Skip to main content

Feeling and Life in Kant’s Account of the Beautiful and the Sublime

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Concept of Drive in Classical German Philosophy
  • 338 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter explores what Kant means by “life”, the “feeling of life”, the “feeling of the promotion (or inhibition) of life”, and related notions, such as the idea of a “vital power”, through the contrast between Kant’s account of the beautiful and his account of the sublime. We argue that it is significant that Kant characterizes the feeling of the beautiful as a feeling of the promotion of life but the feeling of the sublime in terms of vital powers. We account for this difference by showing that in experiences of beauty, we are aware of ourselves as rational but embodied human beings, as part of nature. In the feeling of the sublime, by contrast, we are aware of ourselves as pure rational beings. This entails that in the beautiful, we experience nature as deeply life-promoting, while in the sublime, we experience the independence of our supersensible vocation from nature.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    One difficulty with working out Kant’s views on this and related points is that, although there is a large amount of relevant textual evidence, most of it comes in the form of student lecture notes. Moreover, these notes indicate that Kant’s views on these matters were continuously evolving. We have tried to mitigate these difficulties when possible by quoting from texts that were either published or written to be published and by citing several supporting sources. For a helpful survey of the shifts in Kant’s views, see Caygill (2000). For a detailed examination of the historical roots of Kant’s concept of life, see Fugate (2018).

  2. 2.

    We thus take something to be alive if it “has a faculty to alter its own state as a consequence of its own representations” (LM-Volckmann 295 [28:448–449]). It remains a matter of debate, however, whether we are licensed to say that organisms really are alive. We bracket this issue, focusing only on life and the feeling of life as it obtains in human beings. For discussion, see McLaughlin (1990), Ginsborg (2001), Breitenbach (2013b, 2014).

  3. 3.

    See also CPR 438 [A393], LM-Volckmann 354 [28:594]; LM-L2 354 [28:594] and LM-K2 396 [28:755] and 405 [28:675]. Cf. MFNS 251–252 [4:544].

  4. 4.

    As we mentioned earlier, Kant sometimes appears to identify life with the faculty of desire. (See Deimling (2018) for a careful defense of these claims.) We suggest, however, that desire is a sufficient condition or “mark” of life.

  5. 5.

    See also the references to the “entire power of mind” (LM-L1 63 [28:247]) and our “entire faculty” (LM-Mrongovius 258–259 [29:890–891]), as well as the reference to life as unity in an interesting Reflexion (R6862) that Adickes dates between 1776 and 1789 (NF 443 [19:183]).

  6. 6.

    We adopt and build on an interpretation of the function of feeling in the Kantian mind elaborated and defended in earlier work by Cohen (2020, 2021).

  7. 7.

    For example, Kant regularly uses “vital power” in discussing temperament but not character. See PA 384 ff. [7:285 ff.], LA-Mrongovius 467 [25:1370], and LA-Busolt 523–524 [25:1531], for example. See Cohen (2017b) for discussion.

  8. 8.

    For example, see Guyer (1997, 2006, 2009), Allison (2001), Zuckert (2007), and Ginsborg (2015).

  9. 9.

    By “cognitive judgments”, we mean the range of judgments ultimately aiming at determinate concept-application: determining judgments but also reflecting judgments that aim at generating a systematic unity of empirical concepts and laws.

  10. 10.

    Though we cannot give a full defense of this reading of aesthetic and cognitive judgments here, the claims to follow do not depend on adopting this reading. For an alternative interpretation that identifies a “common core” between aesthetic and cognitive judgments, see Breitenbach (2013a, 20152020, Forthcoming). The view we adopt has, on the face of it, a harder time accounting for the universality of aesthetic judgments (though see Cohen 2017a, 146–147), whereas a view such as Breitenbach’s must deal with the prima facie counterintuitive implication that all cognizable objects are (or could be) beautiful.

  11. 11.

    Although in this passage, Kant is talking about works of art, rather than natural beauty, the specific kind of cognitive enhancement characterized here seems to be secured just by the nature of the harmonious free play and thus seems generalizable to all beautiful experiences. The same is not true with respect to the kind of cognitive enhancement Kant attributes to the experience of beautiful poetry, which, according to Kant, “expands the mind by setting the imagination free and presenting, within the limits of a given concept and among the unbounded manifold of forms possibly agreeing with it, the one that connects its presentation with a fullness of thought to which no linguistic expression is fully adequate” (CJ 203–204 [5:326]). Though the freedom of imagination’s activity remains central to this cognitive enhancement, the involvement of specific concepts raises the possibility that the sort of cognitive enhancement described here might be unique to the case of poetry.

  12. 12.

    Cf. Zammito (1992, 295), whose analysis of the feeling of life focuses on ourselves in the “world of sense,” and Makkreel (1990, 92), whose account connects the feeling of life with “pure mental spontaneity”. We take our view to articulate a third option.

  13. 13.

    See Matthews (1996) and Clewis (2009) for helpful analyses of the sublime; both, however, focus on the role of the sublime in enabling awareness of our supersensible capacities, whereas we argue that the experience of the sublime also enhances our ability to use these capacities.

  14. 14.

    Though the passage quoted earlier focuses on the mathematical sublime, the same point is made explicitly with reference to both the mathematical and the dynamical sublime in the following passage: “Reason inevitably comes in as a faculty of the independence of the absolute totality, and produces the efforts of the mind, though it is in vain, to make the representation of the senses adequate to that. This effort, and the feeling of the unattainability of the idea by means of the imagination, is itself a presentation of the subjective purposiveness of our mind in the use of the imagination for its supersensible vocation” (CJ 151 [5:268]).

  15. 15.

    It is unable, however, to grasp and comprehend everything it can apprehend (CJ 135 [5:251–252] and 138 [5:255–256]).

  16. 16.

    Though this passage is about the dynamical sublime, Kant also characterizes experiences of the mathematical sublime as producing a “disposition of the mind” useful for our practical pursuits; see CJ 139 [5:256].

  17. 17.

    A complete answer must further reckon with the murky claims about the “supersensible substratum” that unifies theoretical reason and practical reason and enables the transition from nature to freedom. See CJ 227 [5:353] and 216–217 [5:340–341].

References

  • Allison, Henry E. 2001. Kant’s Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breitenbach, Angela. 2013a. Aesthetics in Science: A Kantian Proposal. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 113: 83–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013b. Kant on Biology and the Experience of Life. In Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht: Akten des XI. Kant-Kongresses 2010, ed. Margit Ruffing, Claudio La Rocca, Alfredo Ferrarin and Stefano Bacin, 19–30. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Biological Purposiveness and Analogical Reflection. In Kant’s Theory of Biology, ed. Eric Watkins and Ina Goy, 131–148. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Beauty in Proofs: Kant on Aesthetics in Mathematics. European Journal of Philosophy 23 (4): 955–977.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. One Imagination in Experiences of Beauty and Achievements of Understanding. British Journal of Aesthetics 60: 71–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. Forthcoming. Imaginative Reflection in Aesthetic Judgment and Cognition. In Proceedings of the 13th International Kant Congress, ed. Camilla Serck-Hanssen and Beatrix Himmelmann. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caygill, Howard. 2000. Life and Aesthetic Pleasure. In The Matter of Critique: Readings in Kant’s Philosophy, ed. Andrea Rehberg and Rachel Jones, 79–92. Manchester: Clinamen Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clewis, Robert. 2009. The Kantian Sublime and the Revelation of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Alix. 2017a. Kant on Beauty and Cognition: The Aesthetic Dimension of Cognition. In Thinking about Science and Reflecting on Art: Bringing Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Science Together, ed. Steven French and Otávio Bueno, 140–154. London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017b. The Natural, the Pragmatic and the Moral in Kant’s Anthropology: The Case of Temperaments. Early Science and Medicine 22 (2–3): 253–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. A Kantian Account of Emotions as Feelings. Mind 129 (514): 429–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021. Feeling, Orientation and Agency in Kant: A Response to Merritt and Eran. Kantian Review 26 (3): 379−391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deimling, Wiebke. 2018. Two Different Kinds of Value? In Kant and the Faculty of Feeling, ed. Kelly Sorensen and Diane Williamson, 25–41. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fugate, Courtney. 2018. Life and Kant’s Critique of Aesthetic Judgment. In Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants: Akten des X. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, ed. Valerio Rohden, Ricardo R. Terra, and Guido A. de Almeida, 609–621. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsborg, Hannah. 2001. Kant on Understanding Organisms as Natural Purposes. In Kant and the Sciences, ed. Eric Watkins, 231–258. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. The Normativity of Nature: Essays on Kant’s Critique of Judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, Paul. 1997. Kant and the Claims of Taste. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. The Harmony of the Faculties Revisited. In Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant’s Critical Philosophy, ed. Rebecca Kukla, 162–193. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. The Harmony of the Faculties in Recent Books on the Critique of the Power of Judgment. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 67 (2): 201–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1992. Lectures on Logic. Edited and translated by J. Michael Young. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Lectures on Metaphysics. Edited and translated by Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Edited and translated by Paul Guyer and Allen Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Practical Philosophy. Edited and translated by Mary J. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Critique of the Power of Judgment. Edited by Paul Guyer and translated by Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Theoretical Philosophy after 1781. Edited by Henry Allison and Peter Heath and translated by Gary Hatfield, Michael Friedman, Henry Allison, and Peter Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Notes and Fragments. Edited by Paul Guyer and translated by Curtis Bowman, Paul Guyer, and Frederick Rauscher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Anthropology, History and Education. Edited by Günter Zöller and Robert Louden and translated by Mary Gregor, Paul Guyer, Robert Louden, Holly Wilson, Allen Wood, Günter Zöller, and Arnulf Zweig. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Lectures on Anthropology. Edited by Allen Wood and Robert Louden and translated by Robert Clewis, Robert Louden, G. Felicitas Munzel, and Allen Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makkreel, Rudolf. 1990. Imagination and Interpretation in Kant: The Hermeneutical Import of The Critique of Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, Patricia M. 1996. Kant’s Sublime: A Form of Pure Aesthetic Reflective Judgment. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54 (2): 165–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, Peter. 1990. Kant’s Critique of Teleology in Biological Explanation: Antinomy and Teleology. Lewiston: E. Mellen Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, John. 1992. The Genesis of Kant’s Critique of Judgment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuckert, Rachel. 2007. Kant on Beauty and Biology: An Interpretation of The Critique of Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank the editors, Manja Kisner and Jörg Noller, for their patience and ongoing support, as well as all the participants of the Munich conference for their helpful feedback, with special thanks to John Zammito for his insightful comments. We are also grateful to Angela Breitenbach, Robert Clewis, and Ido Geiger for the time they so generously spent discussing some of the ideas developed in the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yoon H. Choi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Choi, Y.H., Cohen, A. (2022). Feeling and Life in Kant’s Account of the Beautiful and the Sublime. In: Kisner, M., Noller, J. (eds) The Concept of Drive in Classical German Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-84160-7_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics