe were not slow in coming to light. All that was required on the part of the military was a 3-year campaign with thirteen thousand warriors. Let us, on the one hand, compare the significance of the results and, on the other hand, consider the population of Greece and Macedonia under Alexander compared with the small Achaean population, which sent such a large military contingent (110,000 men) to Troy. We will see, then, in a stark fashion that after these seven centuries the relative number of human lives that had to be sacrificed to achieve historical goals decreased. Another comparison of a more general character leads to the same conclusion. The Persian kingdom, whose millions of soldiers could not ensure military success in the struggle with tiny Greece,Footnote 35 was barely able to hold up under the protection of such forces for two centuries. The Roman Empire, three times as large and with a population of no less than 200 million, kept at most 400,000 legionnaires under arms for the defense of its vast borders and lasted three times longer than the kingdom of Darius and Xerxes (around six centuries). And how immeasurably more important to humanity were the fruits of civilizationFootnote 36 which these few legions protected compared with that for the sake of which the innumerable hordes of the king of kings assembled!

Therefore, the progress in the business of war represented by the advantages of the Macedonian phalanx and the Roman legion over the Persian hordes expressed itself, generally speaking, in the preponderance of quality over quantity and of form over matter. At the same time, it represented great moral and social progress by enormously reducing the number of the human casualties devoured by war.

IV

From an external historical standpoint, the replacement of the Roman world (and peace) by the Christian did not immediately bring about any essential change in the status of the problem of war. True, in unconditionally condemning all hatred and hostility, Christianity in principle [433]destroyed the moral root of war. However, cutting the root is still not the same as felling the tree. Indeed, the preachers of the Gospels did not want to fell Nebuchadnezzar’s tree,Footnote 37 for they knew that the Earth needed its shade until the true faith emerged from the small seed that would replace it, “the greatest among herbs”Footnote 38 in whose shade both people and beasts of the field can safely hide.

The Christian missionaries did not reject the state and its vocationFootnote 39 to “execute wrath upon him that doeth evil.”Footnote 40 Consequently, they did not reject war. The followers of the new faith saw for themselves a great triumph in the fact that two victorious wars gave Emperor Constantine the chance to hoist the Cross of Christ over the old, unaltered edifice of the Roman Empire. Moreover, under this unaltered political exterior the secret work of spiritual forces was hidden. For the Christian, the state, even one blessed by the cross, ceased to be the highest good and the final form of life. Faith in eternal Rome, i.e., in the unconditional significance of political unity, was replaced by the expectation of a “New Jerusalem,” i.e., of an inner, spiritual union of reborn peoples and nations. However, apart from an elevation, a lifting of human consciousness to a higher level, the progress of an external real unification within the body of humanity continued, though slowly at first.

The Christian world (tota christianitas, toute la chrétienté),Footnote 41 which in the Middle Ages replaced the ancient Roman Empire, covered a significantly greater expanse. True, wars were not unusual within it. (Just as in the Roman Empire, there were revolts of peoples and mutinous generals.) However, the representatives of Christian principles saw these wars as deplorable internecine conflicts and tried in every way to limit them. Also, the constant struggle between the Christian and the Moslem worlds (in Spain and in the Levant), undoubtedly had a positive cultural and progressive character. For the defense of Christianity against the Islamic offensive saved the pledge of a higher spiritual development for historical humanity instead of being absorbed by a comparativelyFootnote 42 lower religious principle.Footnote 43 Moreover, the interaction of these two fundamentally hostile worlds could not be confined to bloodlettingFootnote 44 alone. In time, this interaction would lead to [434]an expansion of the intellectual outlook of both sides. The great epoch of the Renaissance of the arts and sciences and then of the Reformation was thereby prepared for Christianity.

Three general facts in modern history have the greatest significance for our problem:

(1) the emergence of nationalities, (2) the corresponding emergence of international relations of all sorts, and (3) the dissemination of cultural unity around the entire globe.

After breaking out from under the tutelage of the Catholic Church and rejecting the impotent claims of the Holy Roman Empire, the European nationalities segregated themselves into autocraticFootnote 45 political units. Each national state viewed itself and was viewed by others as a perfect body, i.e., as having supremacy or absolute and full power within its borders and consequently as not being subordinate to any outside earthly tribunal. The direct consequences of this national segregation were not favorable to the cause of peace. In the first place, war even among Christian states thereby became a regular occurrence, for it served as the sole means of resolving conflicts between separate unconditionally independentFootnote 46 units, which had no arbiter above them to settle disputes. In the Middle Ages, the arbiter was always in principle and sometimes in factFootnote 47 the Roman pope (and in part also the emperor). Second, when it was taken as the supreme principle of the life of nations the national idea, naturally, degenerated into national pride, the true character of patriotism became distorted and active love for one’s nation was transformed into an idolatry of the nation, conceived as the supremeFootnote 48 good. This, in turn, changed into hatred and contempt for other nations and led to unjust wars as well as to the capture and oppression of other nationalities.Footnote 49

However, hidden behind these negative aspects lies the positive significance of nationality. As the living organs of humanity, nationalities must exist and develop with their peculiarities. Without these organs, the unity of humanity would be empty and dead, and such a dead peace would be worse than war. The true unity of humanity and the longed-for peace must be based not on weakness and the suppression of nations, but on the highest development of their powers and on the free interaction of nationalities, which complement one another.Footnote 50 [435]Despite all the efforts arising out of national selfishness,Footnote 51 which strives for the hostile estrangement of nations, positive interaction between them exists and constantly penetrates deeper and increases in breadth. Previously established international relations have not disappeared, but have intensified internally, and new ones have been added. Thus, although it has lost its external power, the spiritual authority of the Roman church in the West has significantly increased. It has cleansed itself of many ofFootnote 52 its crude medieval abuses, and the damage that the Reformation inflicted on it deservedly has been recompensed by other spiritualFootnote 53 conquests. Alongside this church and in a struggle withFootnote 54 it, there arose the powerful brotherhood of freemasons but with the same broad embrace. Everything in it is mysterious except its international and universal character. Relations of another kind were established on an unprecedented scale in the economic sphere: The world market appeared. There is not one country todayFootnote 55 that is economically self-sufficient. Not one country today produces everything it needs without getting something from others and not giving them something in return. In this way, in this fundamental respect, the idea of an independent state as a “perfect body,” i.e., as an unconditionally independent social organism,Footnote 56 turns out to be the purest fabrication. Furthermore, constant cooperation between all educated countries in scientific and technical work, the fruits of which are now becoming public property; inventions that eliminate distances; the daily press, which brings continuous news from everywhere; finally the striking increase in the international “exchange of goods” by new means of communication—all this makes civilized humanity into a single whole, which actually, even though involuntarily, lives one common life.

This, the civilized portion of humanity, is becoming more and more all of humanity. From the start of the modern era, Europeans have extended the sphere of their activity in all directions. Having seized America in the west, India in the southeast and Siberia in the northeast, the greater part of the globe with its population has already come under European control. We can now say that this power embraces the entire globe. The Islamic world is surrounded and permeated throughout with strands of European culture. Only in the tropical deserts of the Sudan can it still defend its savage independence (the Kingdom of the Dervishes)—and then without any hopeFootnote 57 of success. [436]The entire coastal circumference of Africa has already been divided among the European powers, and the center of the black continent has now become the arena for their rivalry. Beyond the frontiers of European influence still remains Mongolian Asia—China and Japan. However, before our very eyes this last partition in humanity is being removed. With amazing haste and success, the Japanese have in a quarter century assimilated the entire material side of European civilizationFootnote 58 as well as its positive-scientific side and then, above all, tried in a convincing manner to prove the necessity of such assimilation to their Mongolian brothers. The Chinese, whose self-confidence was already shaken by the English but were still slow in understanding these foreigners, understood at once their fellow tribesmen. Now, the notorious Chinese wall is no longer a symbol of enduring isolation, but only a monument to the irretrievable past.Footnote 59

What relation does this curious process of the universal “gathering of lands”Footnote 60 by means of a single material culture have to war? On the one hand, war plays an active role in it. It is well known howFootnote 61 the Revolutionary and Napoleonic Wars provided a powerful contribution to the advance and dissemination of general European ideas, which brought about the scientific, technical and economic progress of the nineteenth Century and which materially united humanity. In the same way, the last act of this unification (its dissemination to the final stronghold of isolated barbarism, China) began in our eyes not by peaceful preaching but by war. On the other hand, the universality of material culture, which is realized in part by war, itself becomes a powerful means and foundation of peace. At the present time, the enormous majority of the globe’s population forms in practice a single connected body, whose parts are in at least physical, if not moral, solidarity. This solidarity is manifested in the sphere from which no one can escape, viz. the economic sphere. An industrial crisis in New York has an immediate and strong impact in Moscow and Calcutta. A common sensorium (sensorium commune)Footnote 62 has been formed in the body of humanity. A consequence of this is that every particular stimulus palpably produces a universal effect. Every serious and protracted war is inevitably accompanied by the most severe economic shocks, which, given the present connection between the different parts [437]of the globe, will be felt as worldwide shocks. Such a state of affairs, which arose during the course of the nineteenth century,Footnote 63 but which became clear to all only at the end of it, is a sufficient reason to fear war. This fear has now seized all civilized nations but was quite unknown in earlier times. However, already in the first half of the century, wars became shorter and less common. Between Waterloo and Sevastopol, Europe saw a 40-year period of peace—an instance unprecedented in its earlier history. Later, special causes rooted in history provoked several comparatively short European wars in 1859, 1864, 1866 and in 1870.Footnote 64 The Russo-Turkish War of 1877–1878 did not succeed in becoming a European war.Footnote 65 However, the most important of these wars,Footnote 66 the Franco-Prussian War, is a typical example. Although it left a bitter sense of national insult and a thirst for vengeance in the leading European nation, because of the fear of war alone these feelings 28 years later are still not strong enough to pass into action! Can you even imagine such abstention in the XVIII or the XVII century, let alone even earlier? What do all the monstrous armaments of the European states pointFootnote 67 to if not the terrible and quite overpowering fear of war and, consequently, the immanent end of wars?Footnote 68, Footnote 69

It would be irrational, however, to think and act as though this immanent end had already arrived. The common economic sensorium now unites all parts of the world’s population by a connection that to them is palpable. However, this connection is by no means equally firm everywhere and not all of these parts are uniformly sensitive. There are still nations that in the event of a world war would risk little, and there are also some ready to risk even a great deal. The introduction of the Mongolian race into the orbit of European material culture has in fact mutual significance. This race, whoseFootnote 70 chief representative, the Chinese nation, calculated to be at least 200 million souls,Footnote 71 is noted for its racial pride and for its great contempt for life, not only that of foreigners, but also of its own. It is more than probable that in the decisive struggle [438]the entire yellow race’sFootnote 72 assimilation of western cultural technique will serve only as a means to prove the superiority of their spiritual principles over that of the Europeans. This coming armed struggle between Europe and Mongolian Asia will certainly be the last and therefore all the more horrible world war. It is not a matter of indifference to the fate of humanity which side will turn out to be victorious.

V

The general history of human wars, whose principal moments we have recalled, presents a wonderful unity and harmony. Through the rosy haze that makes up our recollections of historical childhood, there rises, above all, the clear, though partially fantastic, image of the Trojan War. It was the first great collision between the West and the East, between Europe and Asia. Herodotus lookedFootnote 73 on the Trojan War in this way and began his history with it. Certainly, it was not for nothing that the first inspired monument of purely human poetry (the Iliad) is associated with it. Actually, this war is the beginning of the earthly, worldly history of humanity, which throughout its entire course revolves around the fateful struggle between the East and the West in an ever-widening arena. This arena has now reached its ultimate expanse—the entire surface of our earthly globe. In place of the desolate Skamander,Footnote 74 there is the Pacific Ocean; in place of the smoking PergamonFootnote 75—the ominousFootnote 76 colossus of China. The struggle is just the same as before between the hostile principles of the East and the West. There was a moment of crisis in this process, a break, when, after the external unification of the then historical East with the West in the Roman Empire—under the power of the descendants of Aeneas of TroyFootnote 77—the light of Christianity internally abolished the ancient hostility.

And spilling out openly

Carried out with signs and powers

The light that flowed from the East

The West and East reconciled.Footnote 78

However, the old material and culturalFootnote 79 unification turned out to be unstable, and the spiritual still awaits its final realization. True, instead of the politicalFootnote 80 unity of the Roman Empire , [439]humanity has now developed another unity—an economic one,Footnote 81 which, like the first, places great external obstacles in the path of armed struggle. However, these obstacles, thanks to which we have been saved lately from a European war, are not in a position to prevent the last and the greatest conflict between these two worlds—the European and the Asiatic. They are not now represented by their peoples, as were the Achaeans and the Trojans, or even the Greeks and the Persians. They appear, instead, in their actual entire import, as the two great hostile halves into which all of humanity is divided. The victory of this or that side will actually bring peace to the whole world. ThereFootnote 82 will no longer be struggles between states. However, will this political peace, this establishment of international unity in the form of a universal state (whether monarchical or other)Footnote 83 be a genuine and perpetual peace? Will it end the struggle—even sometimes an armed one—between other non-political elements of humanity? Will it not repeat, now on a grand scale, what took place before our eyes within narrower confines? Germany once consisted of many states at war with each other. The national body suffered from the absence of a real unity, and the creation of such a unity became the cherished dream of the patriots. As a result of several wars, this idea was realized, but it then turned out to be insufficient. The Germans certainly will never relinquish political unity, but they clearly see that unification was just one necessary step forward and not by any means the achievement of the ultimate goal. The political struggle between small states has been replaced throughout the entire empire by a more profound struggle—a religious and economic one. The ultramontanesFootnote 84 and the social democrats are turning out to be more formidable than the Austrians and the French. When all of humanity is politically united—whether it be in the form of a worldwide monarchy or a worldwide international unionFootnote 85—will this stop the struggle of freemasons with clericalism? Will it restrain the hostility of socialism towards the well-to-do classes and of anarchism towards any form of social and state organization? Is it not clear that the struggle between religious beliefs and material interests outlives the struggle between nations and states and that the final establishment of external, political unity decisively reveals its internal inadequacy? It also reveals the moral truth that external peace is still not in itself the true good and that [440]it becomes good only in connection with the internal regeneration of humanity.Footnote 86 And it is only when the inadequacy of this external unity will be known by experience, and not by theory, that the time will have finally come for the spiritualization of the united body of the universe and for realizing the Kingdom of Truth and of Eternal Peace in it.

VI

As we have seen, war has served as the chief historical means for effecting the external politicalFootnote 87 unification of the human race. Wars between clans and gentesFootnote 88 led to the formation of the state, which abolished war within the boundaries of its power. External wars between individual states led, then, to the creation of more extensive and complex cultural and political bodies that tried to establish peace and a sense of equilibrium within their borders. There was once a time when the mass of humanity, scattered and separated, was permeatedFootnote 89 throughout by war, which never stopped between the numerous small groups. War was omnipresent. However, being gradually pushed further and further out, it now threatens to be a virtually inevitableFootnote 90 danger only at the boundary between the two chief races into which historical humanity is divided. The process of unification is approaching its end, but this end has not yet come. TheFootnote 91 peaceful inclusion of the yellow race into the sphere of general human culture is highly improbable, and from the historical point of view, there is no reason to think war will be immediately and completely abolished. However, are we obliged by our human moral awareness to take this point of view?

The issue takes this form: “Whatever the historical significance of war, it is above all the murder of certain people by others. However, our conscience condemns murder, and, consequently, we should honestly refuse to participate in war and urge others to do the same. The dissemination of this view by word and deed is the true and the only sure means of abolishing war. For clearly if everyone would refuse to perform military service, war would become impossible.” For this argument to be convincing we must first agreeFootnote 92 that war and even military service is nothing other than murder. However, it is impossible to agree with this claim. In performing military service, war is only a possibility. During the 40-year period [441]between the wars of Napoleon I and those of Napoleon III, several million men in Europe performed military service, but only an insignificant number experienced actual war. However, even in those cases where it ensues, war still cannot be reduced to murder, i.e., to a crime that presupposes an evil intent directed towards a definite object, towards this particular person whom I kill. In war, the individual soldier, generally speaking, just does not happen to have such an intention, particularlyFootnote 93 given today’s common-enough means of fighting with long-range cannons and guns against an enemy located at a long distance out of sight. Only in cases of actual hand-to-hand combat doesFootnote 94 the question of conscience arise for the individual, who must decide for himself according to his conscience. In general, war as a conflict between collective organisms (states) and their collective organs (armies) is not a matter of single individuals who play a passive role in it. On their part, a possible murder is only accidental.

Would it not be better, however, to prevent the very possibility of an accidental murder by refusing to perform military service? Undoubtedly, this would be the case if it were a matter of free choice. A person who has attained a certain level of moral awareness or has a sense of pity that has been developed separately certainly does not choose on his own to perform his military service at the frontline. Instead, this person prefers peaceful occupations. However, as long as compulsory service is required by the state, we must recognize that for the individual to refuse to perform it is a greater evil than to comply with the current institution, and this does not thereby mean an approval of universal military service, the inconvenience of which is obvious and the efficiency dubious. Since the person who refuses to serve knows that a certain number of recruits will be supplied in any case and that another will be drafted in his place, he deliberately subjects his neighbor to all the burdens of military duty, burdens from which the neighbor would otherwise be free. In addition, the general meaning of such a refusal satisfies the demands neither of logic nor of morality. For it amounts to the fact that in order to avoid the remote possibility in the future of accidentally killing an enemy in a war, which would not depend on me, I myself now declare war against my state and force its representatives to take a whole set of violent actions [442]against me at the present time. I make this declaration in order to save myself from possibly carrying out accidental violence in an unknownFootnote 95 future.

Our law states the purpose of military service by the formula “defense of the throne and fatherland,”Footnote 96 i.e., of the political unit to which the given person belongs. Just as it has happened many times in the past, there is a possibility that the state will in the future abuse its armed forces andFootnote 97 use them in unjust and aggressive wars, instead of in self-defense.Footnote 98 However, this cannot serve as a sufficient reason for my own actions in the present. Such actions must be determined by my own moral duties, and not by those of others. Thus, the question ultimately comes down to this: Do I have a moral obligation to participate in the defense of my fatherland?

Theories thatFootnote 99 unequivocally reject war and consider it everyone’s duty to refuse the state’s demand for military service, in general, deny that the individual has any obligations to the state. From their point of view, the state is no more than a gang of robbers who hypnotizeFootnote 100 the crowd in order to keep it under state control and to use the crowd for its own ends. However, to think seriously that this exhausts or in any way expresses the true essence of the matter would be quite naïve. Such a view particularly lacks a foundation when it refers to Christianity.

Christianity has revealed to us our unconditional moral worth, the absolute significance of the inner human essence, of the human soul . This unconditional moral worth imposes on us an unconditional obligation to realize the truth throughout our lives, not just in our personal but also in our collective lives. We, thereby, indubitably know that this task is impossible for each separate, or isolated, individual and that in order for it to be accomplished a particular individual’s life must be completed by the historical social life of humanity. One means to achieve this completion, one of the forms of social life, indeed the chief and predominant form at the present historical moment, is the fatherland, organized in the definite form of the state. Certainly, this form is not the highest and final expression of human solidarity, and the fatherland must not replace God and His universal Kingdom. However, [443] from the fact that the state is not everything it does not at all follow that it is unnecessary and that it is acceptable to seek its destruction.

Let us suppose that the country in which I live is overtaken by some general disaster, for example, a famine.Footnote 101 Footnote 102 In such a case, what is the duty of a particular individual as an unconditionally moral being? Both my feelings and my conscience clearly dictate that I must do one of two things: Either feed all who are hungry or die myself from starvation. I cannot possibly feed the starving millions. Yet, if my conscience does not in the slightest blame me for staying alive,Footnote 103 this is solely due to the fact that the state takes on itself my moral obligation to supply bread to the hungry and can fulfill that obligation thanks to both its collective resources and its organization, which is adapted for swift action on a broad scale. In this case, the state turns out to be the institution that can successfully carry out the morally obligatory work that a single individual is physically incapable of doing. However, if the state fulfills my direct moral obligations in my stead, then how can it be said that I owe it nothing and that it has no rights over me? If without it I, in good conscience, would have had to give up my own life, then how can I refuse to give it my small share of the means that it needs to complete my own work?

What, one might ask, if the taxes and duties collected by the state go not to things whose usefulness is obvious, but to those which seem to me useless and even harmful? In such a case, my obligation is to expose these abuses, but not to reject, by either word or deed, the very principle of state taxation, the recognized purpose of which is the welfare of the general public.Footnote 104

However, the military organization of the state, in essence, has such a foundation. If some savages, such as the recent Caucasian mountaineers or the present KurdsFootnote 105 and the Black Flags,Footnote 106 attack a traveler with the clear intention of murdering him and killing his family, he undoubtedly has an obligation to fight them. He fights them not out of hatred or malice, nor even in order to save his life at the cost of his neighbor’s life, but in order to protect those who are weaker and are under his protection. To help those near to oneself in such circumstances is [444]an unconditional moral obligation, and it is impossible to limit this obligation to one’s own family. However, an individual alone cannot successfully defend all who are weak and innocent from criminal violence. It is impossible even for groups of people alone. Such a defense along the lines of a collective organization is the purpose of a state’s military forces. To support the state’s philanthropic work in one way or another is everyone’s moral obligation, an obligation that no abuses whatever can eliminate. Just as the conclusion that rye is harmful does not follow from the fact that ergot is poisonous, so the burdens and dangers of militarism do not speak against the necessity of having armed forces.Footnote 107

The military and, in general, any compulsory organization is not an evil, but a consequence and an indication of evil. There was no mention of such an organization when, out of malice, the innocent shepherd Abel was killed by his brother. Justly fearing that the same thing would later happen to Seth and other peaceful men as well, the good guardian angels of humanity mixed clay with copper and iron to create the soldier and the policeman. Moreover, until Cain’s feelings disappear from human hearts, the soldier and the policeman will be a good, not an evil. Hostility towards the state and its representatives is, nevertheless, still hostility, and such hostility alone towards the state is enough to see the need for the state. It is strange to be hostile towards the state for the reason that by external means it merelyFootnote 108 limits but does not internally abolish everywhere the malice that we cannot eliminate from within our own selves!

VII

Between the historical necessity of war and its abstract rejection by a particular individual lies the duty of that individual to the organized whole (the state), which down to the end of history conditions not only the existence but also the progress of humanity. However, the undeniable fact that the state possesses the means not only to preserve human social life as it presently is, butFootnote 109 also to move it forward, imposes on the individual other duties to the state in addition to the simpleFootnote 110 fulfillment of its legal demands. If the state were the perfect embodiment [445]of the normal socialFootnote 111 order, fulfilling these demands would be enough. In fact, however, the state, being the condition and the instrument of human improvement, is itself gradually progressing in various respects. For this reason the single individual is obliged, within the bounds of one’s abilities and faculties, to participate actively in the general politicalFootnote 112 process. There is within the individual an unconditional moral awareness of the perfect ideal of moral truth and peace, an awareness of the Kingdom of God. He obtains this awareness not from the state, but from above and from within. This ideal, however, can be genuinely realized in the collective life of humanity only by means of a preparatory Footnote 113 state organization. It follows from this that the individual who actuallyFootnote 114 takes the moral point of view has a direct and positive obligation to assist the state, through persuading and preaching, to fulfill its preliminary task in the best possible manner. The state itself, of course, becomes superfluous after this fulfillment, but not before.Footnote 115 The individual can and should have such an influence on society with regard to war as well as with regard to all other aspects of life within the state.

The evil of war lies in the extremeFootnote 116 hostility and hatred between the parts of a shatteredFootnote 117 humanity. In personal relations, no one justifiably has bad feelings, and it is useless to reveal such feelings. However, in the case of international hatred the bad feeling is usually combined with false opinions and incorrect reasoning. In fact, these often evoke the bad feeling. To struggle against this lie is the first duty of anyone who really wants to bring humanity closer to a morally good peace.Footnote 118

As for the futureFootnote 119 decisive struggle between Europe and Asia, despite the high probability of its occurrence, we do not consider it an unconditional and inescapable necessity. The matter is still in our hands. Although it is highly unlikely to occur, the first condition for the possible peaceful inclusion of the Mongolian race into the circle of Christian civilizationFootnote 120 lies in the Christian nations becoming more Christian. They should be guided to a greater degree in all aspects of their collective life by moral principles than by shameful self-interest and evil economic, national and religious hostility.

Recently at the world congress of religion in Chicago,Footnote 121 certain Asians—Buddhists and Brahmins—addressed the Europeans [446]with words that expressed current opinion in the East: “You send us missionaries to preach your religion. We do not deny the merits of your religion, but having gotten to know you for the last two centuries we see that your entire life runs counter to the demands of your faith and that you are moved not by the spirit of moral truth and love, bequeathed to you by your God, but by the spirit of greed and violence common to all bad people. Consequently, it is either of two things: Either your religion, despite its inner superiority cannot be practically realized and so it is not useful even for you who profess it; or you are so bad that you do not want to do what you can and should do. In either case, you present no advantage over us and should leave us in peace.”Footnote 122 Only deeds, not words, can serve as a convincing reply to this objection. Against an internally united and truly Christian Europe, Asia would have no justification for fighting nor meet the conditions for victory.Footnote 123 Footnote 124

War was the direct means for the external unification of humanity and the indirect means for its internal unification. Reason forbids abandoning this instrument as long as it is needed, but conscience obliges us to try to make it unnecessary and to try to make the natural organization of humanity, currently divided into hostile parts, into an actual moral, or spiritual, organization. The general description of this entire moral organization, which is contained in human nature, rests internally on the unconditional Moral Good and through world history is fully realized. The moral conditions justify the moral good in the world. This description of the aggregate moral conditions must be the culmination of moral philosophy .Footnote 125