Skip to main content

Affordances, the Social Environment, and the Notion of Field: State of the Debate and Methodological Insights

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Situated Cognition Research

Part of the book series: Studies in Brain and Mind ((SIBM,volume 23))

  • 257 Accesses

Abstract

In his writings, Gibson firmly claimed that cultural or social factors could never distort perception. Cultural artefacts, social norms, language and signs were instead described as influencing perception and behavior only indirectly. At the same time, in his last monumental monograph, Gibson introduced the concept of affordance as applicable to the “whole realm of social significance”. Unfortunately, Gibson did not elaborate further on the relationship between the notion of affordance and the socio-cultural organization of niches like ours. This issue divided Gibson’s followers into two sides. Some of them followed Gibson, claiming that socio-cultural factors can drive behavior but never permeate perceptual experience to its bottom layers. A second group assumes instead that the presence of a structured socio-cultural context permeates the meaning of affordances already at the perceptual level. The aim of this chapter is twofold. The first part of the chapter aims to reconstruct Gibson’s view on the role of culture and sociality and then highlight the reasoning that animates both groups of theorists. In particular, a large part of the discussion is based on motivating the problematics that led the second group of theorists to disagree with Gibson and his idea that the individual’s social background never permeates sensory perception. The second aim is to throw the seeds to develop a methodological tool available to these theorists in order to characterize the experience of affordances as shaped by the social and cultural context in which they are embedded; the notion of field. This notion has a long history in psychology but its methodological consequences are often overlooked. Notably, one of the risks of the concept of field is, as scholars of the Gestalt school like Parlett and Lee claimed, that the notion could be framed so broadly to include “anything and everything”, making it theoretically and scientifically trivial and hence unable to provide a rigorous characterization of what is encountered in individual experiences. To avoid the trivialization of this concept, I conclude by developing a recent proposal that suggests endorsing the notion of field specifically elaborated by the phenomenologist Aron Gurwitsch.

Do you not believe that one can first speak of symbols only after the differentiation between the sacred and the profane has occurred, or is starting to occur? Before this differentiation, the sacred is not symbolized, but rather manifests itself in that, what from the perspective of our standpoint is a symbol – from ours and not from that of the participants […]. It is “self-evident” to us that they are facts and events, and so we interpret them as symbols.

September 10, 1952. Aron Gurwitsch , Letter to Alfred Schutz,

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Following Costal and Still (1989, p. 482), Gibson’s differentiation between the perception of affordances and the perception of cultural artefacts was primarily motivated by ethical and not just ontological concerns, mostly developed during the World War II. Gibson was worried about the ethical outcomes of cultural relativism and the cynicism of the social scientists of his time towards the rise of anti-Semitism. He refused to accept the idea that Germans related to the Jews perceptually or in an immediate fashion, claiming instead that they were purely guided by social stereotypes and non-perceptual habits.

  2. 2.

    Importantly, this chapter deals with Gibson’s followers that endorsed the central ideas at the heart of the ecological approach, i.e., the thesis of direct perception, the coupling between perception and action, the complementarity between organism and environment, etc. At the same time, it should also be recognized that the popularity of the concept of affordance has surpassed that of the ecological research program and has often been appropriated by conventional cognitive science. On many occasions, the term has been extrapolated from the role it plays in ecological psychology and has been either read in a representationalist key or, even if theorized as a world-involving phenomenon, that could nonetheless be grasped by neurocentric and representationalist theories of cognition (see Bickhard & Richie, 1983; Orlandi, 2016; Scarantino, 2003; Dennett, 2017 just to name a few). The theoretical issues concerning the relationship between the socio-cultural environment and individual affordances would certainly be approached differently from the perspective of representationalist theories, in which, as one reviewer kindly noticed, the notion of mental representation would play a key role in determining the normative character of a situated action. A position that may summarise the representationalist position on this issue was articulated by Chow (1989) in his debate with Heft, in which he argued that theorizing affordances in representational terms is necessary to make sense of how the meaning of the same object may be differently perceived when situated in different social contexts (for a response see Heft, 1989). Including the limitations and strategies available for non-ecological approaches that decided to rely on the term affordance is unfortunately beyond the scope of this chapter. I would like to thank the reviewer for bringing out this important point to light.

  3. 3.

    It is worth noticing that in this book Reed substituted the word “perception” with “experience”.

  4. 4.

    The notion of form of life is in this context borrowed from the late-Wittgenstein and is used by Kiverstein and, in general by defenders of the relational approach to affordances known as the Skilled Intentionality Framework to grasp the stable and regular way of doing things together of a group of animals or individuals (see also Rietveld & Kiverstein, 2014)

  5. 5.

    See Moran (2017) for an excursus on the phenomenological tradition on this issue.

  6. 6.

    It is also interesting to notice that Lewin’s Field theory, as much as the work of Koffka, have directly inspired Roger Barker’s Behavior Setting theory; an approach to study social behavior in an ecological fashion that in recent years has received a large attention in 4E and ecological theories (see Heft, 2001; McGann, 2014)

  7. 7.

    It is now possible to compare it with Gibson’s asocial conception of affordance perception. In the passage mentioned in Sect. 16.2 (1972, p. 88), Gibson thought of affordances as exclusively determined by the stimulus “and nothing else”. Gurwitsch, because of the influence of Piaget and Gestalt psychology (in particular Koffka and Köhler), assumed an opposite stance and characterized perception as a developmental and historical process. The Lithuanian phenomenologist follows Gestalt psychologists in claiming that perception cannot be understood independently of the equally relevant contribution of the perceiver’s developmental history and environment. Gurwitsch defended the idea that the contributions of internal (organismic) and external (environmental) factors are both necessary and dependent conditions to understand how the objects’ functional connotations can be acquired, modified, and maintained. The dependency on internal and external conditions has been sometimes formalized through the formula P = f (xe, xi) (2010, p. 94). Here, a percept P is modified even if just one of the two constants goes through any change. These modifications might include the subject’s individual developmental history (internal conditions; xe) and the presence of new environmental stimuli (external conditions; xi). Very reasonably, by not off-loading to the environment the role of fully determining the stimulus meaning, Gurwitsch managed to open a window towards the developmental and historical factors necessary to consider the socio-cultural dimension at the roots of affordance perception. This stance, however, does not need to be interpreted as the idea that reality is perceived through abstract concepts, rules or memories (that actually consisted in the view of Benussi, a Gestalt psychologist from the School of Graz that Gurwitsch heavily criticized and labeled for the dualistic commitments of his approach) but rather seen as a stronger form of relationalism. Gurwitsch followed the main idea promoted by Gestalt psychology that, as Piaget puts it, is s to explain intelligence by perception” (Ivi., p. 48). The field of consciousness, as much as the same existence of the orders of existence constituted by the activities of the members of a society needs thus to be seen as going through continuous re-organizations and changes as the same notion of field implies.

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Artese, G. F. (2022). Gurwitsch’s field of consciousness and radical embodied cognitive science: A case of mutual enlightenment. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 53(2), 177–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar, M. (2004). Visual objects in context. Nature Reviews. Neuroscience, 5, 617–629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H., & Richie, D. M. (1983). On the nature of representation: A case study of James J. Gibson’s theory of perception. Praege.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borghi, A. (2018). Affordances, context and sociality. Synthese, 199(5–6), 12485–12515.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borghi, A. M., Flumini, A., Natraj, N., & Wheaton, L. A. (2012). One hand, two objects: Emergence of affordance in contexts. Brain and Cognition, 80(1), 64–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyce, S. J., Pollatsek, A., & Rayner, K. (1989). Effect of background information on object identification. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and Performance, 15, 556–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruineberg, J., & Rietveld, E. (2014). Self-organization, free energy minimization, and optimal grip on a field of affordances. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8, 599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chow, S. I. (1989). An intentional analysis of “affordance” revisited. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 19, 357–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cisek, P., & Kalaska, J. F. (2010). Neural mechanisms for interacting with a world full of action choices. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 33, 269–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costall, A. (1995). Socializing affordances. Theory & Psychology, 5(4), 467–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costall, A., & Still, A. (1989). Gibson’s theory of direct perception and the problem of cultural relativism. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 19, 433–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2017). From bacteria to Bach and back: The evolution of minds. WW Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dings, R. (2018). Understanding phenomenological differences in how affordances solicit action. An exploration. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 17, 681–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donald, M. (2000). The central role of culture in cognitive evolution on the myth of the “isolated mind”. In L. P. Nucci & G. B. Saxe (Eds.), Culture, thought, and development (pp. 19–38). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (1999). The primacy of phenomenology over logical analysis. Philosophical Topics, 27(2), 3–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2005). Overcoming the myth of the mental: How philosophers can profit from the phenomenology of everyday expertise. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 79(2), 47–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2007). Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing it would require making it more Heideggerian. Philosophical Psychology, 20(2), 247–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Kelly, S. D. (2007). Heterophenomenology: Heavy-handed sleight-of hand. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(1–2), 45–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, N., Salo, V., Debnath, R., Morales, S., & Smith, E. (2020). The mirror neuron system and social cognition. In J. Lockman & C. Tamis-LeMonda (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of infant development: Brain, behavior, and cultural context (pp. 495–519). Cambridge University Pres.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fujiwara, T., Cruz, T. L., Bohnslav, J. P., & Chiappe, M. E. (2017). A faithful internal representation of walking movements in the drosophila visual system. Nature Neuroscience, 20, 72–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1951). Theories of perception. In W. Dennis (Ed.), Current trends in psychological theory (pp. 85–110). University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as perceptual systems. Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1972/2002). A theory of direct visual perception. In A. Noë, & E. Thompson (Eds.), Vision and mind: Selected readings in the philosophy of perception (pp. 77–89). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J.J. (1979/2015). The ecological approach to visual perception. Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J., & Crooks, L. E. (1938). A theoretical field-analysis of automobile-driving. The American Journal of Psychology, 51(3), 453–471.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, J. M. (2007). The affordances for social psychology of the ecological approach to social knowing. Theory & Psychology, 17(2), 265–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (1966). Studies in phenomenology and psychology. Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (1974). Phenomenology and theory of science. Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (1979). Human encounters in the social world. Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (2010). The collected works of Aron Gurwitsch (1901-1973) Vol. III the field of consciousness: Theme, thematic field, and margin. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heft, H. (1989). Perceiving affordances in context: A reply to Chow. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 20(3), 277–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heft, H. (2001). Ecological psychology in context: James Gibson, Roger Barker, and the legacy of William James’s radical empiricism. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heft, H. (2017). Perceptual information of “an entirely different order”: The “cultural environment” in the senses considered as perceptual systems. Ecological Psychology, 29(2), 122–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heras-Escribano, M. (2019). The philosophy of affordances. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Iacoboni, M., Molnar-Szakacs, I., Gallese, V., Buccino, G., Mazziotta, J. C., & Rizzolatti, G. (2005). Grasping the intentions of others with one’s own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology, 3(3), e79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ingold, T. (1992). Culture and the perception of the environment. In E. Croll & D. Parkin (Eds.), Bush Base, Forest farm: Culture, environment and development (pp. 38–56). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadar, E., & Effken, J. (1994). Heideggerian meditations on an alternative ontology for ecological psychology: A response to Turvey’s (1992) proposal. Ecological Psychology, 6, 297–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kadar, E., & Shaw, R. E. (2000). Toward an ecological field theory of perceptual control of locomotion. Ecological Psychology, 12, 141–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Käufer, S., & Chemero, A. (2021). Phenomenology: An introduction (2nd ed.). Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J. (2020). In defence of a relational ontology of affordances. Constructivist Foundations., 15(3), 226–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J., & Van Dijk, L. (2021). Language without representation: Gibson’s first- and second-hand perception on a pragmatic continuum. Language Sciences, 85, 101380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klaassen, P., Rietveld, E., & Topal, J. (2010). Inviting complementary perspectives on situated normativity in everyday life. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koffka, K. (1935). Principles of Gestalt psychology. Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1947). Gestalt psychology. Liveright Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, K. (1951). Field theory in social science. Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2007a). What myth? Inquiry, 50(4), 338–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2007b). Response to Dreyfus. Inquiry, 50(4), 366–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGann, M. (2014). Enacting a social ecology: Radically embodied intersubjectivity. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, D. (2017). The phenomenology of the social word: Husserl on Mitsein as Ineienandersein and Füreinandersein. Metodo International Studies in Phenomenology and Philosophy, 5, 99–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noble, W. (1981). Gibsonian theory and the pragmatist perspective. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 11(1), 65–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Callahan, C., Kveraga, K., Shine, J. M., Adams, R. B., & Bar, M. (2017). Predictions penetrate perception: Converging insights from brain, behaviour and disorder. Consciousness and Cognition, 47, 63–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oberman, L. M., Pineda, J. A., & Ramachandran, V. S. (2007). The human mirror neuron system: A link between action observation and social skills. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 2(1), 62–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orgs, G., Dombrowski, J.-H., Heil, M., & Jansen-Osmann, P. (2008). Expertise in dance modulates alphabeta event-related desynchronization during action observation. European Journal of Neuroscience, 27(12), 3380–3384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orlandi, N. (2016). Bayesian perception is ecological perception. Philosophical Topics, 44(2), 327–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parlett, M., & Lee, R. G. (2005). Contemporary gestalt therapy: Field theory. In A. L. Woldt & S. M. Toman (Eds.), Gestalt therapy: History, theory, and practice (pp. 41–63). Sage Publications.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, E. S. (1993). The intention to use a specific affordance: A conceptual framework for psychology. In R. M. Wozniak & K. W. Fischer (Eds.), Development in context: Acting and thinking in specific environments (pp. 61–92). Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, E. S. (1996a). Encountering the world: Toward an ecological psychology. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, E. S. (1996b). The necessity of experience. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E. (2008). Situated normativity: The normative aspect of embodied cognition in unreflective action. Mind, 117(468), 973–1001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26(4), 325–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949/2009). The concept of mind. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A. (2003). Affordances explained. Philosophy of Science, 70(5), 949–961.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schnall, S. (2017). No magic bullet in sight: A reply to firestone and Scholl (2017) and Durgin (2017). Perspectives on Psychological Science, 12(2), 347–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schutz, A. (1945). On multiple realities. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 5, 533–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shuler, M. G., & Bear, M. F. (2006). Neurons in the primary visual cortex respond differently to a flash of light after it has been paired with a reward, unexpectedly showing that cognitive information is coded at this level in the cortex. Science, 311, 1606–1609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staemmler, F.-M. (2005). A Babylonian confusion? On the uses and meanings of the term “field”. British Gestalt journal, 15, 64–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Still, A. W., & Good, J. M. M. (1992). Mutualism in the human science: Towards the implementation of a theory. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 22, 105–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural ecology of young children’s interactions with objects and artifacts. In E. Winograd, R. Fivush, & W. Hirst (Eds.), Ecological approaches to cognition: Essays in honor of Ulric Neisser (pp. 153–170). Hove Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. (1992). Affordances and prospective control: An outline of the ontology. Ecological Psychology, 4, 173–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Dijk, L., & Kiverstein, J. (2020). Direct perception in context: Radical empiricist reflections on the medium. Synthese, 198(9), 8389–8411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Dijk, L., & Rietveld, E. (2017). Foregrounding sociomaterial practice in our understanding of affordances: The skilled intentionality framework. Frontiers in Psychology, 7, 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M. (2015). Organisms, agency, and evolution. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Windsor, W. L. (2004). An ecological approach to semiotics. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 34, 179–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Withagen, R., de Poel, H. J., Araújo, D., & Pepping, G. (2012). Affordances can invite behavior: Reconsidering the relationship between affordances and agency. New Ideas in Psychology, 30, 250–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Withagen, R., Araújo, D., & de Poel, H. J. (2017). Inviting affordances and agency. New Ideas in Psychology, 45, 11–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wokke, M. E., Knot, S. L., Fouad, A., & Ridderinkhof, K. R. (2016). Conflict in the kitchen: Contextual modulation of responsiveness to affordances. Consciousness and Cognition, 40, 141–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yoon, E. Y., Humphreys, G. W., & Riddoch, M. J. (2010). The paired-object affordance effect. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 36(4), 812.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giuseppe Flavio Artese .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Artese, G.F. (2023). Affordances, the Social Environment, and the Notion of Field: State of the Debate and Methodological Insights. In: Casper, MO., Artese, G.F. (eds) Situated Cognition Research. Studies in Brain and Mind, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-39744-8_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics