Skip to main content

Where Are Ethical Properties? Predication, Location, and Category Mistake

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Women in Pragmatism: Past, Present and Future

Part of the book series: Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences ((WHPS,volume 14))

  • 282 Accesses

Abstract

The debate between expressivism and representationalism raises the question of whether ethical claims should be analyzed as predications of ethical properties. Representationalism is the thesis that every meaningful claim represents a time–space located or locatable state of affairs. So, when it is used to account for the meaning of ethical discourse, we are faced with the placement problem (Price, 2011), the problem of placing ethical properties in the physical world. By contrast, classic expressivism (Ayer, 1936/1971) avoids appealing to predication concerning ethical concepts and proposes explaining their meaning in terms of the expression of speakers’ states. This avoids the placement problem but poses the Frege-Geach problem, a difficulty in accounting for the propositional behavior exhibited by ethical claims. This paper maintains that both sides of the debate share a false premise. They both adopt a representationalist notion of proposition, according to which every predication ascribes an instantiable-in-locatable-entities property. I will defend that this notion of proposition does not reflect the linguistic practices of speakers, which exhibit a logico-semantic pluralism that makes it necessary to distinguish between two orders of predication. In particular, I will endorse the view that ethical concepts are higher-order predicables (Frápolli,2019), which operate on non-locatable entities (Frápolli, 2014). From this point of view, I will describe the placement problem as a pseudo-problem resulting from a category mistake and I will claim that the classic expressivist reaction to this problem fails to recognize it as such.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Copp (2001) for an exception.

  2. 2.

    A similar idea is advocated in Frápolli & Villanueva (2015, 2016). There they defend the organic model of propositional individuation. The label organic intuition refers to a criterion for the identification of propositions.

  3. 3.

    I prefer the label “non-physicalistic”, as it emphasizes the locational aspect.

References

  • Ayer, A. J. (1936/1971). Language, truth and logic. Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On, D. (2012). Expression, truth, and reality: Some variations on themes from Wright. In A. Coliva (Ed.), Mind, meaning, and knowledge: Themes from the philosophy of Crispin Wright (pp. 162–192). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On, D., & Sias, J. (2013). Varieties of expressivism. Philosophy Compass, 8(8), 699–713.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bar-On, D. (2019). Neo-expressivism: (self-)knowledge, meaning, and truth. In M. J. Frápolli (Ed.), Expressivisms, knowledge and truth, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 86 (pp. 11–34). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boisvert, D. (2008). Expressive-assertivism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 89, 169–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making it explicit. Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (2000). Articulating reasons. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camp, E. (2018). Metaethical expressivism. In T. McPherson & D. Plunkett (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of metaethics (pp. 87–101). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chrisman, M. (2008). Expressivism, inferentialism, and saving the debate. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77(2), 334–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chrisman, M. (2010). Constructivism, expressivism and ethical knowledge. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 18(3), 331–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chrisman, M. (2011). Ethical expressivism. In C. Miller (Ed.), The Continuum companion to ethics (pp. 29–54). Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chrisman, M. (2018). Two nondescriptivists views of normative and evaluative statements. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 48(3–4), 405–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. (2001). Realist-expressivism: A neglected option for moral realism. Social Philosophy and Policy, 18(2), 1–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frápolli, M. J. (2014). You and me baby ain’t nothing but mammals: Subject naturalism and default positions. Análisis: Revista de investigación filosófica, 1(1), 41–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frápolli, M. J. (2019). Propositions first: Biting Geach’s bullet. In M. J. Frápolli (Ed.), Expressivisms, knowledge and truth, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 86 (pp. 87–110). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frápolli, M. J. (2021). Frege pragmatised: Bringing sense back into logical theory. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frápolli, M. J., & Villanueva, N. (2013). Frege, Sellars, Brandom: Expresivismo e inferencialismo semánticos. In D. Pérez (Ed.), Perspectivas en la filosofía del lenguaje (pp. 583–617). Prensas de la Universidad de Zaragoza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frápolli, M. J. & Villanueva, N. (2015). Expressivism, relativism, and the analytic equivalence test. Frontiers in Psychology, 6. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01788/full

  • Frápolli, M. J. & Villanueva, N. (2016). Pragmatism. Propositional priority and the organic model of propositional individuation. Disputatio, 8(43), 203–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1884/1960). The foundations of arithmetic: a logico-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number. Harper & Brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1891/1997). Function and concept. In M. Beaney (Ed.) The Frege Reader (pp. 130–148), Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1960). Ascriptivism. The Philosophical Review, 69(2), 221–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geach. P. T. (1962/1980). Reference and generality: an examination of some medieval and modern theories. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (2003). Thinking how to live. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (2012). Meaning and normativity. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1903/1993). Principia ethica. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Navarro, L. (2017). Inferencialismo en el discurso ético. Boletín de la Sociedad de Lógica, Metodología y Filosofía de la Ciencia, Special issue (November 2017), 67–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (2011). Naturalism without mirrors. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (2013). Expressivism, pragmatism and representationalism. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ridge, M. (2006). Ecumenical expressivism: Finessing frege. Ethics, 116(2), 302–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ridge, M. (2007). Ecumenical expressivism: The best of both worlds? In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Vol. 2, pp. 51–76). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949/2009). The Concept of Mind. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Roojen, M. (2018). Moral cognitivism vs. non-cognitivism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2018 Edition). Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/moral-cognitivism/

  • Villanueva, N. (2018). Expresivismo y semántica. In D. Pérez (Ed.), Cuestiones de la filosofía del lenguaje (pp. 437–469). Prensas de la Universidad de Zaragoza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, C. J. F. (1992). Towards a unified theory of higher-level predication. The Philosophical Quarterly, 42(169), 449–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work has been funded by the Spanish Ministry of Education, Culture, and Sports (FPU16/04185) and the FiloLab Group of Excellence (University of Granada). I am thankful to Manuel Almagro, Michela Bella, María José Frápolli, María Jiménez, Núria Sara Miras Boronat, Javier Osorio, and the audiences of the Women in Pragmatism International Conference and the V Jornadas Filo-Doc conference for their valuable comments on previous versions of this chapter.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Llanos Navarro .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Navarro, L. (2022). Where Are Ethical Properties? Predication, Location, and Category Mistake. In: Miras Boronat, N.S., Bella, M. (eds) Women in Pragmatism: Past, Present and Future. Women in the History of Philosophy and Sciences, vol 14. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-00921-1_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics