Skip to main content

From Constitutional Discretion to the Positivist Weight Formula

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Proportionality, Balancing, and Rights

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 136))

Abstract

A correct understanding of balancing discretion shows how proportionality works as an internal limit of discretion and how suitability, necessity and proportionality in the narrow sense constrain the choices to be made by a legislative normative authority. On the other hand, an accurate contraposition between the laws of balancing (the content of proportionality in the narrow sense) and Alexy’s Weight Formula leads to the conclusion that this equation does not express (as it should) the role those laws have in constraining the range of choice presented by “prima facie discretion”. Coming from the problems therein detected, a new formula is presented; a formula that fully matches the substantive and the epistemic laws and that, to satisfy its function of internal justification of a balancing decision, only entails the variables those laws support.

I am deeply thankful to Margarida Duarte for her support with the mathematical features of proportionality. For their critical approach, I am also grateful to Miodrag Jovanović, Bojan Spaić, Wojciech Załuski and Katarzyna Eliasz (Belgrade Seminar), Robert Alexy, Jan Sieckmann, Laura Clerico, Martin Borowski, Matthias Klatt, Carsten Bäcker and Daniel Oliver-Lalana (Erlangen Seminar), and Pedro Moniz Lopes, Jorge Silva Sampaio and Ana Escher from our Lisbon Legal Theory Group.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For instance, to enact a norm in time1 or time2 or to ask for expertise1 or expertise2. For procedural aspects of legislative discretion, Borowski (2010), p. 135; Walker et al. (2015), p. 358.

  2. 2.

    On content related discretion, Hart (2013), p. 656; materially, Sartor (2013), p. 1450.

  3. 3.

    Provided that the legal order at hand entails a principle of proportionality, a contingent state of affairs (as with all norms enacted by normative authorities or produced by customary sources). As a matter of fact, it is not impossible (although absurd) to insert into a constitution a principle of disproportionality. On the contingency of the content of legal orders, Bulygin (2010), p. 285; Mendonca (2000), p. 63. Differently, claiming the universality of proportionality, Sieckmann (2018), p. 4; Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 1.

  4. 4.

    This criterion is particularly operative here since it gives the best view to distinguish balancing discretion from other kinds of constitutional discretion. For other classifications, Alexy (2002), p. 394; Rivers (2007), p. 170.

  5. 5.

    Nino (2003), p. 256; Duarte (2018), p. 136.

  6. 6.

    If for “norm sentence” we understand a closed text strictly expressing the totality of elements that match a certain criterion of norm individuation (NS → N). Obviously, as an utterance, a norm sentence (understood just as a written text) can entail an unlimited quantity of norms (NS → N1 ∧ N2), something quite common in long constitutional articles (for instance, article 26/1 of the Portuguese Constitution has, at least, seven norms).

  7. 7.

    On vagueness, Moreso (2017), p. 49; Escher (2019), p. 163.

  8. 8.

    For instance, the syntactical uncertainty provided by the disjunctive or conjunctive use of the word “and”: in a norm sentence expressing “O q ∨ r “and” s”, we can read the following possible norms “O q ∧ s”, “O r ∧ s”, or “O q ∨ r ∨ s”. The discretion present is, however, and regardless of its own proper scheme, totally due to a linguistic uncertainty.

  9. 9.

    A kind of discretion that, consequently, presupposes that the linguistic moment of interpreting the norm sentence is already behind. Navarro and Rodríguez (2014), p. 180; Sardo (2018), p. 58.

  10. 10.

    By bilateral permission it is meant the permission of an action (φ) and its contradictory (~φ); a faculty. Hansson (2013), p. 199; Ratti (2018), p. 89.

  11. 11.

    Wróblewski (1992), p. 289; Moreso and Vilajosana (2004), p. 106. It is relevant to note, however, that any kind of uncertainty coming from the norm of conflicts (its sentence) is necessarily due to linguistic indeterminacy, which means, evidently, that in this case we are again within the first category of constitutional discretion.

  12. 12.

    Moreso (2002), p. 21; Chiassoni (2019), p. 189. One note: it is only based on statistical preponderance that principles are being used as examples of constitutional norms in a conflict conferring balancing discretion (Pino [2014], p. 612). Since rules are as defeasible as principles (and in the same way), nothing prevents similar constitutional conflicts with rules.

  13. 13.

    For instance, Hart (2013), p. 661; Klatt (2007), p. 507.

  14. 14.

    Internal limits of discretion can provide, then, a total “reduction of discretion to zero” or, differently, a maintenance of alternatives (same or less than initially): here, without legal parameters, judicial review is constitutionally forbidden. Framing the problem as one of competence, Alexy (2016), p. 69; Bernal Pulido (2009), p. 116.

  15. 15.

    For the underlying scheme of analogy, Golding (2018), p. 133; Duarte (2015), p. 144.

  16. 16.

    On the topic, for instance, Clérico (2009), pp. 39, 101; Bernal Pulido (2007), p. 620.

  17. 17.

    For example, Alexy (2014), p. 519; Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 80.

  18. 18.

    Borowski (2013), p. 1418; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 75.

  19. 19.

    Alexy (2002), p. 415; Rivers (2007), p. 177.

  20. 20.

    Alexy (2003), p. 447; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 76.

  21. 21.

    On the discussion between reliability and truth, Olsson (2007), p. 343; Bird (1998), p. 147.

  22. 22.

    Obviously, truth entails all its “parallels”, such as truthlikeness (verisimilitude), probability (objective chance), or inference to the best explanation (best competing explanation). See, respectively, Niiniluoto (2004), p. 538; Bird (1998), p. 123; Lipton (1991), p. 56.

  23. 23.

    On justified true belief, Shope (2004), p. 285; Bird (1998), p. 156.

  24. 24.

    The (negative powers) double triadic scale will be used in the next example. Later on, a more precise explanation for this scale will be given. On the other hand, and just for the sake of simplicity, it is assumed that each premise contributes with the same weight to the overall degree of certainty given to the premises related to a specific P. However, and obviously, this is just a simplification (it is possible but not necessary).

  25. 25.

    On the present topic, Klatt writes with Meister (2012) and Schmidt (2012). However, and for the sake of simplicity, only his name is mentioned in text (differently from footnotes, of course).

  26. 26.

    Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 110; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 75.

  27. 27.

    Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 113; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 77.

  28. 28.

    That reads as follows: “the more reliable a more intensive classification of intensity of interference is, the more reliable must be a less intensive classification of intensity of interference”. Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 118; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 81.

  29. 29.

    Using now the single triadic scale as Klatt does. Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 120; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 82.

  30. 30.

    Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 114; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 77.

  31. 31.

    Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 113; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 75.

  32. 32.

    For the scale, Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 112; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 76. Not being a review scale means that it is not dependent on (or strictly usable by) a reviewer body.

  33. 33.

    In other words, certainty means that classification balancing is dispensable.

  34. 34.

    It must be said that the values with negative powers are just to classification balancing (and Alexy’s Weight Formula). To the Positivist Weight Formula, as it will be seen later on, only the values with positive powers are needed (and regarding the measurement of “certainty” one only has to substitute “gain or loss” by “certainty”).

  35. 35.

    Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 119; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 82.

  36. 36.

    Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 120; Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 83.

  37. 37.

    It has to be stressed that, with the stalemate, what is given is a choice on intensities of interference (bringing with them specific uncertainties). Thus, classification balancing does not deal directly with empirical uncertainty.

  38. 38.

    Given that there are two alternative uncertainties (because they come with the most pessimistic interference and with the most certain one), with the stalemate we will insert in variable Re of the Weight Formula one of those degrees of uncertainty (the one corresponding to the intensity chosen); then, the Weight Formula will always receive a «certain» amount of uncertainty independently from how uncertain we are about the degree of uncertainty.

  39. 39.

    Alexy (2002), pp. 415, 421.

  40. 40.

    Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 87; Rivers (2007), p. 178.

  41. 41.

    Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 88; Rivers (2007), p. 178.

  42. 42.

    This criticism already in Klatt and Schmidt (2012), p. 87.

  43. 43.

    There has been some divergence on the wording of both laws of balancing, specifically regarding the epistemic one. For instance, Julian Rivers formulates the second law as follows: “the more serious a violation of a right is, the greater must be the reliability of the legislature’s assessment that a competing interest will be realized to a sufficiently great extent” (2007, p. 183). Matthias Klatt and Johannes Schmidt put it as follows: “the more serious an interference with a principle Pi is, the more certain must be those premises that justify the classification of intensity of interference Ii” (2012, p. 85). No doubt about the importance of the wording. However, as a part of proportionality, the main point is that its core has to be intersubjectively defended from specific theories or perspectives. Thus, it is with the purpose of preserving that core that such an aseptic wording (as the one above) was conceived.

  44. 44.

    On “the more” as a quantifier, Lassiter (2009), p. 40. Also, Sauerland and Stateva (2011), p. 125.

  45. 45.

    Because it turns out that such a thing as «epistemic discretion», understood as the variation regarding what we know about one possible world at some specific time, does not exist: in a space-time point, we know what we know. What exists, instead, is the discretion related to the measurement of how much we do know (this is, the quantification of losses, gains and certainties).

  46. 46.

    Being this a coherent outcome with what has been previously said: if our knowledge is what it is, the sole possibility of discretion in the epistemic realm comes from the uncertainties about the “quantification” of that knowledge.

  47. 47.

    It is important to note that a legal order entails proportionality not only when explicitly stated in a constitution, but also when it has been produced as a customary norm (the cases of Germany or Brasil). On the topic, Barak (2012), p. 211; Bernal Pulido (2007), p. 505.

  48. 48.

    Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 71; Bernal Pulido (2007), p. 693. For a different perspective, Clerico (2018), p. 32.

  49. 49.

    On different notions of necessity, Sartor (2010), p. 198. Generally, Barak (2012), p. 326.

  50. 50.

    Of course, there are also ratios in “gains necessity” and in “losses necessity”. However, the purpose here is just to isolate the cases where there are no equal gains or equal losses (and name them as “ratio necessity”).

  51. 51.

    Sartor (2018), p. 628; Pinker (2013), p. 130; Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 79.

  52. 52.

    Similarly, Sartor (2018), p. 629.

  53. 53.

    But it seems mistaken to sustain, nonetheless, that necessity regards the R that is less intrusive in a right (Rivers 2007, p. 171). The simple situation of a collision between two rights shows this formula to be empty. See, for instance, Sieckmann (2012), p. 220; Pinker (2013), p. 30.

  54. 54.

    Because with equal ratios, the solution is undisputed: necessity never implies disproportionality.

  55. 55.

    For instance, Alexy (2010), p. 8; Petersen (2017), p. 38.

  56. 56.

    With a good example for this claim, Sartor (2010), p. 198.

  57. 57.

    Which seems to be, thus, the main reason say that necessity is the strongest test among all given by proportionality. On this test as the strongest one, Klatt and Meister (2012), p. 90; Petersen (2017), p. 100. Specifically on the problems posed by Pareto optimality in balancing, Chapman (2013), p. 267.

  58. 58.

    On this inverse realizability, Sieckmann (2018), p. 5; Alexy (2017), p. 37.

  59. 59.

    This is R2 and R3. As probably noted, R1 (inaction) has been discarded. The reason is simple: considering the threat the disease is for human life, R1 would bring into the analysis the norm (P) conferring the right to be alive. However, since such move implies abandoning the model of two Ps, it would change the matrix of the present exercise.

  60. 60.

    Then, while in necessity two Rs (or more) are compared, in proportionality in the narrow sense only one R is on the table. For this reason, in the latter the contraposition is strictly realized between principles (effective place of balancing). It is difficult to understand, therefore, the connection between balancing and necessity that is mentioned by Sieckmann (2012), p. 93, or the so called “balancing necessity” described by Sartor (2010), p. 203.

  61. 61.

    Indifference is usually represented by a convex curve bending to the left (Sieckmann 2012, p. 90; Rivers 2007, p. 174). However, this convexity signals the decreasing marginal rate of substitution (when the same degree of higher satisfaction of one P does not substitute the same degree of lower satisfaction of the other), which implies that whenever this marginal rate is constant (perfect substitutes) the curve of indifference becomes linear (Varian 2005, p. 39; Banerjee 2015, p. 42). Given that this feature (perfect or imperfect substitution) is irrelevant for the present purposes (conflicts of principles do not necessarily imply the marginal rate of substitution to decrease; it is a strict contingent effect), nothing prevents indifference to be linearly represented. On conflicts between principles with convexity, Sartor (2010), p. 193. On indifference, Steiner (1994), p. 156; Kolmar (2017), p. 150.

  62. 62.

    Evidently, we may compare as many Rs as we want with the constant of direct proportionality. The main point is that, differently from indifference, where the information given by its curve is useful for the comparison between Rs, with the constant of those laws the information given by its curve is only useful for evaluating how much one specific R is satisfying and unsatisfying the conflicting Ps.

  63. 63.

    Differently, Sieckmann (2012), p. 93; Eriksen (2006), p. 83.

  64. 64.

    Which means that, for the cases where the conflict between two Ps is (empirically) compatible with all the Rs under the inverse satisfiability of both Ps (as in [lxxiii]), the constant is on the curve of possible cumulative satisfaction of both Ps (this is, 28 [256]). Consequently, in these specific cases, a R above is impossible, a R on the curve is optimal and proportional in the narrow sense. However, below, besides non-optimal (already disapproved in the necessity test), it would never be proportional in the narrow sense.

  65. 65.

    Therefore, and differently from the previous proportionality tests, where each one is a necessary condition to the subsequent, the order of the substantive and the epistemic laws is merely a matter of convention.

  66. 66.

    Alexy (2006), p. 26. Also, Borowski (2013), p. 1416; Petersen (2017), p. 46; Brożek (2007), p. 330.

  67. 67.

    Evidently, it is not an option to change the laws of balancing in order to make them agree with the equation (as suggested by Pulido 2006, p. 105).

  68. 68.

    Which also means that the quotient of the Weight Formula is mute about the quotient of interferences between P1 and P2 and also mute about which law of balancing has been violated. This is a serious problem affecting the whole equation, coming from the fact that its internal engineering is completely based on trade-offs among variables (I, W, Re, and Rn); however, and rigorously, these internal trade-offs are exactly the opposite of what the laws of balancing are all about (on the trade-offs within the Weight Formula, Lindahl 2009, p. 361).

  69. 69.

    On the rule of the Weight Formula, Alexy (2003), p. 444.

  70. 70.

    On the controversy about W’s content, for instance, Sieckmann (2010), p. 105; Guibourg (2010), p. 156. On the ordinal consequence of the abstract weight, Moreso (2007), p. 231; Lindahl (2009), p. 366.

  71. 71.

    Meaning that it is not uncertain because of empirical uncertainties.

  72. 72.

    For the simple reason that an uncertainty about a gain (or a loss) can cause both a higher or a lower intensity of interference. It is a problem of not knowing the precise value of the interference and not a causal connection between a degree of ignorance and a lower impact an interference has in the quotient of the Weight Formula.

  73. 73.

    Consequently, the epistemic law asks for certainties about the world (empirical) in connection to a specific amount of losses, regardless of these being certain or uncertain, which has to be seen as a different problem, irrelevant for the definition of the scope of certainty.

  74. 74.

    Since there are no losses without gains (and vice-versa [even if not symmetrical]), not considering all the underlying premises would be a distortion of the overall consequences of a R. Since the rationale of the epistemic law is that we accept some losses when we have good knowledge about the world, then, given that gains are a necessary condition for losses, we cannot put apart the underlying premises of gains. How could we accept some losses if we do not take into account our degree of knowledge about the gains we are going to obtain with those losses?

  75. 75.

    Obviously, only when the measurement of gains, losses and certainties is not totally certain (this is, when there is discretion of quantification).

  76. 76.

    On the discussion about distinct intensities of review, Tushnet (2008), p. 228; Young (2010), p. 390.

  77. 77.

    Which means that the review device can serve both a normative and a descriptive functions: the former when imposing which should be the margin of self-restraint, the latter when describing which was the real margin.

References

  • Alexy R (2002) Theory of constitutional rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2003) On balancing and subsumption. A structural comparison. Ratio Juris 16(4):433–449

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2006) Discourse theory and fundamental rights. In: Menéndez A (ed) Arguing for fundamental rights. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 15–32

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2010) In: Clérico L, Sieckmann J (eds) La Construcción de los Derechos Fundamentales. Derechos Fundamentales, Princípios y Ponderación. Comares, Granada, pp 1–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2014) Formal principles: some replies to critics. Int J Const Law 12:511–524

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2016) Constitutional rights and constitutional review. In: Himma K (ed) Fundamental rights, justification and interpretation. Eleven, Den Haag, pp 63–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy R (2017) The absolute and the relative dimensions of constitutional rights. Oxford J Legal Stud 37:31–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee S (2015) Intermediate microeconomics. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Barak A (2012) Proportionality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernal Pulido C (2007) El Princípio de Proporcionalidad y los Derechos Fundamentales, 3rd edn. Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernal Pulido C (2009) El Neoconstitucionalismo y la Normatividad del Derecho. Externado, Bogotá

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird A (1998) Philosophy of science. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2010) La Sujeición a Determinaciones del Legislador en la Ponderación de Derechos Fundamentales. Cambridge. In: Clèrico L, Sieckmann J (eds) Derechos Fundamentales, Princípios y Ponderación. Comares, Granada, pp 111–145

    Google Scholar 

  • Borowski M (2013) On apples and oranges. Comment on Niels Petersen. German Law J 14:1409–1420

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brożek B (2007) The weight formula and argumentation. In: Pavlakos G (ed) Law, rights and discourse. Hart Publishing, Oxford, pp 319–330

    Google Scholar 

  • Bulygin E (2010) Sobre la Equivalencia Pragmática entre Permiso y No Prohibición. Doxa 33:283–296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chapman B (2013) Incommensurability, proportionality, and defeasibility. Law Probability Risk 12:259–274

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni P (2019) La Balanza Inexistente. Analisi e Diritto 2:165–231

    Google Scholar 

  • Clérico L (2009) El Examen de Proporcionalidad em el Derecho Constitucional. Eudeba, Buenos Aires

    Google Scholar 

  • Clérico L (2018) Proportionality in social rights adjudication: making it workable. In: Duarte D (ed) Proportionality in law. Springer, Cham, pp 49–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Duarte D (2015) Analogy and Balancing: The Partial Reducibility Thesis and its Problems. Revus 25:1–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Duarte D (2018) Norms on Language and the Regulativeness of Constitutive Norms. Diritto Questione Publiche XVIII(1):135–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Eriksen E (2006) Democratic or Jurist-Made law? In: Menéndez A (ed) Arguing for fundamental rights. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 69–100

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Escher A (2019) When it is vague what is vague: identifying vagueness. In: Duarte D (ed) Legal interpretation and scientific knowledge. Springer, Cham, pp 161–186

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Golding M (2018) Argument by analogy in the law. In: Kaptein H (ed) Analogy and exemplary reasoning in legal discourse. Amsterdam University Press, Amsterdam, pp 123–136

    Google Scholar 

  • Guibourg R (2010) On Alexy’s weighing formula. In: Sieckmann J (ed) Legal reasoning: the methods of balancing. Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart, pp 145–160

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson S (2013) The varieties of permission. In: Gabbay D (ed) Handbook of deontic logic and normative systems. College Publications, Milton Keynes, pp 195–240

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart H (2013) Discretion. Harv Law Rev 127:652–665

    Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M (2007) Taking rights less seriously: a structural analysis of judicial discretion. Ratio Juris 20:506–529

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M, Meister M (2012) The constitutional structure of proportionality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klatt M, Schmidt J (2012) Epistemic discretion in constitutional law. Int J Const Law 10:69–105

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolmar M (2017) Principles of microeconomics. Springer, Cham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lassiter D (2009) The Algebraic Structure of Amounts: Evidence from Comparatives. In: Proceedings of the 14th Student Session of ESSLLI. ESSLLI, Bordeaux, pp 51–61

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindahl L (2009) On Robert Alexy’s weight formula for weighing and balancing. Liber Amicorum de José de Sousa Brito. Almedina, Coimbra, pp 355–376

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton P (1991) Inference to the best explanation, 2nd edn. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendonca D (2000) Las Claves del Derecho. Gedisa, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreso JJ (2002) Conflitti tra Princìpi Costituzionali. Diritto & Questioni Pubbliche 2:19–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreso JJ (2007) Alexy y la Aritmética de la Ponderación. In: Garcia Manrique R (ed) Derechos Sociales y Ponderación. Fundación Coloquio Jurídico Europeu, Madrid, pp 223–247

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreso JJ (2017) Marry me a little. How much precision is enough in law? Droit & Philosophie 9:45–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreso JJ, Vilajosana JM (2004) Introducción a la Teoría del Derecho. Marcial Pons, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Navarro P, Rodríguez J (2014) Deontic logic and legal systems. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto I (2004) In: Niiniluoto I (ed) Induction. Handbook of epistemology. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 521–548

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nino CS (2003) Introducción al Análisis del Derecho, 11th edn. Ariel, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Olsson E (2007) Reliabilism, stability, and the value of knowledge. Am Philos Q 44(4):343–355

    Google Scholar 

  • Petersen N (2017) Proportionality and judicial activism. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker B (2013) Proportionality analysis and models of judicial review. Europa Law Publishing, Groningen

    Google Scholar 

  • Pino G (2014) Proporzionalità, Diritti, Democrazia. Diritto e Società 3:597–628

    Google Scholar 

  • Pulido B (2006) On Alexy’s weight formula. In: Menéndez A (ed) Arguing for fundamental rights. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 101–110

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ratti GB (2018) Tres Addenda a Sistemas Normativos. Doxa 41:85–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rivers J (2007) Proportionality, discretion and the second law of balancing. In: Pavlakos G (ed) Law, rights and discourse. Hart Publishing, Oxford, pp 167–188

    Google Scholar 

  • Sardo A (2018) Let’s talk about antinomies. Normative systems reloaded. Revus 36:53–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartor G (2010) Doing justice to rights and values: teleological reasoning and proportionality. Artificial Intelligence Law 18:175–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartor G (2013) The logic of proportionality: reasoning with non-numerical magnitudes. German Law J 14:1419–1456

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartor G (2018) A quantitative approach to proportionality. In: Bongiovanni G, Postema G et al (eds) Handbook of legal reasoning and argumentation. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 613–635

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland U, Stateva P (2011) Two types of vagueness. In: Égré P, Klinedinst N (eds) Vagueness and language use. Palgrave MacMillan, London, pp 121–145

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shope R (2004) The analysis of knowing. In: Niiniluoto I (ed) Handbook of epistemology. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 283–330

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J (2010) Balancing, optimisation, and Alexy’s “Weight Formula”. In: Sieckmann J (ed) Legal reasoning: the methods of balancing. Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart, pp 101–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J (2012) The logic of autonomy. Hart Publishing, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieckmann J (2018) Proportionality as an universal human rights principle. In: Duarte D (ed) Proportionality in law. Springer, Cham, pp 3–24

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner H (1994) An essay on rights. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tushnet M (2008) Weak courts, strong rights. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Varian H (2005) Intermediate microeconomics, 7th edn. W. W. North & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker V et al (2015) Representing the logic of statutory rules in the United States. In: Araszkiewicz M (ed) Logic in the theory and practice of lawmaking. Springer, Cham, pp 357–381

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wróblewski J (1992) The judicial application of law. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young K (2010) A tipology of economic and social rights adjudication: exploring the catalytic function of judicial review. Int J Const Law 8:385–420

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Duarte .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Duarte, D. (2021). From Constitutional Discretion to the Positivist Weight Formula. In: Sieckmann, JR. (eds) Proportionality, Balancing, and Rights . Law and Philosophy Library, vol 136. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-77321-2_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-77321-2_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-77320-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-77321-2

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics