Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy ((LOET,volume 39))

  • 185 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter argues that nothing truly binds us in the absence of our ability to bind ourselves to ourselves, an ability which Crowell, following Heidegger, calls “commitment” (Bindung) or “resoluteness” (Entschlossenheit). There is something paradoxical about commitment, however. As Joseph Rouse puts it: A “self-determined commitment could have only the semblance of authority,” since, “as Kierkegaard trenchantly noted, the authority that a commitment could secure through self-determination […] is like the authority of a monarch in a country where revolution is legitimate.” This paradox has led philosophers to seek the ground of bindingness in some authoritative entity: natural law, social convention, human rights, ideal consensus, the moral law, God. But, as Heidegger notes in what amounts to a motto for the present chapter: “We orient ourselves toward beings, and yet are never able to say what it is about beings that binds us.” This does not mean that we cannot say what binds us; rather, it means that what binds us does not belong to the order of beings but to being—specifically, what it means to be a self. Being bound by beings presupposes the capacity to bind oneself to oneself. This sounds very much like a version of Rouse’s paradox, and in order to show why it is not, Crowell’s argument is divided into three sections: (1) a review of some ways of being bound, together with some consideration of whether we are really bound in any of these ways; (2) an argument, based on Heidegger’s phenomenology of commitment, that we are indeed bound in these ways, but only if self-binding is possible; and (3) a concluding sketch of Heidegger’s answer to Rouse’s paradox.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Rouse’s own view is more complicated: “What needs to be understood is not how we can commit ourselves to something […], but how something already at stake in our situation can have a hold on or over us” (2002, 247). The complication lies in the fact that “what is at stake” belongs to the order of meaning (being), not beings.

  2. 2.

    The hyphen’s mode of “binding and separating” parallels Heideggers account of the logical “copula” and informs his ontological grounding of reason in care. Interpreting Aristotle, Heidegger argues that the “is” of an assertion (logos apophantikos) binds and separates only because it rests on a more primordial phenomenon of “agreement” which Heidegger calls nous and identifies with understanding something as something. In Heidegger’s own terms—which we shall explore below—this understanding is “comportment,” and an essential element of comportment is commitment, or self-binding. Commitment is thus a necessary condition even for logical “binding” (Heidegger 1995, 304–333).

  3. 3.

    In the film, the prisoners help one another to break their chains. This brings certain “second-person” considerations into play, which will be discussed below.

  4. 4.

    This objection, central to Hegel’s criticism of Kant, is extensively explored in Slavens (2017).

  5. 5.

    This is the crux of the disagreement between Rouse and Haugeland. The latter’s “mistake” is to conceive “practical and discursive normativity in terms of commitments undertaken by subjects that would confer normative authority upon otherwise anormative objects.” For Rouse, this leads Haugeland’s philosophy of science into a “problematic voluntarism,” together with a “problematic scientism” (Rouse 2002, 235, 257). A partial response to Rouse can be found in Crowell (2017).

  6. 6.

    Heidegger’s term for this sort of possibility is Seinkönnen, translated by Macquarrie and Robinson as “potentiality-for-being” (Heidegger 1962, 119). We might also translate it as “ability to be.” Heidegger’s technical term for it is “understanding” (Verstehen), and he explains it as follows: We “sometimes use the expression ‘understanding something,’ ‘being a match for it,’ ‘being competent to do something.’ In understanding, as an existentiale [i.e., a category of Dasein’s being], that which we have such competence over is not a ‘what,’ but being as existing.” This is what a practical identity is: “Dasein is not something present-at-hand which possesses its competence for something by way of an extra; it is primarily being-possible. Dasein is in every case what it can be, and in the way in which it is its possibility” (Heidegger 1962, 183). The point is that acting for the sake of some “possibility for being” is a skill, and as such, norm-sensitive.

  7. 7.

    On “avowal” in this sense, see Moran (2001) and the discussion in Crowell (2013), ch. 4.

  8. 8.

    Why isn’t this simply another “metaphysical” definition, “simply the truth”? This is a complicated question, and it turns on Heidegger’s understanding of philosophy as itself a kind of practical identity whose meaning is at issue. This means that all philosophical assertions must be understood as “formal indications” (not simply “truths”) that serve to put those who consider them in a position to assess the phenomenological evidence for themselves. On formal indication see Crowell (2001, Chap. 7). We cannot develop this issue in detail, but the point is that Heidegger is offering a better description of our selfhood than the one attained through the description, “rational animal,” and his description does not entail valuing one’s rational animality as a practical identity, though it does not rule it out either.

  9. 9.

    Heidegger’s notion of death as a “possibility” (“nicht-mehr-dasein-könnens”) includes the sense of an “ability-to-be” we introduced earlier. Death is not something that “happens” to Dasein; it is a way to be (Blattner 1994).

  10. 10.

    For a fuller treatment of the themes introduced in the present discussion see Crowell (2013, Chaps. 8 and 9).

  11. 11.

    In these passages, Maquarrie and Robinson translate Grund and its variations with “basis.” I have altered this to “ground.”

  12. 12.

    As I mentioned earlier, Rouse ultimately grounds this normativity in what is at stake in the practice in which we are engaged together, and not in the commitment of the participants. Apart from disagreeing with his criticisms of existential commitment, I find Rouse’s general account (and within it, his account of the “normativity of nature”) quite compelling.

  13. 13.

    Authenticity differs from autonomy in the way that “transparency” with regard to my responsibility for normative force differs from “respect” for my power to bring my behavior under the form of law.

  14. 14.

    This brings Heidegger into unexpected proximity to Habermas’s notion of “discourse ethics.” For some discussion see Crowell (2013, Chap. 10).

References

  • Blattner, William. 1994. The Concept of Death in Being and Time. Man and World 27: 49–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, Steven. 2001. Husserl, Heidegger, and the Space of Meaning: Paths Toward Transcendental Phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Competence Over Being as Existing: The Indispensability of Haugeland’s Heidegger. In Giving a Damn: Essays in Dialogue with John Haugeland, ed. Zed Adams and Jacob Browning, 73–102. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, Stephen. 2006. The Second-Person Standpoint. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, John. 1998. Truth and Rule-Following. In Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1962. In Being and Time, ed. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1982. Vom Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit, Gesamtausgabe Bd 31. Frankfurt: Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. In The Metaphysical Foundations of Logic, ed. Michael Heim. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. In Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics, ed. William McNeill and Nicholas Walker. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. On the Essence of Ground. In Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1989. In Ideas Toward a Pure Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy. Book II, ed. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 2012. In Phenomenology of perception, ed. A. Donald. Landes. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, Richard. 2001. Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, Joseph. 2002. How Scientific Practices Matter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1987. On the Social Contract. In The Basic Political Writings, ed. Donald Cress. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slavens, Jesse. 2017. Tracking Kant’s Bête Noire: The Significance of Hegel’s Emptiness Critique for Contemporary Kantian Ethics. PhD dissertation. Rice University.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steven Crowell .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Crowell, S. (2022). Commitment: What Is Self-Binding, and How Is It Possible?. In: Fernández, P.A., García Martínez, A.N., Torralba, J.M. (eds) Ways of Being Bound: Perspectives from post-Kantian Philosophy and Relational Sociology. Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy, vol 39. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-11469-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-11469-4_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-11468-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-11469-4

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics